Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez

Similar documents
Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

From Meaning is Use to the Rejection of Transcendent Truth

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

How Not to Defend Metaphysical Realism (Southwestern Philosophical Review, Vol , 19-27)

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Notre Dame Law Review

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

What the History of Science Cannot Teach Us Ioannis Votsis University of Bristol

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

Module 1: Science as Culture Demarcation, Autonomy and Cognitive Authority of Science

what makes reasons sufficient?

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 11

Ontological Justification: From Appearance to Reality Anna-Sofia Maurin (PhD 2002)

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Can Excellence Be Taught?

NORTON ANTHOLOGY OF WESTERN PHILOSOPHY: AFTER KANT TABLE OF CONTENTS. Volume 2: The Analytic Tradition. Preface Acknowledgments GENERAL INTRODUCTION

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN 1. AGAINST ANALYTIC METAPHYSICS

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

145 Philosophy of Science

Philosophical Underpinnings of the First Amendment

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Relativism. We re both right.

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

Aalborg Universitet. A normative sociocultural psychology? Brinkmann, Svend. Publication date: 2009

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2013 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

HPS 1653 / PHIL 1610 Revision Guide (all topics)

Realism and the success of science argument. Leplin:

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

Demarcation of Science

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Justification as a Social Activity

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

ETHICS (IE MODULE) 1. COURSE DESCRIPTION

There is no need to explain who Hilary Putnam is in light of the sheer number of books and articles on his work that have appeared over the past

Epistemology and sensation

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber

1. The basic idea is to look at "what the courts do in fact" (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean?

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Language

Realism and Idealism Internal realism

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

FINAL EXAM REVIEW SHEET. objectivity intersubjectivity ways the peer review system is supposed to improve objectivity

Business Research: Principles and Processes MGMT6791 Workshop 1A: The Nature of Research & Scientific Method

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FALL 2014 COURSE DESCRIPTIONS

Philosophy Courses-1

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

A DILEMMA FOR JAMES S JUSTIFICATION OF FAITH SCOTT F. AIKIN

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Could i conceive being a brain in a vat? John D. Collier a a

MARK KAPLAN AND LAWRENCE SKLAR. Received 2 February, 1976) Surely an aim of science is the discovery of the truth. Truth may not be the

NATURALISED JURISPRUDENCE

Naturalism and is Opponents

Paper #1: Maria tegui & The Problem of the Indian

Development of Soul Through Contemplation and Action Seen from the Viewpoint of lslamic Philosophers and Gnostics

A Christian Philosophy of Education

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

Philosophy Courses-1

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

On Anti-Philosophy. Kai Nielsen. Ludwig Wittgenstein s anti-philosophy philosophy still seems to leave us with some

Other Recommended Books (on reserve at library):

METHODENSTREIT WHY CARL MENGER WAS, AND IS, RIGHT

MODELS CLARIFIED: RESPONDING TO LANGDON GILKEY. by David E. Klemm and William H. Klink

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Phenomenology, Empiricism, and Science

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Two Approaches to Natural Law;Note

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 100, No. 3. (Jul., 1991), pp

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

What is Justification?

Kazuhisa Todayama (Graduate School of Information Science, Nagoya University, Japan)

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Epistemic Responsibility in Science

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Transcription:

Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Digital Commons at Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Law Reviews 1-1-1996 Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez Dennis Patterson Recommended Citation Dennis Patterson, Law as a Social Fact: A Reply to Professor Martinez, 29 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 579 (1996). Available at: https://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/llr/vol29/iss2/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews at Digital Commons @ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons@Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. For more information, please contact digitalcommons@lmu.edu.

LAW AS A SOCIAL FACT: A REPLY TO PROFESSOR MARTINEZ Dennis Patterson* Philosophy's struggle with the concept of truth has been both protracted and vigorous. Since Plato, one picture of truth-perhaps the dominant view-has been that truth is a matter of verisimilitude or convergence of one thing and another. In modernity, truth has attained its most capacious development in the context of scientific inquiry. Before Fleck, Kuhn, and Feyerabend, no philosopher had mounted a serious attack on the idea that scientific truth is a matter of convergence between a proposition and some state of affairs in virtue of which the asserted proposition is made true-realism. Since the early days of scientific empiricism, the humanistic disciplines have struggled in the shadow of the natural sciences. One need only recall the protracted efforts of Freudian psychoanalysts to claim scientific status for their speculations in order to appreciate the pervasive hold of the scientific aspiration. The theoretical struggles between scientists and humanists take many forms. One persistent debate has been over the nature of the object of study for each. On the one hand, there are those who, like myself, believe that the object of the natural sciences is of a fundamentally different order than that of art criticism or literature. George Steiner notes well the distinction between the scientific and nonscientific disciplines with the observation that in the nonscientific disciplines, "theories" 1 are never falsified, they just fend off the competition. Consider Aristotle's theory of -rhetoric. It cannot be said to be a "theory" in the sense that, say, Copernicus's account of planetary * Distinguished Professor of Law, Rutgers University School of Law (Camden). 1. See GEORGE STEINER, REAL PRESENCES 72-77 (1989). Two indispensable criteria must be satisfied by theory: verifiability or falsifiability by means of experiment and predictive application. There are in art and poetics no crucial experiments, no litmus-paper tests. There can be no verifiable or falsifiable deductions entailing predictable consequences in the very concrete sense in which a scientific theory carries predictive force. I& at 75.

