CANCER CARE AND SAVING PARROTS. Hilary Greaves (Oxford) Philosophical foundations of effective altruism conference St Andrews, 30 March 2016

Similar documents
SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

CONSEQUENTIALISM AND THE SELF OTHER ASYMMETRY

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Justifying Rational Choice The Role of Success * Bruno Verbeek

Against Collective Consequentialism

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Act Consequentialism s Compelling Idea and Deontology s Paradoxical Idea

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Effective Animal Advocacy

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

A Contractualist Reply

Correspondence. From Charles Fried Harvard Law School

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

RALPH WEDGWOOD. Pascal Engel and I are in agreement about a number of crucial points:

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2014 Russell Marcus

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Ethics is subjective.

Maximalism vs. Omnism about Reasons*

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

The Discounting Defense of Animal Research

Moral Reasons, Overridingness, and Supererogation*

On the Separateness of Individuals, Compensation, and Aggregation Within Lives

Is atheism reasonable? Ted Poston University of South Alabama. Word Count: 4804

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Phil 108, July 15, 2010

UTILITARIANISM AND CONSEQUENTIALISM: THE BASICS

Handout 2: The Ethical Use of PEDs

The view that all of our actions are done in self-interest is called psychological egoism.

The Moral Significance of Animal Pain and Animal Death. Elizabeth Harman. I. Animal Cruelty and Animal Killing

Altruism, blood donation and public policy:

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

Are Humans Always Selfish? OR Is Altruism Possible?

Florida State University Libraries

Responsibility and Normative Moral Theories

The Social Nature in John Stuart Mill s Utilitarianism. Helena Snopek. Vancouver Island University. Faculty Sponsor: Dr.

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

ACCOMMODATING OPTIONS 1

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

Thomson s turnabout on the trolley

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Accounting for Moral Conflicts

Practical Equilibrium: A Way of Deciding What to Think about Morality

The Chinese University of Hong Kong 2018/19 2nd semester PHIL 3833 Consequentialism and its critics Course Outline (tentative)

In this paper, the phrase admirable immorality

IA Metaphysics & Mind S. Siriwardena (ss2032) 1 Personal Identity. Lecture 4 Animalism

CLIMBING THE MOUNTAIN SUMMARY CHAPTER 1 REASONS. 1 Practical Reasons

Williams The Human Prejudice

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

Ethical non-naturalism

Against Against Intellectual Property: a Short Refutation of Meme Communism

Rule-Consequentialism and Irrelevant Others DOUGLAS W. PORTMORE. Arizona State University

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

Strengths & Weaknesses of Utilitarianism

AGAINST THE BEING FOR ACCOUNT OF NORMATIVE CERTITUDE

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

THE CASE OF THE MINERS

Agnosticism, the Moral Skepticism Objection, and Commonsense Morality

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Creation & necessity

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Two Conceptions of Reasons for Action Ruth Chang

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

Utilitarianism pp

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome

CGSC 281/PHIL 181: Phil&Sci Human Nature Gendler/Yale University, Spring Reading Guide The Ring of Gyges: Morality and Hypocrisy

Contractualism and Justification 1. T. M. Scanlon. I first began thinking of contractualism as a moral theory 38 years ago, in May of

Consequentialism. The defining feature of consequentialism is that it ranks outcomes (the outcomes

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Again, the reproductive context has received a lot more attention than the context of the environment and climate change to which I now turn.

Moral Demands and Ethical Theory: The Case of Consequentialism

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

On the Alleged Incoherence of Consequentialism. by Robert Mckim and Peter Simpson

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

Transcription:

CANCER CARE AND SAVING PARROTS Hilary Greaves (Oxford) Philosophical foundations of effective altruism conference St Andrews, 30 March 2016

The EA questions Two questions for would-be effective altruists: (1) How much to give? (2) Which organisations to give it to? Moral philosophers versions of these questions (1) How much is one morally required to give? (2) What are the moral requirements concerning which organisations to give to? (Focus on giving money, for simplicity/concreteness. But the issues apply more generally.)

