How probability begets belief

Similar documents
Hume s Critique of Miracles

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

HUME'S THEORY. THE question which I am about to discuss is this. Under what circumstances

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 5d God

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Your Decision Determines Your Destiny

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Philosophy 428M Topics in the History of Philosophy: Hume MW 2-3:15 Skinner Syllabus

1/8. Introduction to Kant: The Project of Critique

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

On the Expected Utility Objection to the Dutch Book Argument for Probabilism

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

16 Free Will Requires Determinism

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Skepticism and Internalism

Forms of Justification when Reading Scientific Arguments

The British Empiricism

PHIL1110B Introduction to Philosophy 哲學概論 Course Outline

The end of the world & living in a computer simulation

Series: Trust Issues: Is Christianity Believable Today? Title: The Bible: Fact or Fiction? Pastor Chad E. Billington

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Possibility and Necessity

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

Instructor Information Larry M. Jorgensen Office: Ladd Hall, room Office Hours: Mon-Thu, 1-2 p.m.

RATIONALITY AND SELF-CONFIDENCE Frank Arntzenius, Rutgers University

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Module - 02 Lecturer - 09 Inferential Statistics - Motivation

Module 02 Lecture - 10 Inferential Statistics Single Sample Tests

Go and make a survey of the land and write a description of it.

Olle Häggström, Mathematical Sciences, Chalmers University of Technology.

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

New Chapter: Ethics and Morality

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

BCC Papers 5/2, May

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Science and the Christian Faith. Brent Royuk June 11, 2006

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

GREAT PHILOSOPHERS: Thomas Reid ( ) Peter West 25/09/18

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

PH 1000 Introduction to Philosophy, or PH 1001 Practical Reasoning

Now you know what a hypothesis is, and you also know that daddy-long-legs are not poisonous.

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

6. The most important thing about climate change

I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth.

Nigerian University Students Attitudes toward Pentecostalism: Pilot Study Report NPCRC Technical Report #N1102

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

that the only way a belief can be justified is if it is based on sufficient evidence. However,

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Contradictory Information Can Be Better than Nothing The Example of the Two Firemen

Lend me your eyes; I can change what you see! ~~Mumford & Sons

There are various different versions of Newcomb s problem; but an intuitive presentation of the problem is very easy to give.

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Objective Evidence and Absence: Comment on Sober

Certainty, Necessity, and Knowledge in Hume s Treatise

A Posteriori Necessities

Defining Ontological Naturalism

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

The Illusion of Scientific Realism: An Argument for Scientific Soft Antirealism

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Chapter 20 Testing Hypotheses for Proportions

Against Individual Responsibility (Sinnott-Armstrong)

A Posteriori Necessities by Saul Kripke (excerpted from Naming and Necessity, 1980)

This is the central lesson of Calculated Risks, a fascinating book by Gerd Gigerenzer, a cognitive

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Lesson 1: Conditions, Choices & Gray Areas

climate change in the american mind Americans Global Warming Beliefs and Attitudes in March 2012

Outline. The argument from so many arguments. Framework. Royall s case. Ted Poston

CAN TWO ENVELOPES SHAKE THE FOUNDATIONS OF DECISION- THEORY?

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

King and Kitchener Packet 3 King and Kitchener: The Reflective Judgment Model

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Varieties of Apriority

Knowledge, Trade-Offs, and Tracking Truth

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

January Parish Life Survey. Saint Paul Parish Macomb, Illinois

The Qualiafications (or Lack Thereof) of Epiphenomenal Qualia

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Epistemic Risk and Relativism

He was told to send us his data and he did send something, but I do not believe that there is anything there about the aggregations. I may be wrong.

Chapter Summaries: A Christian View of Men and Things by Clark, Chapter 1

Winning the Day Spiritually: Temptation Survey Results

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Transcription:

Philosophy 304 How probability begets belief Topic #3 Betsy McCall Spring 2010

In An Inquiry Concerning Human Understanding, David Hume argues strongly against our ability to know a great many things for certain. Other than facts which are known to us from past experience, or mathematical truths, we cannot know anything about future events, or true metaphysical states of the universe, particularly those that apply to forces, or cause and effect. Indeed, Hume argues that cause and effect is essentially an appearance, and future events cannot be known to follow from past similar events. However, Hume does suggest that we can believe something about future events (as opposed to know) based on past experience. For he says that : If we allow that belief is nothing but a firmer and stronger conception of an object than what attends the mere fictions of the imagination, this operation may, perhaps, in some measure be accounted for. (Hume 70). In other words, if we see an event attend upon another a number of times, then we will begin to expect, to believe, that the event we have seen so often in the past will happen yet again. And that our belief will be roughly proportional to the number of times those events have occurred together vs. when they have not, as in the manner of a probability, since, from our perspective, we cannot tell the difference between chance events and events which are otherwise (and unpredictably) related by their, in Hume s mind, accidental occurrence together and having the appearance of cause and effect. Because we cannot tell the difference, in our minds we treat them identically: as probabilities. (Hume 71) The strength of our beliefs depends on the strength of the probabilities, and thus the number of times the event has occurred relative to the number of times it has failed to occur. (Hume 71) If an event occurs repeatedly and apparently without fail in the past, our belief will 2

