Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Similar documents
It turns out that there is an important class of sentences that we have so far pretty much avoided mentioning: modal sentences.

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

Nature of Necessity Chapter IV

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Is the law of excluded middle a law of logic?

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. Against Descriptivism

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

Possibility and Necessity

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Language, reference and representation

Theories of propositions

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Analyticity and reference determiners

REFERENCE AND MODALITY. An Introduction to Naming and Necessity

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Quantificational logic and empty names

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

Rule-Following and Constitutive Rules: A Reconciliation

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Intermediate Logic Spring. Extreme Modal Realism

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

Dispositionalism and the Modal Operators

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

A CRITIQUE OF THE USE OF NONSTANDARD SEMANTICS IN THE ARBITRARINESS HORN OF DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

All philosophical debates not due to ignorance of base truths or our imperfect rationality are indeterminate.

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Conceptual idealism without ontological idealism: why idealism is true after all

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Day 3. Wednesday May 23, Learn the basic building blocks of proofs (specifically, direct proofs)

Timothy Williamson on the Contingently Concrete and Non-concrete 1. Timothy Williamson s important book Modal Logic as Metaphysics is an extended

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Armstrongian Particulars with Necessary Properties

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

In Reference and Definite Descriptions, Keith Donnellan makes a

15 Does God have a Nature?

5 The necessary and the possible

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

ELEMENTS OF LOGIC. 1.1 What is Logic? Arguments and Propositions

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

PART III - Symbolic Logic Chapter 7 - Sentential Propositions

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Modal Knowledge and Counterfactual Knowledge

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 87, No. 4. (Oct., 1978), pp

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

On A New Cosmological Argument

Logic: A Brief Introduction

6. Truth and Possible Worlds

Metametaphysics. New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology* Oxford University Press, 2009

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Varieties of Apriority

Ramsey s belief > action > truth theory.

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Slides: Notes:

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

Revelation, Humility, and the Structure of the World. David J. Chalmers

Russell: On Denoting

Overcoming Inconstancy

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Transcription:

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? by Eileen Walker 1) The central question What makes modal statements statements about what might be or what might have been the case true or false? Normally a statement is deemed to be true if it describes a state of affairs which actually obtains. 'Crows are black' is true if there are black crows. But consider: 'Cameron might have lost the election'. This describes a counterfactual state of affairs one which does not obtain. If it is true, what makes it true, and why? 2) Truth and truthmaking First, my view of truth carries on where Peter Gibson's left off. Like him, I regard myself as a 'Rottweiler realist' (to use the expression coined by Tim Williamson). I regard coherence and pragmatist theories of truth as insufficient and as leaving the door open to antirealism. The only option left seems to be some form of correspondence theory. As Peter pointed out, traditional correspondence theories, while claiming to be realist, see correspondence as a relation of equality holding between statements (propositions) on the one hand, and facts or states of affairs on the other. Correspondence is thus a symmetric relation holding between two kinds of abstract object, so is not as realist as it claims to be. Truthmaker theory attempts to address this problem. As I see it, truthmaking is an asymmetric relation between a statement or proposition and the way some things in the world are. The truthmaker of the statement 'There are 58 people in this room', if it's true, are the 58 people actually being in the room at the time of its utterance. A proposition or statement is true if it correctly represents a way things actually are. We can say that sentences, statements, assertions and thoughts all express propositions which represent a way the world is, in which case they are true. If the world fails to comply, they are false. 3) Truthmaking and modality A modal proposition states what is possible, necessary or impossible. It can also assert what might be or what might have been the case. It does not state what actually is. And this is why modality creates a problem for theories of truth and truthmaking. Modal statements - some examples (T = true; F = false): 1) Pigs might fly. (F) 2) Although David Cameron won the 2015 election (T), he might have lost it (T). 3) Although I am a human being (T), I might have been a poached egg or a football match (F). 4) The number 8 is necessarily even. (T) 5) The number of planets is necessarily even. (F) 6) There are 11 players in a football team. (T) It's possible that there might have been 13 (had the rules been set up differently) (T), but it's impossible that there could have been zero players (T). 7) No individual concrete object can be in two distinct spatiotemporal locations (No one concrete thing can be in two places at the same time). (T) 8) Necessarily, gold is the element with atomic number 79. (T) We seem to have no difficulty in judging intuitively whether modal statements are true or false. The majority of us will agree on the attributions of truth or falsehood to the modal statements above. However, there are two key problems regarding the truth of modal statements. The first is a technical question: how to account for their truth within a logical system, so that we can assign truth values and truthmakers to them systematically. The second and deeper question is to state why modal statements have the truthmakers that they do have. The solution to the technical problem, 'Possible Worlds', does not address the second problem, as we shall see. This talk was given as a Power-Point presentation with the intention of encouraging discussion and has been adapted slightly from the original. To see why, see the Stanford entry, 'Truth', by Michael Glanzberg.