The austere answers The austere answers (A1) You re morally required to give up to the point of equal marginal utility (PEMU). (A2) You re morally required to: give only to the most cost-effective charities. Concerns about these answers Re (A1): Note (for whatever it s worth ) that no-one actually does this. Re (A2): What about Personal connections to benefactors: The neighbourhood child who knocks on your door asking for sponsorship Personal connections to beneficiaries: Supporting the refugee camp you have just visited Personal connections to causes: Feminism, cancer research

Alternatives to the austere answers Permissive answers: You re permitted to give less than the austere answer demands (although giving more would be agent-neutrally better). You re permitted to give to less cost-effective charities (although giving to more cost-effective charities would be agent-neutrally better). Scalar answers Giving more (up to the maximisation point), rather than less, is better. Giving to charities that are more cost-effective, rather than less, is better. Eschew any notion of moral permissibility/requirement. A mixed answer You re permitted to give less than the austere answer demands (although giving more would be better). But you are required to: give only to the most cost-effective charities.

A mixed answer in the EA literature (maybe) Should I have donated to the Fistula Foundation, knowing that I could do more to help people if I donated elsewhere? I do not think so [and] similar thoughts apply to deciding what cause to focus on more generally. By all means, we should harness the sadness we feel at the loss of a loved one in order to make the world a better place. But we should focus that motivation on preventing death and improving lives, rather than preventing death and improving lives in one very specific way. Any other decision would be unfair to those whom we could have helped more. (MacAskill 2015; emphasis added)

Outline Support for a mixed answer? Parrots, and the argument from analogy Three ways to deny (A1) Long-game maximising consequentialism Rule-consequentialism Agent-centred prerogatives all of which about-equally rationalise denying (A2) too. The argument from analogy revisited Conclusions A mixed answer to the EA questions is motivationally unstable. And the common intuitions about parrots may be wrong.

Support for the mixed answer? Analogy: The burning building You are outside a burning building. Inside, a person and a parrot are trapped. You can enter the building in an attempt to rescue either the person or the parrot, at some risk to yourself (the same risk for both rescue missions). Or you can stay outside. Arguably: in this case, it is permissible to save the person, and permissible to stay outside, but not permissible to save the parrot. But isn t this just like: it s permissible to give to the moreeffective charity, and permissible to keep the money for yourself, but not permissible to give to the less-effective charity? If so, whatever justifies the intuitive answer to the parrot case will also justify a mixed answer to the EA questions.

Inspiration from parrots What is the explanation of the intuitive permissibility pattern in the parrot case? Two stabs at this: It s both permissible to accept some cost to yourself, and to refuse that cost. But holding fixed the amount of cost-to-yourself that you have accepted, you re required to maximise aggregate benefit to others. More generally: There are two morally relevant respects of betterness in play: betterness w.r.t. cost-to-oneself, and betterness w.r.t. aggregate-benefit-to-others. The choice of how to weigh these up against one another is (perhaps within reasonable limits) a matter of agential prerogative. But a choice is permissible only if it is rationalisable by some such weighing. I.e.: maximise λ V agent + (1-λ) V others, for some reasonable value of λ.

Doubts about parrots It s not clear why betterness w.r.t. me, the parrot and the stranger cannot be three morally relevant respects, with agential freedom over how to weigh all 3. In particular, there doesn t seem to be anything obnoxious about someone who is more strongly motivated to rescue a parrot than a stranger. (Especially, but perhaps(?) not only, if it s his own parrot.) I just thought I ll have to go back and get [my parrot]. The fireman said you can t go in there, but it just had to be done. Kevin Ross, house fire survivor, 4 April 2015 Still, those who have the standard parrot intuition seem committed to the view that, for whatever reason, there are only two morally relevant respects here.

The argument from analogy In the parrot case, [for some perhaps-unknown reason] it is permissible to save the person and permissible to stay outside, but impermissible to save the parrot. The analogue of permissible to save person or neither, but impermissible to save parrot is the mixed answer to the EA questions ( permissible to give to most costeffective charities or not to give, but impermissible to give to less cost-effective charities ). The two cases are analogous in all relevant respects. Therefore, The mixed answer to the EA questions is correct [for some perhaps-unknown reason].

