R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford p : the term cause has at least three different senses:

Similar documents
Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

John Duns Scotus. 1. His Life and Works. Handout 24. called The Subtle Doctor. born in 1265 (or 1266) in Scotland; died in Cologne in 1308

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

1/13. Locke on Power

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

Stout s teleological theory of action

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

According to Russell, do we know the self by acquaintance? (hint: the answer is not yes )

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Kant and his Successors

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

DETERMINISM is the view that all events without exception are effects or, a little

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Time travel and the open future

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

EFFICIENT CAUSATION A HISTORY. Edited by Tad M. Schmaltz. Oxford Philosophical Concepts. Oxford

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

A Rate of Passage. Tim Maudlin

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Act individuation and basic acts

This handout follows the handout on Hume on causation. You should read that handout first.

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

The CopernicanRevolution

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

What God Could Have Made

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

The British Empiricism

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

This handout follows the handout on Determinism. You should read that handout first.

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

Thomas Reid on personal identity

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

8 Internal and external reasons

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

1/8. The Third Analogy

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Mary Shepherd's Two Senses of Necessary Connection

Kant and the Problem of Personal Identity Jacqueline Mariña

1/5. The Critique of Theology

DENIALS & AFFIRMATIONS

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

The Supplement of Copula

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

The Holy Spirit. The Voice for God or the Voice of God? by Robert Perry. When and why did it happen? August/September/2014/Issue #130

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

DALLAS BAPTIST UNIVERSITY THE ILLOGIC OF FAITH: FEAR AND TREMBLING IN LIGHT OF MODERNISM SUBMITTED TO THE GENTLE READER FOR SPRING CONFERENCE

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Kant s Copernican Revolution

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

PHIL / PSYC 351. Thinking and Reasoning

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Minh Alexander Nguyen

Transcription:

R. G. Collingwood, An Essay on Metaphysics, Clarendon Press, Oxford 1998. p. 285-6: the term cause has at least three different senses: Sense I. Here that which is caused is the free and deliberate act of a conscious and responsible agent, and causing him to do it means affording him a motive for doing it. Sence II. Here that which is caused is an event in nature, and its cause is an event or state of things by producing or preventing which we can produce or prevent that whose cause it is said to be. Sense III. Here that which is caused is an event or state of things, and its cause is another event or state of things standing to it in a one-one relation of causal priority: i.e. a relation of such a kind that (a) if the cause happens or exists the effect also must [286] happen, or exist, even if no further conditions are fulfilled, (b) the effect cannot happen or exist unless the cause happens or exists, (c) in some sense which remains to be defined, the cause is prior to the effect; for without such priority there would be no telling which is which. If C and E were connected merely by a one-one relation such as is described in the sentences (a) and (b) above, there would be no reason why C should be the cause of E, and E the effect of C, rather than vice versa. But whether causal priority is temporal priority, ior a special cause of temporal priority or priority of some other kind, is another question. He distinguishes them as (roughly) the historical, practical. theoretical sense. (What s missing: the sense in which a free agent is the cause of what she does. Collingwood does not think this is a case of causation, because causing is doing something by doing something else.) SENSE I p. 292: In the contrary, as I shall show in the following chapters, both sense II and sense III logically presuppose sense I; and any attempt to use the word in sense II or III without the anthropomorphic implications belonging to sense I must result either in a misuse of the word cause (that is, its use in a sense not consistent with the facts of

established usage), or in a redefinition of it so as to make it mean what in established usage it does not mean: two alternatives which differ only in that established usage is defied with or without a formal declaration of war. p. 292-3: For causation in sense I, one needs an aim ( causa ut ) and certain circumstances ( causa quod ). That is, one may cause someone to do X by making her intend X, or by putting her in a position so that she can attain X, or both. Collingwood says: A brings about that p is not a case of causation (in sense I) A brings about that B does C is a case of causation. - why? For Collingwood, a cause (in sense I) is always a cause for someone to do something. p. 294: Collingwood admits the special case of someone causing herself to do something; that is: she sets herself a goal and brings herself in the position to achieve it. (p. 320: the word necessary also has a primarily historical sense, in which it refers to the necessity for a person to act in a certain way.) SENSE II p. 296: In this sense, the cause of an event in nature is the handle, so to speak, by which human beings can manipulate it. If we human beings want to produce or prevent such a thing, and cannot produce or prevent it immediately (as we can produce or prevent certain movements of our own bodies), we set about looking for its cause. p. 297: What is immediately produced (in position of the switch) is the cause in sense II of what is thus mediately produced. Causes are always means for getting a further result. Just doing something is not causing it; only doing something by doing something else is causing it. p. 301: A cause in sense II is never able by itself to produce the corresponding effect. (Conditions must be appropriate.) A cause in sense II is conditional, a cause in sense III is unconditional. Collingwood s point is: in sense III, the cause of X is that from which it necessarily followed; but this must include all conditions under which it