580 LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW [Vol. 29:579 motion is a theory. The essential difference between the two is that scientific theories can be tested in the realm of experiment and their hypotheses confirmed or not. There is no analog in Aristotle's account of rhetoric to the scientific hypothesis. Nothing can show Aristotle's theory of rhetoric to be "false." No evidence can be marshalled "for" or "against" it. The propositions of Aristotle's rhetoric are not apt for confirmation in the ways of science. Against this background, some philosophers have wanted to say that nonscientific propositions cannot have truth values. 2 Because scientific propositions assert facts, their truth or falsity depends on states of affairs in which the asserted propositions are true or false. Because there are no nonscientific "facts," no nonscientific proposition can be either true or false. Hence, truth is a concept inappropriate to the nonscientific realm. This brings us to Professor Martinez's interesting commentary on recent work in legal theory, including my own, regarding the nature of truth. 3 The specific philosophical question which I consider is what it means to say that a proposition of law is true. First articulated by Ronald Dworkin, 4 this question asks us what we mean when we say that a claim about the current state of the law is correct or incorrect, accurate or inaccurate, true or false. Of course, this question is one of general philosophical'interest, for it always makes sense to ask what it means to say that someone is doing something correctly or not in any field of endeavor, as in painting, finance, or politics. Professor Martinez's article is a critical piece: He finds fault with my account of the nature of truth in law. 5 Professor Martinez correctly states that my work is informed by the approach to the philosophy taken by Wittgenstein after 1929.6 Having made the genetic identification, Professor Martinez proceeds to raise questions about this approach to jurisprudence by adverting to questions raised by philosophers about the genetic prototype, Wittgenstein's work. In 2. See ALFRED JULES AYER, LANGUAGE, TRUTH AND LOGIC (2d ed. 1946). 3. George A. Martinez, The New Wittgensteinians and the End of Jurisprudence, 29 LoY. L.A. L. REV. 545 (1996). 4. Introduction to THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 1, 5-9 (R.M. Dworkin ed., 1977) (discussing the idea of "truth" with respect to legal propositions). 5. Martinez, supra note 3, at 572. 6. See generally LUDWIG WITrGENSTEIN, PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS (G.E.M. Anscombe trans., 3d ed. 1968) (containing a collection of philosophical concepts Wittgenstein observed over a period of 16 years).

January 1996] LAW ASA SOCIAL FACT short, Professor Martinez wants to carry over to jurisprudence general criticisms of the work of Wittgenstein. I do not think this a very fruitful way to critique a jurisprudence. General philosophical objections rarely have a direct and discernible impact on jurisprudential issues. For example, none of the objections raised by Professor Robert Fogelin7,to Wittgenstein's later philosophy has any direct bearing on issues in legal theory. For these criticisms to have an impact, one must show how they solve a given problem or answer some question. I do not see Professor Martinez forging the necessary connections. However, Professor Martinez has some quite specific criticisms of my approach to the question of truth in law. It is to these that I wish to respond. The first of these criticisms concerns the development of what, following Alasdair MacIntyre, 8 Professor Martinez characterizes as "new conceptual schemes."' The gravamen of Professor Martinez's argument is that jurisprudence must not limit itself to the description of our existing justificatory practices, for those very practices have the effect of marginalizing certain groups and oppressing their members. In short, it is the task of jurisprudence to "develop perspectives of the oppressed to infiltrate dominant legal institution[s]. 10 Well, alright. Who could be against liberation of the oppressed? There is nothing in my work, 1 nor the work of any other "New Wittgensteinian," which argues against liberation of the oppressed. It is a mistake to see the Wittgensteinian perspective as somehow at odds with emancipatory projects. In fact, it is perfectly consistent to be a philosophical Wittgensteinian and a political radical. Indeed, it probably helps to have a Wittgensteinian perspective on the jurisprudential issues, because in order to show that one is truly engaged in the work of liberation, one first has to give an account of what from which one is liberated. A jurisprudence which can identify the true state of the law appears to be just the sort of thing one might wish to have. 7. See ROBERT J. FOGELIN, WITrOENSTEIN (Ted Honderich ed., 2d ed. 1987) (cited by Martinez, supra note 3, at 548). 8. See ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, WHOSE JUSTICE? WHICH RATIONALITY? (1988). 9. Martinez, supra note 3, at 567. 10. IL at 570. 11. In fact, I argue that feminism can be reconstructive and critical, even from a postmodern point of view on truth. Dennis Patterson, Postmodernism/Feminisr/Law, 77 CORNELL L. REv. 254,256-58 (1992).

