Kierkegaard and Nietzsche: the Last Philosophers

Similar documents
The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

EXISTENTIAL PHILOSOPHY

EXISTENTIALISM. Wednesday, April 20, 16

Existentialism. And the Absurd

PHILOSOPHY 211 Introduction to Existentialism

Going beyond good and evil

PHILOSOPHY 211 Introduction to Existentialism

Understanding the burning question of the 1940s and beyond

VOL. 2 ISSUE 10 JULY 2016 ISSN An International, Peer-Reviewed, Open Access, Monthly, Online Journal of English Language and Literature

KINGSBOROUGH COMMUNITY COLLEGE of The City University of New York. Common COURSE SYLLABUS

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Existentialism Willem A. devries

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

VOL. 1 ISSUE 12 MAY 2015 ISSN An International, Peer-Reviewed, Open Access, Monthly, Online Journal of English Language and Literature

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

1. Short (1 2pp.) reflection papers * due at the beginning of each class

I. THE PHILOSOPHY OF DIALOGUE A. Philosophy in General

Chapter 11. Conclusion. appreciate certain aspects of his music, but inevitably his enormous literary and

Book Review: Badiou, A. (2007). The Century, Oxford, UK: Polity Press.

Violence as a philosophical theme

Definition: The denial of the possibility of knowledge, philosophy, and value in anything.

Applying Early Existential Critiques to Contemporary Themes in American Culture

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1

A Multitude of Selves: Contrasting the Cartesian and Nietzschean views of selfhood

The Human Deficit according to Immanuel Kant: The Gap between the Moral Law and Human Inability to Live by It. Pieter Vos 1

Journal Of Contemporary Trends In Business And Information Technology (JCTBIT) Vol.5, pp.1-6, December Existentialist s Model of Professionalism

Introduction to Kierkegaard and Existentialism

Undergraduate Calendar Content

Fear and Trembling: The knight of faith and movement. (Lecture 3 accompanying notes for reading of the Preamble from the heart )

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Philosophy Catalog. REQUIREMENTS FOR A MAJOR IN PHILOSOPHY: 9 courses (36 credits)

VOL. 1 ISSUE 5 OCTOBER 2014 ISSN An International, Peer-Reviewed, Open Access, Monthly, Online Journal of English Language and Literature

The Paradox of Democracy

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

JESUS IN YOU AND LOVING Patterning After the Healthy Christ Part 5 Dr. George O. Wood

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Nietzsche s Philosophy as Background to an Examination of Tolkien s The Lord of the Rings

11/6/2016 An Antidote to the Age of Anxiety: Alan Watts on Happiness and How to Live with Presence Brain Pickings

Philosophy of Ethics Philosophy of Aesthetics. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. A. Research Background. being as opposed to society as a one organism (Macquarrie, 1973). Existentialism mainly finds

Investigating the concept of despair and its relation with sin in Kierkegaard's view

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

A Major Matter: Minoring in Philosophy. Southeastern Louisiana University. The unexamined life is not worth living. Socrates, B.C.E.

ACIM Edmonton - Sarah's Reflections

Phil 311: Phenomenology and Existentialism Fall 2007 Syllabus

What Is Existentialism? COPYRIGHTED MATERIAL. Chapter 1. In This Chapter

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

1200 Academy St. Kalamazoo, MI 49006

Robot como esclavos modernos

James. Participants Guide. Do not merely listen to the word, and so deceive yourselves. Do what it says. James 1:22

PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY

Søren Abaye Kierkegaard ( )

Rules for Decision (Text Chapter 30 Section I) Excerpts from the Workshop held at the Foundation for A Course in Miracles Temecula CA

Meursault s Ethical Transcendence : A Žižekian Reading of The Stranger. What does it mean to be displaced, separated from the ever-present sense of

Aristotle s Doctrine of the Mean and the Circularity of Human Nature

Romans Chapter One - Page 1

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

The Search for Meaning PHIL 180 University Studies Program. Course Outline

Course Text. Course Description. Course Objectives. StraighterLine Introduction to Philosophy