be quite strong that the same event, or combination of events, will again occur under the same circumstances. However, if we have a number of possible outcomes for a given situation, as with rolling a die, our expectation, or belief, in a given outcome will be considerably lower. Consider the case of the sun rising in the morning. We know from past experience that the sun rises every day, and has done so all the days of our lives that we can remember. Indeed, we know from talking the others and recorded information going back as long as history has been written, that there are no exceptions to this rule. (Even if one believes the Biblical story in Joshua 10:13, that the sun and moon stopped in the course of their movement, there is but a single exception.) Even in a single human lifetime, we may ourselves witness 28,000 such sunrises. Because of this tremendously consistent track record, we can say with nearly complete confidence that the sun will indeed rise in the morning. Because this is a future event, we cannot know for certain, but our belief is incredibly strong because we assess the probability of this event failing to happen to be quite close to zero, indeed, something like 78 365 1 99.996487% certain ( ) 1. Modern science takes a position very similar to this, 78 365 despite disagreeing with Hume on cause and effect, but science reaches its probabilistic conclusions from a slightly different source. Knowing that the sun rises because the Earth turns and our position to the sun changes, it is still possible to conceive of the sun not rising tomorrow. There may be ways to make the Earth stop turning, or in theory, to remove the Earth from the vicinity of the Sun altogether, à la Dr. Who, that would have the effect of the sun failing to rise in the morning. (Whether we would still be here in the morning to notice or care 1 I am assuming a human lifespan of 78 years, and 365 days a year, and one exception. This is a simplistic calculation, but should be sufficient for the point. A Bayesian model would probably be more appropriate for what Hume has in mind, but certainly that is beyond the scope of this paper. 3

after such a cataclysmic event as is necessary according to modern science is another matter altogether.) However, these events are incredibly unlikely, and so while the scientist might insist he knows, barring these extraordinary events, he nonetheless believes in the manner of Hume, in a strictly probabilistic sense; he just believes very strongly. In the case of believing that it will be above 80 on average in August 2010, our belief is still strong, but not as certain as our belief that the sun will rise tomorrow. For one thing, there are many fewer Augusts to draw on in our memories, even if we live here our whole lives, or even on record, from which to calculate a probability. Because of that, any single deviation from the norm will loom much larger than a single failed sunrise, long ago in the distant past. Indeed, even one August in a single lifetime that fails to average above 80 generates a probability of approximately 98.7179% ( 77 78 )2. We may also draw on our experience of other summer months in recent years where the temperature was unseasonably cool. Our beliefs in such an event, that it will average above 80 in Columbus in August, is strong enough that we may be willing to make plans based on that event, and argue for it in debate, and even, perhaps, be willing to bet money on the likelihood; however, would one be willing to stake one s life on such a belief? Our beliefs that the sun will rise tomorrow are so strong, that we probably would consider it an easy risk, with so little likelihood of failing to occur that there is no real risk at all. But for the case of a warm August, we are confident in our beliefs, but not quite so much so. In the case of Professor Shabel showing up for the final exam, if we have this belief at all, we may hold it very tentatively indeed. Since I have never had a class with Professor Shabel 2 Assuming a lifespan of 78 years, and one exception. 4

before, I don t know what her particular habit is, but even if I had seen it happen before, I might question why she would bother with two TAs to take over for her (although, for Hume, these facts are unconnected). Or, I might have seen it happen sometimes, and not other times. The deviation, then, from perfect consistency, and lacking the number of occurrences that might firmly establish the belief in my mind, causes me to hold such a belief, if I hold one at all, very tentatively. I would not be surprised greatly in either event, that Professor Shabel shows up, or if she does not, even if I conclude, ultimately, that she will. 3 This notion of how the strength of our beliefs are held in proportion to the probabilities associated with those beliefs seems to be intuitively realistic and conforms to our common sense ideas. When we are given no information about an event other than its occurrence or failure of occurrence without cause-and-effect information (since Hume believes there is no such thing) (Hume 44), and we are compelled to look at the world as a kind of black box into which we cannot peer, even the numbers themselves seem plausible. However, in a universe where cause and effect is real and knowable, even in some sense, then additional information can be used to determine probabilities associated with our beliefs because we can bring additional information to bear on a question, and to drive the probabilities in the direction of near certainty (as with the sun rising in the morning), or in the direction of uncertainty (as with having a warm August this year). It is here where Skepticism, and the Empiricism of modern 3 To get above 50% mark, one would need 3 events, two of which turned out the same. Even so, 66.6667% is not a very strong probability. 5

science, fail to meet, and it is here where Hume s conclusions about future events will seem unnecessarily tentative. 4 4 Of course, Hume will find more sympathy among those afraid to fly, since they, too, don t trust past experience nor science, and expect their plane to fall out of the sky at any minute, 6