582 LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW (Vol. 29:579 We now come to the area of greatest disagreement, that of truth. In the section of his essay devoted to "Truth," Professor Martinez quotes me for the proposition that "a proposition of law is true if one can show that one is correctly using the words in question."' 2 He further states that, in my view, "there is nothing more to be said about the truth of a proposition of law than advancing the reasons for its assertion."' 3 From these quotations, Professor Martinez draws the conclusion that for me, truth equals justification. 4 It is the identification of truth with justification that Professor Martinez contests. The relationship of truth to justification is a complicated affair. In traditional terms, truth is a metaphysical relationship and justification an epistemic one. For example, I may be justified-in other words, have good reasons-in believing that my child is at school, although that belief is false, because, for example, she has skipped classes to be with her friends. Justification of belief is a matter of evidence. Truth is a matter of what is the case. Because I do not employ the concept of justification in the epistemic sense just described, I do not believe Professor Martinez's critique undermines any aspect of my position. I hold that the truth of a proposition of law is shown by the use of forms of argument. Forms of argument are the culturally-endorsed modes of appraisal for propositions of law. True, I labeled "justification" the activity of showing the truth of a proposition of law, but nothing in my work suggests that believing-an epistemic state-a proposition of law to be true makes it so. Saying something true requires that, on any given occasion, the speaker uses the words in question in appropriate ways. 5 12. Martinez, supra note 3, at 572 (citing Dennis Patterson, Conscience and the Constitution, 93 COLUM. L. REv. 270,289 (1993) (reviewing PHILIP BOBBITr, CONSTITU- TIONAL INTERPRETATION (1991))). 13. Id. (quoting Dennis Patterson, The Poverty of Interpretive Universalism: Toward the Reconstruction of Legal Theory, 72 TEX. L. REV. 1, 56 (1993)). 14. Ld. 15. This view is expressed by Hilary Putnam, thus: The suggestion I am making, in short, is that a statement is true of a situation just in case it would be correct to use the words of which the statement consists in that way in describing the situation... [W]e can explain what "correct to use the words of which the statement consists in that way" means by saying that it means nothing more nor less than a sufficiently well placed speaker who used the words in that way would be fully warranted in counting the statement as true of that situation. HILARY PUTNAM, REPRESENTATION AND REALITY 115 (1988).

January 1996] LAW AS A SOCIAL FACT Having distinguished between epistemic and metaphysical senses of justification, and having shown that the sense of justification relevant for the present discussion is not epistemic but metaphysical, let me now address the metaphysics of legal justification. This returns us to a theme broached earlier, that of the distinction between the natural and the social. There are two types of facts: natural and social. Natural facts concern the realm of nature, and are the province of the physical sciences. Scientific activity seeks understanding of the naturalistic realm through the twin processes of observation and experiment. Because law is not a natural fact, observation and experiment have no role in discerning the state of the law at any given time. Legal facts are institutional in nature. 6 Owing to the institutional nature of legal affairs, understanding law means understanding the social practices we identify as legal. Without social practices, there would be no law. The same is true for all other cultural products, such as money, art, or beauty.1 7 Professor Martinez takes issue with my account of the nature of law by contrasting it with a certain picture of the development of law. He states: The justification conditions for sentences change as our total body of knowledge changes. Thus, not only may we discover that statements we now regard as justified are false, but we may even discover that procedures we now regard as justificatory are not, and that different justification procedures are better.' 8 For the reasons given, I think this view of the nature of law is false. Legal facts-what is the case as a matter of law-are not "discovered." Cures for diseases are discovered through the intervention of the creative scientist. But there are no contracts in the world in the same way there is cancer. The fact that there is cancer in the world depends not at all on us. By contrast, there would be no contracts in the world without the social practice we identify as contract law. 16. For a development of this claim in the context of commercial law, see Dennis M. Patterson, Wittgenstein and the Code: A Theory of Good Faith Performance and Enforcement Under Article Nine, 137 U. PA. L. REv. 335 (1988). 17. See JOHN R. SEARLE, THE CONSTRUCrION OF SOCIAL REALITY (1995) (providing a recent treatment of this topic). 18. Martinez, supra note 3, at 572 (citing PUTNAM, supra note 14, at 85).

584 LOYOLA OF LOS ANGELES LAW REVIEW [Vol. 29:579 Nothing in this account of the nature of law undermines the possibility of legal facts or the objectivity of law. Rather, it seeks to show that the nature of law is of an order fundamentally different from that of the physical world. For that reason, any account of it must itself be of a different order. It is always difficult in the space of a short reply to be as complete as one might like in responding to criticism. I believe that one obstacle to fruitful debate over the issues that divide Professor Martinez and myself is the lack of a clear consensus as to what the disagreement is about. In my theoretical work, 9 I have pressed the case against a certain conception of truth in law, one imported from the natural sciences. I believe Professor Martinez relies on this conception in criticizing my position. I hope I have shown why this criticism misses its intended target. 19. A complete statement of my views is found in my forthcoming book Law and Truth (Oxford University Press, 1996).