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (CRN 12245) Fall 2013

Philosophy. Aim of the subject

Follow links for Class Use and other Permissions. For more information send to:

FREEDOM AND THE SOURCE OF VALUE: KORSGAARD AND WOOD ON KANT S FORMULA OF HUMANITY CHRISTOPHER ARROYO

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Existentialism Philosophy 303 (12070) Fall 2011 TR 9:30-10:45 Kinard 312

Doctrine of God. Immanuel Kant s Moral Argument

THE PROBLEM OF GOD Study Guide Questions

NOTE: Courses, rooms, times and instructors are subject to change; please see Timetable of Classes on HokieSpa for current information

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

Anthropology. Theology 2 Moody Bible Institute Spring 2003

Kierkegaard As Incomplete Ironist

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Shannon Nason Curriculum Vitae

From Levinas radio interview, The Face

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

PHILOSOPHY. Written examination. Monday 18 November 2002

THEMES: PROMPT: RESPONSE:

Legitimacy: Man's Search for Meaning

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. P. F. Strawson: On Referring

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Existentialism. Course number PHIL 291 section A1 Fall 2014 Tu-Th 9:30-10:50am ED 377

How to Live a More Authentic Life in Both Markets and Morals

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Phenomenology Religion in the I and Thou of Martine Buber

RUNNING HEAD: Philosophy and Theology 1. Christine Orsini RELS 111 Professor Fletcher March 21, 2012 Short Writing Assignment 2

ACIM Edmonton - Sarah's Reflections. LESSON 135 If I defend myself, I am attacked.

Becoming More Authentic: The Positive Side of Existentialism

Differences between Psychosynthesis and Jungian Psychology 2017 by Catherine Ann Lombard. Conceptual differences

Who do you say Jesus is? Your response to Him will determine not only your values and lifestyle, but your eternal destiny as well.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

ELEONORE STUMP PENELHUM ON SKEPTICS AND FIDEISTS

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

Understanding Jesus in the Context of Evolution. I have come that they may have life, and have it to the full (John 10:10)

Today s Lecture. Preliminary comments on the Problem of Evil J.L Mackie

TABLE OF CONTENTS. A. "The Way The World Really Is" 46 B. The First Philosophers: The "Turning Point of Civilization" 47

Transcription:

Lake Forest College Lake Forest College Publications All-College Writing Contest 5-1-1989 Kierkegaard and Nietzsche: the Last Philosophers Peter Seigh Lake Forest College Follow this and additional works at: https://publications.lakeforest.edu/allcollege_writing_contest Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Seigh, Peter, "Kierkegaard and Nietzsche: the Last Philosophers" (1989). All-College Writing Contest. https://publications.lakeforest.edu/allcollege_writing_contest/43 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Lake Forest College Publications. It has been accepted for inclusion in All-College Writing Contest by an authorized administrator of Lake Forest College Publications. For more information, please contact levinson@lakeforest.edu.

- KIERKEGAARD AND NIETZSCHE: THE I.AST PHILOSOPHERS by Peter Seigh For whatever reason, Western philosophy has always emphasized the rational nature of things. Occasionally the irrational was acknowledged, as with Descartes and his deceiving Demon, but eventually the rational was demonstrated to be reigning over the irrational. This tendency to posit the rational order of all things came to fruition with Hegel, who turned reason into a crystal palace where one could not "put out one's tongue or make a long nose on the sly" (Dostoevsky 210). With Soren Kierkegaard and Friedrich Nietzsche comes the collapse of the Crystal Palace. The Individual and the Absolute To begin, let us assume that philosophy (a) must be rational, and (b) must reflect the Truthnot just particular truths, because particular truths are relative-but rather the Truth, the terra firma of all existence (philosophers are very ambitious). Taking both of these requisites into account, we would need a rational totality which would encompass everything-logic, music, art, history, trees and butterfly wings. Such a system would encompass the whole universe and our whole lives, and we would cease to have any self-proclaimed meaning. If we were to watch this system form itself out of a void, wouldn't we, from the depths of our being, yell "enough" at this parasite of a system? Kierkegaard and Nietzsche did, and when they did, the Crystal Palace shattered, thereby demonstrating the individual's power over and above the Absolute. Each carried out his task in his own individual way, not in a systematic way. They wrote not for the "rabble" who adhered to the system, but for those special individuals who stood outside the system. Only they were able to understand. Ethics and Necessity Hegel did acknowledge the possibility of evil actions in human behavior, but he saw the choice of Good over Evil as a "necessary" choice in the historical development, one that inevitably comes about as we progress toward the Absolute. Thus one could be assured that, although there was no immediate acknowledgement of the good of one's actions, in an ultimate sense all actions 21 -- --- - -----------