4) Classical logic, modal logic and truth Classical logic is a system of representational symbols and logical operators which work together according to clearly-defined rules. The system is designed to assign truth values to statements of how things are. It handles statements such as 'pigs fly', and pigs don t fly very efficiently, as follows: a) 'Pigs fly' translates as 'for all x, if x is a pig, then x flies'. In symbols: 1 x (Px Fx) - False b) 'Pigs don't fly' translates as: 'for all x, if x is a pig, then it's not the case that x flies'. In symbols: x (Px Fx) - True However, classical logic is not designed to deal with how things might be or might have been. It doesn't have the means to handle modal sentences such as 'pigs might fly or 'pigs can't fly'. So in the mid-20c a number of modal logic systems were developed to include two further operators: 'necessarily', known as 'box', and 'possibly', known as 'diamond'. c) 'Pigs might fly' translates as: 'for all x, if x is a pig, then it's possible that x flies'. In symbols: x (Px Fx) d) 'Pigs can't fly' translates as: 'for all x, if x is a pig, then it's not the case that it's possible that x flies'. In symbols: x (Px Fx) 5) Possibility and necessity defined Necessity, possibility and impossibility are interdefinable. A proposition which is necessarily true (a necessary truth) is not possibly false. [ p p] A proposition which is possibly true (a possible truth) is not necessarily false. [ p p] A proposition which is actually true is possibly true [p p] - because if p weren't possible it couldn't be actual! The axioms above make intuitive sense if we think about them, but there are problems. 6) Modality in a mess a) The problem of substitutivity Take the two following sentences (they are non-modal versions of examples in section 3): 5*) The number 8 is even. 6*) The number of planets is even. Both 5* and 6* illustrate an important principle in non-modal logic: that terms which refer to the same object (co-referential or co-extensional terms), when substituted, should not affect the truth value of the sentences in which they occur. In 5* and 6* above, 'the number 8' and 'the number of the planets' are co-referential and the sentences are both true. But recall what happens when the necessity operator is added: 5. The number 8 is necessarily even. (True, because it's not possible for 8 to be an odd number.) 6. The number of the planets is necessarily even. (False, because the number of planets could have been otherwise, and indeed was deemed to be otherwise until recently.) 1 The logical connectives are: conjunction: ('and') &; disjunction: ('or') v; the material conditional: ('if...then') ; the biconditional: ('if and only if'; 'if') ; the negation operator: ('it is not the case that'). Also known as the 'problem of extensionality', depending on the context of the argument.

