Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Similar documents
Skepticism and Internalism

Williamson s proof of the primeness of mental states

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Comments on Lasersohn

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Varieties of Apriority

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

5 A Modal Version of the

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Scepticism, Rationalism and Externalism *

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

The Problem of the External World

A Priori Bootstrapping

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

Higher-Order Epistemic Attitudes and Intellectual Humility. Allan Hazlett. Forthcoming in Episteme

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Outsmarting the McKinsey-Brown argument? 1

Stout s teleological theory of action

What Should We Believe?

This handout follows the handout on The nature of the sceptic s challenge. You should read that handout first.

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

ABSTRACT: In this paper, I argue that Phenomenal Conservatism (PC) is not superior to

Inferential Evidence. Jeff Dunn. The Evidence Question: When, and under what conditions does an agent. have proposition E as evidence (at t)?

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

PHENOMENAL CONSERVATISM, JUSTIFICATION, AND SELF-DEFEAT

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

What is knowledge? How do good beliefs get made?

EXERCISES, QUESTIONS, AND ACTIVITIES

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Scepticism, Rationalism and Externalism

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

From Descartes to Locke. Consciousness Knowledge Science Reality

What is Justification?

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Notes for Week 4 of Contemporary Debates in Epistemology

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

x is justified x is warranted x is supported by the evidence x is known.

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

24.00: Problems of Philosophy Prof. Sally Haslanger November 16, 2005 Moral Relativism

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

The Epistemic Significance of M oral Disagreement. Dustin Locke Claremont McKenna College

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Decisions and Higher-Order Knowledge

Craig on the Experience of Tense

From Brains in Vats.

1 John Hawthorne s terrific comments contain a specifically Talmudic contribution: his suggested alternative interpretation of Rashi s position. Let m

Problems in Philosophy Final Review. Some methodological points

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

Internalism Re-explained

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Four Arguments that the Cognitive Psychology of Religion Undermines the Justification of Religious Belief

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

New Lessons from Old Demons: The Case for Reliabilism

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

Scepticism, Infallibilism, Fallibilism

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

Transcription:

Chapter 8 Skepticism Williamson is diagnosing skepticism as a consequence of assuming too much knowledge of our mental states. The way this assumption is supposed to make trouble on this topic is that it leads us to think we have the same evidence in the good and bad cases (because evidence is the stuff on the inside we have access to and hence knowledge of, and our evidence is only that kind of stuff). There are dangers of begging the question in what Williamson is trying to do. For example, it s important to see that it just follows automatically from having an epistemologically externalist approach to knowledge that if we are in the good case, then we know we re in the good case. This is because all the causal (say) stuff is working right (e.g. perception), and the epistemological externalist makes no further demands in order to count someone as knowing. (Obviously, the epistemological internalist couldn t disagree more with either of these claims.) But no epistemological externalist thinks that this is a reply to the skeptic or an argument that the skeptic makes false assumptions. If anything, this looks like a strike against an externalist view to the extent that it shows how impoverished externalism is to explain why the skeptical challenge is appealing at all. (Tracking can, but other externalisms have nothing.) Williamson is aware of this danger of course, and does not appeal directly to his E=K thesis (so since your knowledge is different your evidence must be different), for example, in order to diagnose and undermine the appeal of skepticism. He s making arguments that look independent of that. But watch carefully for slip-ups, and ask yourself whether the arguments that he says make skepticism appealing, and that he shows don t work, are really necessary for skepticism to be appealing. Also, ask yourself what would an example be of the kind of evidence that is different in the good and bad cases? Williamson charges that the natural argument the skeptic has that one s evidence is the same in the good case and the bad case is a reduction ad absurdum (pp. 169-70) that assumes that one knows what one s evidence is. In section 8.6 TW waves the sorites wand and reduces this assumption to blubbering foolishness. (Dead horses don t deserve this kind of treatment.) TW says that this argument is an application of the anti-luminosity argument to sameness of evidence (so see our earlier discussion and criticisms of that). Since I ve lost all patience with sorites arguments in this domain, I ll just make a few observations. This argument doesn t seem quite an application, since it goes by constructing an argument that is parallel to the argument he attributes to the skeptic. This means we have to ask whether the parallel argument is relevant to that sameness of evidence argument ((1)- (12), pp. 171-2). One way that it seems to me it s not relevant can be seen in claim (2 i ), p. 175: (2i) For any appropriate property pi, if in a i-1 one s evidence lacks pi, then in a i one knows that one s evidence lacks pi. 1