22 were a necessary component in the process of Spirit's revelation. Both Kierkegaard and Nietzsche deny any necessity leading to some rationally justifiable end. "Every movement of infinity is carried out through passion, and no reflection can produce movement," asserted Kierkegaard. The actor acts in the moment, and no script can be of any use. Nietzsche goes further by proclaiming that any notion of consciousness is itself illusory, and thus Good and Evil are not actualities, but counter-instinctive contrivances which help preserve the species (BGE 11). Following this logic, we must conclude that the individuals are alone in their responsibility for the ethical outcome of their actions. Can we handle the responsibility? Whether we can or not, still we must. Abraham may feel that he is acting righteously in sacrificing his son, but we who have never spoken to God gasp at his madness. We may follow Nietzsche's suggestion that we rise above the notions of Good and Evil, but even he warns us: ''Whoever fights monsters should see to it that in the process he does not become a monster" (BGE 89). The Guilt of the Individual Drawing out the implications of an ethics without necessity, we are confronted with a terrifying possibility: a world devoid of justice, in which either God exists and allows billions to suffer and die, or there is no God, no absolute judge of good to set things in order. In a universe without justice, all incidents of the most violent magnitude stand on the same level of importance as the most insignificant trifles, and Abraham is "either a murderer or a man of faith" (FT /R 57). The reflective individual must eventually be confronted with this absurdity. Does a God who would equate murder with religious faith deserve our faith? But to judge God is dangerous, as Job discovered. The problem exists in the universe, yet every individual must answer for it, not by choice, but just because we are conscious of being individuals ourselves, and therefore know (in an immediate sense) what guilt is. Or as Kierkegaard states it: Now sin is precisely that transcendence, that discrimen rerum [crisis] in which sin enters into the individual. Sin never enters into the world differently and never has entered differently. So when the single individual is stupid enough to inquire about sin as if it were something foreign to him, he only asks as a fool, for either he does not know at all what the question is about, and thus cannot come to know it, or he knows it and understands it, and also knows that no science can explain it to him [emphasis added]. (CASO)

23 In Franz Kafka's The Trial, Joseph K. is informed of this harsh reality by the priest: "But I am not guilty," said K.; "it's a mistake. And, if it comes to that, how can any man be called guilty? We are all simply men here, one as much as the other." 'That is true," said the priest, "but that's how all guilty men talk." (Kafka 264) K. continually asserts his innocence in the eyes of the world, but just by virtue of his attempt to redeem himself in the eyes of the court, he demonstrates his guilt. Here he tries to wash his hands of guilt altogether by asking how it is possible to be guilty, but as the priest points out, the question itself, like the question of the inquirer in Kierkegaard's passage above, is itself indicative of guilt. From Nietzsche's perspective, theconceptofevilisdueatleastinparttotheherdsman'soverestimation of himself: The European disguises himself with morality because he has become a sick, sickly, crippled animal that has good reason to be "tame;" for he is almost an abortion, half made up, weak, awkward. (GS 295) Thus we behave ethically not because our actions can be seriously detrimental, but rather as an ego rationalization to compensate for our inferiority. Why Did They Write? Kierkegaard and Nietzsche present their philosophies in a way which is consistent with their views of reality- -they write with intentional ambiguity. Both are "philosophers of the dangerous 'maybe'" (BGE 11). Kierkegaard proclaims to write "in such a way that the heretics are unable to understand it" (FT /R 225). For those of us who will accept the view that it is we who are responsible for Good and Evil, we who would praise ourselves for being the exclusive audience that these men are writing to, what are we to learn from them? How are we to behave? Have we really learned anything by reading their works, if Evil is something which exists in the immediate action and not in the linguistic system alone? As for the philosophers themselves, why did they write if they knew that the ones who would understand them would be those who had this special type of wisdom? They wrote for the reason I mentioned earlier: they saw the Palace of Crystal forming out of nothing, coming to take them over. All of their projects, their ethical evaluations would be taken --- - - -- - ------------

