REVIEW. Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988.

Similar documents
Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Lecture 38 CARTESIAN THEORY OF MIND REVISITED Overview. Key words: Cartesian Mind, Thought, Understanding, Computationality, and Noncomputationality.

Realism and instrumentalism

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

To Appear in Philosophical Studies symposium of Hartry Field s Truth and the Absence of Fact

THE NATURE OF MIND Oxford University Press. Table of Contents

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Language, reference and representation

Natural Kinds: (Thick) Essentialism or Promiscuous Realism?

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Disarming the externalist threat to self-knowledge

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Lecture 9. A summary of scientific methods Realism and Anti-realism

Lecture 6. Realism and Anti-realism Kuhn s Philosophy of Science

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Classical Theory of Concepts

Multiple realizability and functionalism

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Putnam, Koethe, and Metaphysical Realism

Intersubjective belief * Vivienne Brown. Open University, UK. forthcoming Episteme

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Nature and its Classification

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

1/9. The First Analogy

Methodological Solipsism Reconsidered: Is There Anybody Out There?

Relativism. We re both right.

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Overview. Is there a priori knowledge? No: Mill, Quine. Is there synthetic a priori knowledge? Yes: faculty of a priori intuition (Rationalism, Kant)

Is Content Holism Incoherent? 1. Kirk A. Ludwig Department of Philosophy University of Florida Gainesville, FL

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

1999 Thomas W. Polger KRIPKE AND THE ILLUSION OF CONTINGENT IDENTITY. Thomas W. Polger. Department of Philosophy, Duke University.

TRUTH IN MATHEMATICS. H.G. Dales and G. Oliveri (eds.) (Clarendon: Oxford. 1998, pp. xv, 376, ISBN X) Reviewed by Mark Colyvan

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Naming Natural Kinds. Åsa Maria Wikforss Stockholm University Department of Philosophy Stockholm

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

ON QUINE, ANALYTICITY, AND MEANING Wylie Breckenridge

Van Fraassen: Arguments concerning scientific realism

Philosophy of Mathematics Nominalism

Indeed, the main significance of this book is that it shows implicitly, but very clearly quite how much of Putnam s contribution to his philosophy is

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Philosophical Review.

Wittgenstein and Gödel: An Attempt to Make Wittgenstein s Objection Reasonable

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

To be able to define human nature and psychological egoism. To explain how our views of human nature influence our relationships with other

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Kant and his Successors

Philosophy 125 Day 4: Overview

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Putnam on Methods of Inquiry

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

The Indeterminacy of Translation: Fifty Years Later

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

1. Introduction. 2. Clearing Up Some Confusions About the Philosophy of Mathematics

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Belief States and Narrow Content

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

The personal/subpersonal distinction Zoe Drayson To appear in Philosophy Compass. Abstract

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Informalizing Formal Logic

Comments on Saul Kripke s Philosophical Troubles

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

Transcription:

REVIEW Hilary Putnam, Representation and Reality. Cambridge, Nass.: NIT Press, 1988. In his new book, 'Representation and Reality', Hilary Putnam argues against the view that intentional idioms (with as paradigms the propositional attitudes) can be the subject of a reductionistic scientific approach. Although the book contains some arguments against scienticism in general, and a chapter against eliminativism, the core of the book is directed against functionalism, especially forms of functionalism that try to reduce intenti.onal idioms to computational predicates or relations. Putnam's case rests upon two main lines of argument. The first of these departs from the Quinian issues of meaning holism and the indeterminacy of translation/interpretation. The second elaborates Putnam's own viewpoint that 'meanings aren't in the head'. Preliminarily, Putnam argues that for a real reduction of intentional idioms and relations, the computational state or relation these idioms are reduced to must be nomologically related. This means that every physically possible physical organism which instantiates the intentional predicate must also instantiate the computational predicate. Moreover, Putnam demands that the reducing predicate be definable in finitely many words, which means that the computational predicate cannot be an infinite disju nc tion. Putnam takes meaning holism to imply a) that different individuals can be in the same intentional state (e.g, share the same belief or give the same meaning to the same word) while being in a different functional/computational state and b} that we, in order to notice that they are in the same intentional state, make use of our -hardly to formalize- intuitive standards of rationality. Meaning holism says that in order to ascribe meanings to some subject's words or propositions, one has to interpret his discourse as a whole. But this interpretation is indeterminate: one can invent different 'translation manuals' that do the same job differently (translation manual B can ascribe a different content to S's utterance U than translation manual A by revising some of the beliefs that A supposed S to entertain). Translation manuals can, however, differ in reasonableness: we intuitively feel some translation manuals to do the job better. The same aspect of reasonableness occurs in our decisions on synonimity. In order to decide wether people are giving the same meaning to a word