followed. He refers to Mill. p. 302-3: When we use cause in sense II, we pick out only a part of the cause in sense III, namely the part we can manipulate. p. 304, principle of the relativity of causes: for any given person the cause in sense II of a given thing is that one of its conditions which he is able to produce or prevent. This means that I cannot speak of causes that I cannot manipulate. What only you can manipulate is a cause for you, but I cannot refer to it as a cause at all. p. 308: because causes in sense II are manipulable, they must be specified in general terms. There is no cause in sense II of only one individual event, for the question is: how can one produce or prevent such an event? p. 309: sense II derives from sense I in that the idea that one thing is a cause in sense II of another derives from our experience of how we make people act in certain ways. (Collingwood is answering Hume s question: whence the impression? He says: from interaction with people.) The cause-effect terminology conveys an idea not only of on thing s leading to another but of one thing forcing another to happen or exist; an idea of power or compulsion or constraint. From what impression, as Hume asks, is this idea derived? I answer, from impressions received in our social life, in the practical relations of man to man; specifically, from the impression of causing (in sense I) some other man to do something when, by argument or command or threat or the like, we place him in a situation in which he can only carry out his intentions by doing that thing; and conversely, from the impression of being caused to do something. (Hume answers, in the Enquiry: reference to our experience of humans bringing about stuff does not help. Here we also do not experience causation directly.) p. 309: Sense II of cause is animistic. Collingwood: To speak of causes in sense II is to treat things as if they were persons. Sense II of the word cause is especially a Greek sense; in modern times it is especially associated with the survival or revival of Greek ideas in the earlier Renaissance thinkers; and both the Greek ideas and the earlier Renaissance thinkers held quite seriously an animistic theory of nature. They thought of what we call the material or physical world as a living organism or complex of living organisms, each with its own sensations and desires and intentions and thoughts.

SENSE III p. 313: causes in sense II are thought to be part of a world in which nothing is contingent. The point is not manipulability, but necessity. p. 314: x is a cause in the tight sense if it is necessary and sufficient for its effect. p. 314-5: If in the proposition x causes the explosion we wish to use the word cause in the tight sense, x must be so defined as to include in itself every such conditio sine qua non.... [315]... Only then is the cause in sense III complete; and when it is complete it produces the effect, not afterwards (however soon afterwards) but then. Cause in sense III is simultaneous with effect. Similarly, it is coincident with its effect in space. (Collingwood refers to this as the principle that there can be no action at a distance.) - If Collingwood is right, then cause and effect are the same event according to Davidson s later criterion of event-identity. They happen at exactly the same time and place. Causes in sense III include all conditions that lead to the effect, and therefore cannot stop anywhere short of the actual effect. p. 331: Now the cause of an event can be a previous event only when cause is used in sense II.... for sense III implies a one-one relation between cause and effect, and events between which there is a one-one relation must be simultaneous. p. 322: Causation in sense III is an anthropomorphic idea. Again: The idea of compulsion, as applied to events in nature, is derived from our experiences of occasions on which we have compelled others to act in certain ways by placing them in situations (or calling their attention to the fact that they are in situations) of such a kind that only by so acting can they realize the intentions we know or rightly assume them to entertain: and, conversely, occasions in which we have ourselves been thus compelled. Collingwood seems to think: Primarily, only humans can be compelled to do something, and only humans can compel them to do anything. Necessity does not apply to non-human nature; this is why talk about causation is animistic. p. 323: If a man can be said to cause certain events in nature by adopting certain

means to bringing them about, and if God is conceived semi-anthropomorphically as having faculties like those of the human mind but greatly magnified, it will follow that God also will be regarded as bringing about certain things in nature by the adoption of certain means. p. 324: But this does not mean that all things other than God are causally inert. Collingwood refers to the Liber de Causis: the first cause transfers its causal power to the following causes. And to John the Scot, (Eriugena? Duns Scotus?) who speaks of a division of nature that both is created and creates. p. 324:... the activity of these secondary causes is a scaled-down version of God s and God s is a scaled-up version of man s. p. 327: [If there were only absolute or only relative motion:] It would have become plain that there is no truth concealed beneath the animistic metaphor; and that the idea of causation is simply a relic of animism foisted upon a science to which it is irrelevant. Collingwood implies that this is the case. This is what modern physics has done. Developing the Newtonian doctrine in the simplest and most logical way, it has eliminated the notion of cause altogether. But according to Collingwood this only means that the term cause in sense III is obsolete. p. 327: At the same time, the survival of the term cause in certain sciences other than physics, such as medicine, is not a symptom of their backwardness, because in them the word cause is not used in the same sense. They are practical sciences, and they accordingly use the word in sense II. p. 330: where Newton says that every change has a cause, Kant says that every event has a cause; but a change is when something new begins, and not every event involves something new. From a Newtonian point of view, only events that are not accounted for by laws need a cause. p. 335 about the animistic analogies of causal language: A well-devised vocabulary

for use in natural science would avoid them.