24 up unless they as individuals spoke out. If the system was going to deny individual purpose, then the individual would have to deny the system. Or in the case of Kierkegaard and Nietzsche, he would have to deny systematic validity altogether, and write in a way contrary to systematization. In this same sense, reading their works should itself be an existential experience. What is emphasized in ethics thus is not a particular code of behavior engraved in stone, but rather the sincerity of one's actions; not just some outward measure of sincerity, but a strongly felt inward sincerity. The choice between Good and Evil is not an easy objective decision: Kierkegaard calls it the leap into the abyss (CA 61). Nietzsche suggests that we should instead acknowledge the masked nature of the Truth, (notes) which would thus include the true/false dichotomy. Aesthetics, Ethics, and justice In his book The Naked Ape, Desmond Morris presents the zoological interpretation of the origin of man. According to this view, our ape ancestors found themselves faced with extinction because their natural habitat, the rain forests, were diminishing and they were being forced out into open land. Given the harshness of the new environment, these autonomous beasts had to band together in order to survive in a setting which would otherwise have exterminated them (Morris 18-21). We find a similar interpretation in Nietzsche's philosophy: in the dawn of the human race, the individual's instincts were replaced with a weaker moral paradigm for behavior, in order that "the herd" could survive (BGE 110-114). The community valued weakness over strength so that the weaker would survive, and it is this morality that we value more than our own instincts. Nietzsche seems not to have any sympathy for morality, nor for the "herdsmen" who uphold its truth: The tree needs storms, doubts, worms, and nastiness to reveal the nature and strength of the seedling; let it break if it is not strong enough. (GS 163) In contrast to the aesthetic life of Nietzsche, Kierkegaard chooses the ethical life, only to be thrust into the trial of the religious: The paradox of faith has lost the intermediary, that is, the universal. On the one side, it has the expression for the highest egotism (to do the terrible act, do it for one's own sake), on the other side, the expression for the most absolute devotion, to do it for God's sake. (Fr /R 71)