188 REVIEW or are sharing the same belief, we interpret their discourses by obeying a 'principle of charity'. What charity amounts to is that we tend to construe our interpretations of someone's discourse such that this someone's beliefs are as similar to ours as possible. We are likely to prefer 'interpretation manuals' which preserve beliefs and meanings over -by Quine's indeterminacy thesis- equally possible 'interpretation manuals' which do not. This accounts for the fact that we (or Putnam) don't want to say that the meaning of the term 'electron' in Bohr's 1900 theory differs from the meaning of the same term in his 1934 theory, despite there being lots of differences in the beliefs associated with the term in the two theories (Putnam sometimes suggests that if we would count the two occurrences of 'electron' as differing in meaning, this would imply that they were incommensurable. If they were, Putnam contends, Bohr's early theory would be' completely unintelligible for us. We couldn't even talk about it reasonably. I think Putnam here too easily shifts from 'different in meaning' to 'incommensurable', in the sense of 'making understanding or communication impossible'). Charity however, is constrained by the demand that our interpretation be reasonable: beliefs do not have to be preserved at any cost (e.g. by ascribing the subject we interpret inconsistent or very strange beliefs). We do not translate 'phlogiston' as 'radiant energy', for example. The difference between the electron and the phlogiston cases is, according to Putnam, a difference we intuitively feel by appealing to our little understood 'general intelligence'. A functionalist who agrees with Putnam that the arguments just given indeed show that two people (or intelligent beings) can be in the same intentional state without being in the same computational state, could still reply, in Putnam's mind, that there nevertheless could exist a computational 'equivalence relation' between their respective states. There could exist an algorithm that, given two beliefs and an arbitrary amount of information about the people who have them, could decide on their carrying the same content. A first problem with this claim is that it demands that our general intelligence, our present intuitive judgments of reasonableness be formalized. Moreover, Putnam argues, such an algorithm, in order to discriminate all future (or worse, all physically possible) cases of belief sharing beings, would have to foresee all future (or worse, all physically possible) modes of discourse and standards of rationality, because to be able to decide whether two believers have a belief in common, one has to understand and interpret their discourses. In order to conceive