The addition of the 'necessity' operator has failed to preserve the truth of 6*, thereby infringing the principle of substitutivity salva veritate. It was this problem that led Quine to reject the notion of modality altogether. b) Structure without meaning Various systems of modal logic are developed incorporating 'box' and 'diamond'. All of these make different basic assumptions about the interplay of necessity and possibility, and their axioms and theorems grow increasingly complex. We can end up with long strings of iterated boxes and diamonds like the following: (( p) & ( p) Most of us would have great difficulty in working out what this means. If we can't work out what it means, we can't tell whether it is true, and if we can't tell whether it is true, we can't judge whether it will play a useful role in our truthmaking theory or not. In fact, if we apply the reduction rules of system S5 to this string of symbols, thereby eliminating all boxes and diamonds except the final ones, we get: ( p) & ( p) This translates as: 'It's not the case that "possibly p" and "not possibly p" are both true'. In fact, it is simply the modal form of a fundamental law of logic, that a proposition and its negation cannot both be true. It is thus very useful in any theory of truth. But this is not the only difficulty with the system. To sum up: modal logic can give strange results, can be difficult to interpret, and does not reflect everyday linguistic usage; there are several, sometimes conflicting, modal systems. In an attempt to solve these and other technical complications, Saul Kripke develops his system of 'Possible Worlds' semantics. 7) Possible Worlds and Truthmaking In Kripke's system, developed between 1959 and 1963, Necessity and Possibility are defined as follows: P: A proposition is necessarily true if it is true in all Possible Worlds. P: A proposition is possibly true if it is true in some (at least one) Possible World. Metaphysically speaking, a Possible World is simply a way our world might be or might have been. It is not an alternative concrete world, like the worlds of David Lewis. However, questions regarding the ontological status of Possible Worlds are not under discussion here. Our concern is to address the problems encountered in the previous section, and see how the apparatus of Possible Worlds can provide truthmakers for the modal sentences of section 3. So can Possible Worlds explain the problem of substitutivity? 'The number of the planets is even' happens to be true in at least one Possible World - ours. But it expresses a contingent fact about our solar system; there are Possible Worlds where it isn't true. Setting aside taxonomical issues about the size a chunk of orbiting rock needs to reach to qualify for the label 'planet', it is surely the case that the history of the solar system might have gone otherwise. If Mars had been shattered by an asteroid, the number of planets would have been odd. So 'the number of the planets' picks out different numbers in different Possible Worlds, some odd, some even. Contrast the number 8, which in all Possible Worlds is even, never odd. Where does this leave the Principle of Substitutivity - that co-extensive expressions can be swapped around without affecting the truth value of the statements in which they occur? If there are Possible Worlds where 'the number of planets' and 'the number 8' can pick out different objects, then these expressions cannot be co-extensive after all. The Principle of Substitutivity is not infringed. Kripke labelled terms which pick out the same referent in all Possible Worlds 'rigid'. Rigid terms include proper names, numerals and some natural kind terms such as 'gold' or 'water'. 'The number of the planets' is a descriptive term and picks out whichever referent happens to satisfy the description. Descriptive expressions are rarely rigid. 3