25 Kierkegaard asserts that the reflective individual will come to value the ethical life over the aesthetic, but herein lies the absurdity: to live the true and good life, the individual would have to assert an absolute relation to the true and the good. But the mortal conscious cannot approach the absolute; God and the absolute are absurdly out of reach of the individual. Thus the ethical individual moves into the religious when he realizes that he is confined to his own subjective criteria for Good and Evil. To serve the absolute is from this perspective to potentially become a monster, as Abraham nearly did. Therefore "the single individual is higher than the universal" (Ff /R 55). Or to carry this logic further, the existing individual stands in judgment over existence itself, even over God. For the twentieth-century thinker wrestling with these two philosophies, a philosophy of paranoia must inevitably result. Nietzsche has developed, in a very sophisticated and invigorating manner, the aesthetic that Kierkegaard first turned away from. This view does not need the weak, the shy, or the reserved-if they can't stand the deluge, then they are ultimately responsible for their own extinction. Turning to Kierkegaard, one finds one's self in judgment of a God who can turn one's whole being to naught. "As flies to wanton boys are we to th' gods,/ They kill us for their sport," says Gloucester in Shakespeare's King Lear (IV,i,36-37). The bitter possibility of a world with no justice: What do I owe such a God? Why should I believe in Him? Why shouldn't I turn back to the aesthetic?-but here both Kierkegaard and Nietzsche agree: the aesthetic and the ethical are distinct. Thus anyone who has fully moved into the ethical will find that this human, all-too-human trait cannot be overcome. If the aesthetic (with Nietzsche as its spokesman) threatens to destroy the individual, and if God threatens to destroy the individual for standing in judgment over him (as God had threatened to destroy Job for doing), then the only possibility for the individual is to be the impossible: a selfsustained nothing. What About Me? Hegel demonstrated that all of the individual's projects -philosophy being the highest of these-taken on face value, are failures. He resolves this problem in an unconvincing way by demonstrating that each individual project is part of a larger process, and that individuals might content themselves with this knowledge. The only genuine reaction for Kierkegaard and Nietzsche was disillusionment: they felt that the whole of rational thought had taken on its own identity and turned a cold shoulder towards them. If this faculty of thought is not going to serve me in some reciprocal way, then what do I owe it? In this sense existentialism is a very personal philosophy. Instead of displacing the problematic into a high level of abstraction, out of reach of passionate existence (as Leibniz does in his

26 Monadology), Kierkegaard brings to light the absurdity of reason at its most mundane levels. The literary comparison is Gregor Samsa in Kafka's Metamorphosis, who continues to worry about catching his train and paying the family's debts, almost oblivious to the fact that he has been transformed into an insect. Commentary In terms of ethics, I find that I must take the perspective of Kierkegaard. For myself, an ethical life is the only life worth living. And Kierkegaard's analysis of the religious I feel must be acknowledged by the sincere individual who reflectively follows through the implications of his or her actions. However, what would life be without a touch of the Nietzschean? Carl Jung maintains that the healthy individual must befriend his "shadow" nature. Does an honest, whole-hearted affirmation of one's sensuality necessarily conflict with the ethical life as a whole? Resolution of the two may seem difficult, maybe even impossible, but it is this incongruity which I feel is a source of life's ecstatic ambiguity. Kierkegaard and Nietzsche are my two favorite philosophers. I can respect others for their analyses of particular issues-sartre for his understanding of individual freedom, Derrida for his understanding of language. But taking into consideration the extent to which we expect philosophy to tell us "the way things really are," I find that Nietzsche and Kierkegaard come closest to accomplishing this task by turning metaphysics on its head. They are the last philosophers.

27 REFERENCES Dostoevsky, Fyodor. "Notes From the Underground." Three Short Novels of Dostoevsky. Tr. Constance Garnett, Ed. Avfahm Yarmolinsky. New York: Anchor Books, 1960. Kafka, Franz. 'The Metamorphosis" from Kafka: The Complete Stories. Ed. Nahum N. Glazer. New York: Schocken Books, 1971. Kafka, Franz. The Trial. Tr. Willa and Edwin Muir. New York: Vintage Books, 1969. Kierkegaard, Soren. The Concept of Anxiety. Tr. and Ed. Reidar Thomte. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton UP, 1980. Kierkegaard, Soren. Fear and Trembling/Repetition. Ed. and Tr. Howard and Edna Hong Princeton, NJ.: Princeton UP, 1983. Morris, Desmond. The Naked Ape. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1984. Nietzsche, Friedrich. Beyond Good and Evil. Tr.Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1966. Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Gay Science. Tr. Walter Kaufmann. New York: Vintage Books, 1974. Shakespeare, William. The Tragedy of King Lear. Quoted from: The Riverside Skakespeare. Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1972. ABBREVIATIONS USED IN THE TEXT: EGE CA FI'/R GS Beyond Good and Evil The Concept of Anxiety Fear and Trembling/Repetition The Gay Science