REVIEW 189 of such a relation, we should be able to cqnceive all future or possible modes of discourse and standards of rationality. But this is surely too immense a task for a human being. This implies that, even if there objectively would exist such an algorithm, no one could recognize it. Putnam who takes this impossibility of 'rationalizing' rationality in toto to be analogous to Godel's incompleteness theorem. If all of this is right, functionalists are not able to reduce (in a proper sense of 'reduce') intentional states to non-disjunctive, finitely defined computational states. Putnam thinks that if functionalism cannot but allow disjunctions as its predicates, the functional organizations it will propose to be models of the mind, will be realized by every physical system. In an Appendix, he construes a proof of the following theorem: 'Every ordinary open system is a realization of every abstract finite automaton'. The basic idea (roughly sketched) is that given a succession of functional (more precisely automaton-) states, say ABAB, and a physical system that is in physical states a, b,c,d, one can always define a correspondence, by identifying disjunctions of physical states with the functional states (a v c with A and b v d with B). Once this correspondence is established, the arbitrary physical system is an instantiation of the functional model. I think this argument poses a real threat to many functionalists. For their main theoretical construct is,precisely the propositional attitude (or its image in 'the language of thought'). Given this prominent role, one should require functionalists to provide type- identifying criteria for propositional attitudes. Putnam's argument however, points out that they will fail to do so (if they restrict themselves to functional/computational language to state the criteria in). The second line of argument goes back to Putnam's earlier writings, especially 'The Meaning of Meaning'(Putnam, 1975}. It tells that computationalism, by its commitment to methodological solipsism, must be wrong since meanings are not in individuals' heads: they are constituted partly by society and partly by the environment. Putnam illustrates the fact that the environment contributes in determining the meaning of terms with his famous twin-earth example. One is demanded to imagine a planet which is exactly the same as ours (which implies that it contains replica of the people living on earth at the same time), except for the fact that the water there, though apparently the same as our H20, is in fact a different substance, XYZ. Putnam claims that, even before people or their twin earth replica discovered the chemical con-

190 REVIEW stitution of their 'water', the term had a different reference, and thus a different meaning, on both planets. 'This he explains by invoking that natural kind terms alway~ contain an element of indexicality, i.e. 'water' is defined by 'focusing' on a sample in one's environment, to which all instantiations must bear a similarity-relation (namely that they have the same structure and behavior as that substance). Society plays a role in determining meaning because of a 'division of linguistic labour'. This has to do with the fact many people rely on experts to pick out the referents of common natural kind terms, such as 'gold', which implies that it is not 'what is in those people's head' that determines the reference of the terms. To say that the meanings are individuated the head of the expert would also be mistaken, for different experts might use different theories or tests in order to discriminate real from apparent referents. Which expert's understanding would constitute 'the' meaning of the term? The reasonable thing to do, according to Putnam, is to give up trying to individuate meanings. An obvious, but powerful objection to Putnam's twin-earth argument is to state that Putnam's views commit him to the opinion that we didn't know the meaning of 'water' before we knew modern chemistry, and in general, that we will never know the meanings of our common words before the ultimate scientific truth about their referents is revealed (cf. Fodor(1980)). Putnam replies that this objection exploits an ambiguity in the meaning 'of 'knowing the meaning of'. 'Knowing the meaning of' can, according to Putnam, mean a)knowing how to translate, b) knowing the reference of and c) being able to use the word in discourse. In sense c), Putnam argues, we have always known the meaning of 'water'. What is dubious about this answer, is that Putnam's main point in the H20/XYZ example hinges on separating meaning and use (despite our and twin earthlings' identical use of the term water in e.g. the year 1200, it had a different meaning on each planet even then), while his countering of the mentioned objection consists in identifying meaning and use! Besides these main lines of argument against computationalist functionalism, 'Representation an Reality' contains treatments of more specific versions of functionalism proposed by Jerry Fodor, Ned Block and David Lewis. It also has a chapter arguing against philosophers who want to eliminate intentional idioms. Putnam's position is that these philosophers would have to give up the notion of truth too, which he takes as a reductio of their position. The last chapter contains some sketchy remarks on

REVIEW 191 Putnam's (not yet fully developed) alternative to functionalism, or reductionism or scientific realism in general, his 'internal realism" The body of the book however, is constituted by the arguments against functionalism. I believe that (especially the line of argument first sketched) poses real challenges to the position attacked. I venture that even if this book had not been written by Putnam, it would have been welcomed as a major contribution. REFERENCES Fodor,(1980), "Methodological Solipsism Considered as a Research Strategy in Cognitive Psychology", The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, Vol. 3. Putnam(1975), "The Meaning of 'Meaning"',in Gunderson, ed., Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 7 (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press). Erik Myin Research Associate NFSR Vrije Universiteit Brussel