He says the justification for this claim is just like the justification for claim (2), p. 171: (2) For any property pi, if in the good case one s evidence lacks pi, then in the bad case one knows that in the good case one s evidence lacks pi. To say that the argument for (2 i ) is the same as the argument for this one is to presuppose that the relevant difference between the good and bad cases--what could tell you which case you re in if only you knew it--is like the difference between light changes at 1 millisecond intervals. This doesn t seem at all right since the difference between the good case and bad case is the difference between having a hand and not having a hand, which isn t a gradual question. You could say: well, it doesn t matter since all TW needs is one pi such that people can t know whether pi is a property of their evidence, in order to undermine the skeptic s sameness of evidence claim, since the sameness of evidence claim depended on the claim that one always knows what one s evidence is. But this doesn t seem to me nearly enough. That people don t know, indeed can t know, these small differences doesn t matter since being able to know them wouldn t help, and because it doesn t imply people can t know big differences, the kind of things that are differences between the good and bad scenarios, if only we could see those differences. In other words, one doesn t have to know everything about one s evidence to know that the good and bad cases are indiscriminable. You don t know properties of the evidence that are indiscriminable from each other, but knowing those wouldn t have helped you tell whether you were in the good or bad case anyway, so we don t need to claim we do know them in order to defend an indiscriminability claim. Besides, talk of a sameness of evidence claim is a little misleading. All you need to know is that your evidence is the same as far as you know. I m not sure we needed the anti-luminosity argument against our knowing what our evidence is, since, as TW argues in a later section (8.7), and as has been familiar to Bayesians for some time, rationality is not transparent. That is, one can be rational without knowing that one is. One can be responsive to evidence in a rational way, that is, in conformity with the axioms of probability, for example, without knowing what one s evidence is. (TW is all wrong about Bayesianism in that section.) Thus, we shouldn t have expected in the first place that we know what our evidence is. I m going to focus on the claim: (I) For any appropriate property pi, in any case in which one s evidence has pi, one knows that one s evidence has pi. Roughly, one knows what one s evidence is. In particular, I m going to ask whether the skeptic needed that claim in order to create the problem. I will argue that far from needing that, he really needs a version of the denial of it, the claim that TW himself is arguing for: one does not in general know what one s evidence is. 2

There are two different kinds of evidence that TW persistently conflates in these chapters that deal with the concept. One is the notion we invoke when we say the enormous pool of blood is evidence of a murder, more precisely that there is a huge pool of blood is evidence that there was a murder. In this sense of evidence nothing is implied about whether it is available to anyone. It s this same sense of evidence a detective invokes when she says there must be evidence, if only she could find it. In this sense evidence is facts that are traces or indicators of other putative facts. We may respond rationally and appropriately to such facts without knowing that we do we do this every day and without knowing what our evidence, in this sense, is. If I m in the good case, then that I have a hand is evidence (in this sense) that I m not a brain in a vat, that is, that I m in the good case. If I m in the bad case, then there is no such evidence, to be sure, since there is no hand. Thus there is an asymmetry between the evidence in the good case and bad case, but so far it only applies to the kind of evidence we might call objective, that carries no assumption about its availability to my awareness or about my knowledge that I am responding rationally to it, or about my knowledge that it is there. Nothing in the points I ve described says that the evidence in the good case and the bad case could not look the same to me. (Is TW claiming that is metaphysically impossible? I don t think that s the tack.) The significance of this is that we have granted everything Williamson argued for: that there is a notion of evidence that is not phenomenal (yes, this meets TW s demands for the way science treats evidence, in section 8.5), that we do not know what our evidence is in this sense of evidence, and that we do not know what its appropriate properties are. Yet the skeptic can still make his point. This he can do with the other notion of evidence, which is something like evidence for me, evidence that I m aware is there, so to speak. We can make the point best, perhaps, by discussing it as what my evidence is for all I know. And then the skeptic s point would be to ask how it is I know that what seems to me a hand is evidence that I m not a brain in a vat. The hand-seeming is evidence (in the good case) that I m not a brain in a vat because in that case all is functioning normally so the hand-seeming is an indicator of my having a hand, and both are indicators of nonenvatment. In the good case those things are evidence. In the bad case the first is not and the second isn t the case. I don t know which they are, so for all I know my evidence is the same. I should say that I m not drawing this distinction between two senses of evidence just because it s convenient here. It s also what I endorsed in TT and is desirable on other grounds. If you read these chapters of TW with the distinction in mind, you feel that he is sweeping it under the rug, using the term evidence indifferently between these two ideas, in order to lull us into giving up reference to a distinction between the metaphysically internal and external. Using words differently is a somewhat okay tactic when you re trying to show people it s possible to see something in a new way, but when you see how he s doing it here, and that the success of his argument actually depends on conflating the two notions, then it begins to look like he s massively begging the question. 3