How about truthmakers? The truthmakers of our modal statements are not the Possible Worlds themselves, but their inhabitants, if such there be. If the truthmaker for non-modal statements is a way some things in the actual world are, then the truthmaker for a modal statement is a way some things are in some, all, or no possible world. If 'pigs might fly' is true, there will be at least one possible world that contains the odd flying pig as truthmaker. If there is no such world, then the proposition is false. There is a possible world inhabited by a rejected and dejected David Cameron who provides the truthmaker for the assertion: 'David Cameron might have lost the 2015 election'. Gold has atomic number 79 in all possible worlds where the substance exists, so a proposition asserting this is necessarily true. In no possible world do I exist as a poached egg, so the proposition that I might have been one is necessarily false. Now recall the two key problems raised earlier regarding the truth of modal statements. The first was technical: how to account for their truth within a logical system, so that truth conditions and truth values (hence truthmakers) can be assigned to propositions systematically. The 'Possible Worlds' apparatus, in combination with the systems of modal logic developed in the mid-20c, does give us a way of applying truth conditions and truth values to modal propositions. It does not address the second, more fundamental question: on what grounds do we judge whether a modal statement is true or false? If we try to say why the modal statements we looked at earlier are true or false, we realise that we must already have some presuppositions as to how modality works before arriving at a judgment using the Possible Worlds apparatus. 8) Grounding the truth of modal statements: the varieties of modality Most of us would agree that pigs cannot fly, and would happily accept that there is no possible world where pigs do fly. (Claims that we could perhaps make pigs fly by putting them inside robot flying machines, or interfering with their genome over generations, miss the point.) But a neo- Humean might object on the grounds that we can imagine a flying pig, and what is imaginable or conceivable is possible. If this argument seems unconvincing, it can then be objected that although it is a physical impossibility, there is no logical contradiction involved in asserting that pigs might fly. The neo-humean is surely right on this point. But if it is logically, albeit not physically - or perhaps metaphysically - possible that pigs fly, it leads to the thought that we need to distinguish between types of possibility and necessity before we can say whether a modal statement is true or false. Kripke and others have in fact suggested how the various systems of modal logic might map onto the varieties of necessity and possibility that we actually use. The commonest ones are the logical, metaphysical, physical, mathematical, epistemic and deontic modalities, each of which has its own set of Possible Worlds and key axioms. Since we are concerned with modality and truth, the modalities of interest are the so-called 'alethic' modalities: those where necessarily p implies p. (In symbols: p p). If 'necessarily p' ( p) is true, it is true in all possible worlds. Since all possible worlds include the actual world, we would expect p to be true in the actual world. But it isn t always, as happens for example in the case of deontic necessity. This is the modality to do with ethics and the law, and concerns what one ought to do. 'Ought' ( p) implies 'can' ( p), but doesn t imply that p actually happens. In all possible worlds, one ought to nurture one's children, but there are worlds, including the actual world, where this does not occur. So let us return to the alethic modalities, where if 'P' is necessarily true, it must be actually true. The converse, clearly, does not apply: if something is possibly true, it may or may not be actually For detail, see the Stanford entry on 'Possible Worlds'. The issue of whether conceivability can ground possibility is hotly contested. Most nowadays, including Stephen Yablo, say that it cannot, though David Chalmers disagrees. See their websites. See Peter Gibson's page on Modal Logic for a summary of how the various systems of modal logic map onto the varieties of modality, as we usually understand them. Contact him at:

true - sometimes we don't know enough to decide. But we should bear in mind the following constraints: 'Possibility' diagram for the alethic modalities As shown in the nested diagram, it is generally accepted that logical possibility is the broadest species of possibility. Anything which does not contradict the laws of logic is possible. It is therefore true in some logically possible world that pigs fly, that spaceships exceed the speed of light, and that frogs turn into princes. The truthmakers for these logically possible statements are the magical beings that exist in those worlds. But these worlds are not metaphysically possible. Metaphysical possibilities are of course constrained by logical possibility but also by the natures or essences of all the things that exist or could exist. Physical possibilities are further constrained by the physical laws and constants of our universe. So how does this work? A neo-humean might claim that it is false that the element gold necessarily has atomic number 79. Although the proposition is true in the actual world, there might be metaphysically possible worlds where it has a different atomic number. The response to the Humean is that the natures or essences of the things that exist in our universe are subject to its physical laws and constants, and it is unlikely that they could exist in worlds where those were different - where the Big Bang had had a different outcome. An essentialist (and most chemists) would argue that a substance with a different atomic number would have a totally different nature and properties from those of gold. It would not be gold. So when it comes to modal statements concerning existents in the actual world, it seems plausible that physical and metaphysical possibility coincide. All contestants would agree, however, that there is no logical contradiction involved in the assertion that gold might have had a different atomic number. Of course this is just the beginning of an exploration of truth and modality. I have not touched on key issues such as the epistemology of modality, the analysis of counterfactuals, possible and impossible objects, all of which are discussed in the wonderful SEP. Over to you! References Gibson, Peter (2015) one-page summary of modal logic. Contact him for a copy Hale, Bob (2015) handouts from 2015 OUDCE weekend on Necessity and Possibility: see our website. from the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2015): Glanzberg, Michael: 'Truth'; see also the articles on coherence, correspondence and pragmatist theories. Kment, Boris: 'The Varieties of Modality' Menzel, Christopher: 'Possible Worlds' Vaidya, Anand: 'The Epistemology of Modality' Diagram borrowed from Anand Vaidya's excellent SEP article 'The Epistemology of Modality'. 5