Against the mixed answer (however) Setting aside parrots for now Basic strategy: Argue that each of the available ways of denying (A1) also rationalises denying (A2). Therefore a mixed answer is motivationally unstable. First task: what are the available ways of denying (A1)? Long-game maximising consequentialism Rule-consequentialism Agent-centred prerogatives

First route: Long-game maximising consequentialism The austere account would give the correct account of what maximising utilitarianism implies in a last action case, i.e. if there were no implications for one s future actions of how much one gives now. But the actual case is not last-action. Likely detrimental consequences, for future giving, of giving too much now: You get depressed. Among other things, this makes you less productive at work, hence less able to give in the future. You get demoralised. This makes you more likely to just abandon the whole giving project. Difficult question: What amount of giving is long-game optimal? Probably a lot less than to the point of EMU. But probably still a lot more than almost anyone does give.

Second route: Rule-consequentialism Rule-consequentialist account: the facts about the moral permissibility of giving track the following condition for the optimal rule: whichever rule is such that the consequences of people regarding it as the true standard of moral permissibility are better than for any other rule. On this account, the facts about moral permissibility roughly track what it is strategically best for e.g. GWWC to suggest (in this domain, truth collapses into expediency-to-assert ). Maybe give 10% is the optimal answer to (1) (in this country, now).

Third route: Agent-centred prerogatives A more overtly non-consequentialist moral theory Although considerations of overall good are relevant to permissibility, we are not in general morally required to maximise the good. There are often agent-centred prerogatives to choose actions that lead to less good from an impartial point of view, when the impartially-suboptimal action in question is sufficiently (proportionately) superior in terms of self-interest. (Scheffler, The rejection of consequentialism ) Maximise λ V agent + (1-λ) V impartial, for some reasonable value of λ. Precisely because maximising impartial good when choosing one s donation-amount would be so costly for the agent, this theory will include a moral permission to give significantly less. (Again it is an open question how much less.)

Long-game maximising consequentialism on the second EA question It s not only spending more money on oneself that can reduce the probability of depression and/or demoralisation: giving some of the funds in question to causes that are closer to one s heart could so too. Up to a point. Long-game maximising consequentialism probably doesn t rule out pledging 5 by way of sponsorship for the child on your doorstep, but probably does prohibit e.g. sending 100/ 1000/etc. to Marie Curie. So perhaps we get something close to (A2) here. But note that this first route also got us something relatively close to (A1).

Rule-consequentialism on the second EA question There s a limit to how much a moral theory can require people to give to the most cost-effective charities before people will just ignore the theory in question. But it s plausible that people will be willing to give to causes closer to their heart, beyond that limit. Plausibly-optimal rule (?): Give 10% to the most costeffective charities; in addition, give as much as you want beyond that to whatever other charities you want to support. This denies (A2), so this isn t the sought-after justification for a mixed answer either.

Third route: Agent-centred prerogatives Actually, the binary division into impartial value and selfinterest is too crude if self-interest is taken literally. A more plausible model (and indeed the one Scheffler proposed) allows the agent to assign importance greater than the impartially justified amount to both persons and causes that are close to the agent s heart, not only to the agent herself. (V agent is not just about self-interest.) But this model then very clearly permits support for less cost-effective charities/causes, in much the same way as it permits keeping more than the impartially optimal quantity for oneself. (In the here-relevant sense, keeping for oneself is just giving to a particularly cost-ineffective charity that is particularly close to one s heart.)

Parrots revisited The argument from analogy can also be run as a modus tollens. Our analysis of why the mixed answer is incorrect also suggests reasons why the common intuitions about parrots may be incorrect. There could be an agent-centred prerogative to save the parrot (whether because it s your own pet parrot, or just because you particularly like parrots).

Tentative conclusions A mixed answer is motivationally inconsistent. Anyone who rejects (A1) should also reject (A2). Note that these arguments only support rejecting (A2) in order to permit preference for a suboptimal cause for which the donor has special concern. I haven t defended the permissibility of gratuitous deviations from maximising cost-effectiveness (also an important issue for EA). Perhaps it is permissible to save the parrot rather than the human after all.