Notes on Williamson on Evidence and Skepticism 11/01/06 (B.F.) The central claim Williamson pushes in his scepticism chapter is that there is an evidential asymmetry between the good case and the bad case. According to Williamson, an agent in the good case can posess more evidence than an agent in the bad case. For instance, an agent S in the good case can have the evidence that S has hands, whereas, in the bad case (e.g., an envatted S), S cannot have the evidence that S has hands. I think it s difficult to assess Williamson s position in this chapter without assessing his understanding of The proposition p is part of S s evidence. We ll do this next week in detail, but even this week I think it is useful to have in mind Williamson s schema: (EV) E is evidence for H for S iff S s evidence includes E and E supports H. What s at issue in the scepticism chapter is just the first part of (EV) which propositions are included in S s evidence. We will assume that the proposition (E) that S has hands supports the proposition (H) that S is not in the bad case. What s controversial is whether S can possess this evidence in both the good and the bad cases. The sceptic will say S can possess E in both cases (if S can possess E at all). Williamson will say S can only possess E in the good case. Most of Williamson s moves in the scepticism chapter are defensive in nature. They aim to block certain arguments which aim to show that S s evidence is the same in the good and bad cases. I tend to agree with Fumerton (and Sherri) about the relative weakness of the defensive moves Williamson offers here. He seems to offer a very naïve reconstruction of the sceptic s reasons for saying that S can have E in the bad cases (if S has E in the good case). E.g., (1) For any relevant property P, in any case in which one s evidence has P, one knows that one s evidence has P. As Fumerton explains, nobody (not even a sceptic) should assume something this strong. And, as Sherri explains, there is a rather strong intuition that there can be pairs of good/bad cases in which the agent has the same evidence in what seems to be a salient and legitimate (and interesting) sense of has. An analogy might be useful here. Let s say you re someone who values money for its instrumental power. You like having money only to the extent that it will actually do things for you. As it turns out, unbeknownst to you, you possess lots of money. Some benefactor has placed a large sum of money in an account that (legally) you own. But, the catch is that he didn t tell you anything about this, and you will never find out about it. 1 Are you rich? Well, there is a sense in which you are rich, but it s not a very interesting sense, especially by your own lights. Legally, you own lots of money. But, since as far as you know you re the same poor schmuck you were yesterday, this is a sense of 1 We can fill-in the details of a complicated story here if we want to make this plausible: assume it s a joint Swiss bank account you forgot you had, and you were estranged from the benefactor for many years, who was a former business partner of yours with access to the account, etc., etc. 1

rich that has no cash value for you. I think something analogous is happening in this discussion about what evidence you have in the good vs bad cases. Williamson is quick to point out that we cannot always know what evidence we have. And, I (like Sherri) think that the sceptic should simply welcome this and say Yeah, and that s what stinks about the sceptical cases. As far as S knows, her evidence is just as it would be if she were in the bad case, whether she is in fact in the bad case or not. The sceptic can grant that if S is in the good case, then she has evidence that supports she is not in the bad case; whereas, if S is in the bad case, then she does not have evidence that supports that she is not in the good case. But, it s the cash value of the having that s as issue here. We can similarly grant that if S is in the kind-butforgotten-benefactor (good) case then she has money that is sufficient to pay her mortgage; whereas, if S is in the same-poor-schumck-she-was-yesterday (bad) case, then she does not have money that is sufficient to pay her mortgage. So what? How does that help S pay her mortgage even if she happens to be in the good case? It doesn t. I suspect the sceptic would say something analogous about the extra Williamsonian evidence S has in the good case. The sceptic is interested in accessible differences between bodies of evidence. There may be a sense in which we have more evidence in the good case, but the question is whether this is a sense that has any epistemological cash value. 2