Belief, Awareness, and Two-Dimensional Logic"

Similar documents
All They Know: A Study in Multi-Agent Autoepistemic Reasoning

A Model of Decidable Introspective Reasoning with Quantifying-In

Logical Omniscience in the Many Agent Case

SOME PROBLEMS IN REPRESENTATION OF KNOWLEDGE IN FORMAL LANGUAGES

Knowledge, Time, and the Problem of Logical Omniscience

Belief, Awareness, and Limited Reasoning: Preliminary Report

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Belief as Defeasible Knowledge

Informalizing Formal Logic

Negative Introspection Is Mysterious

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

A Judgmental Formulation of Modal Logic

Varieties of Apriority

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

G. H. von Wright Deontic Logic

Quantificational logic and empty names

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Intuitionistic Epistemic Logic

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Theories of propositions

A Defense of Contingent Logical Truths

Bayesian Probability

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

Review of "The Tarskian Turn: Deflationism and Axiomatic Truth"

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Horwich and the Liar

An Introduction to. Formal Logic. Second edition. Peter Smith, February 27, 2019

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

A Generalization of Hume s Thesis

Conditional Logics of Belief Change

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Circumscribing Inconsistency

Logic I or Moving in on the Monkey & Bananas Problem

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

A Logic of Implicit and Explicit Belief

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Verification and Validation

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

Coordination Problems

JELIA Justification Logic. Sergei Artemov. The City University of New York

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Ling 98a: The Meaning of Negation (Week 1)

CHAPTER 1 A PROPOSITIONAL THEORY OF ASSERTIVE ILLOCUTIONARY ARGUMENTS OCTOBER 2017

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

University of Reims Champagne-Ardenne (France), economics and management research center REGARDS

Evaluating Classical Identity and Its Alternatives by Tamoghna Sarkar

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

A defense of contingent logical truths

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Bob Hale: Necessary Beings

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

On the Aristotelian Square of Opposition

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Presupposition: An (un)common attitude?

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

What is a counterexample?

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

DELUSIONS OF OMNISCIENCE. Roderic A. Gide University of Auckland, Auckland, New Zealand auckland.ac.nz

Alogicforepistemictwo-dimensionalsemantics

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

Review of Philosophical Logic: An Introduction to Advanced Topics *

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

TRUTH-MAKERS AND CONVENTION T

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Pronominal, temporal and descriptive anaphora

2nd International Workshop on Argument for Agreement and Assurance (AAA 2015), Kanagawa Japan, November 2015

What are Truth-Tables and What Are They For?

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Can Negation be Defined in Terms of Incompatibility?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

Logic: A Brief Introduction

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

GROUNDING AND LOGICAL BASING PERMISSIONS

Supervaluationism and the timeless solution to the foreknowledge problem

Ethical Consistency and the Logic of Ought

TOWARDS A PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERSTANDING OF THE LOGICS OF FORMAL INCONSISTENCY

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Transcription:

Belief, Awareness, and Two-Dimensional Logic" Hu Liu and Shier Ju l Institute of Logic and Cognition Zhongshan University Guangzhou, China Abstract Belief has been formally modelled using doxastic logics in recent decades. The possible worlds model provides an intuitive semantics for these logics. But it also commits us to the problem of logical omniscience. A number of logics have been introduced to circumvent the problem. Of particular interest is the logic of awareness. In this paper we present a new method to put awareness into doxastic logic so as to get a flexible way to model actual belief. The underlying logics are two-dimensional logics. Two two-dimensional doxastic logics are given. In the first logic, a quite limited concept of actual belief is presented. In the second logic, twodimensional and classical semantics are combined into a hybrid system. and give them formal semantics by a clause: if and only if for each world / such that it holds that To complete the logic, assume that, besides propositional atoms, formulas can also be composed by means of the usual propositional connectives In order to be sure that certain properties that intuitively hold of belief are valid in this setting, some constraints should be put on the accessibility relation The standard way to do that is requiring that be serial, transitive, and Euclidean. From these constraints, three intuitive properties of belief can be captured: consistency, positive introspection, and negative introspection (they are reflected as the below axioms A5, A3, and A4 respectively). This notion of belief is completely characterized by the following sound and complete axiom system, traditionally called KD45. 1 Introduction There has been a long story in philosophy to find a suitable semantics for logics of knowledge and belief since the twentieth century. The subject was picked up by researchers in the area of artificial intelligence, in which human reasoning or resource-bounded agents reasoning is considered. The standard approach for characterizing knowledge and belief is based on the possible-worlds model. The intuitive idea, which was discovered and labelled by Hintikka [Hintikka, 1962], is that an agent considers a number of situations as possible. Under this interpretation, an agent is said to believe a fact if it is true in all the states that the agent regards as possible. Thus belief is modelled by means of accessibility relations as they are present in possible worlds models. The model is a structure M of the form where S is the set of all worlds, is the truth assignment for every atom and every world, and are the binary relations in S. On the basis of the possible worlds model a logic of belief can be devised. To this end, introduce modal operators to be interpreted as "the agent i believes that", * Authors were supported in part by the logical structure of cognition in open worlds project grant under ministry of education, China grant 20DXM720.402. 'Corresponding author. E-mail address: hssjse@zsu.edu.cn Modelling knowledge and belief of this kind yields what Hintikka called logical omniscience. Logical omniscience presupposes that an agent's beliefs are closed under logical consequence. Furthermore, valid sentences are always believed. It is clear that rational agents can never be so intelligent that they become omniscient. To avoid these undesired properties, something nonstandard is needed. In the literature there appear quite a number of drastically varying approaches. Of these, of particular interest to us is awareness logic. A number of ways of modelling awareness and actual belief have been suggested in the literature, among them we would like to refer to [Rantala, 1982], [Fagin and Halpern, 1988], [Wansing, 1990] and [Thijsse, 1996]. The main problem of logical omniscience is that it forces an agent to believe too much. Fagin and Halpern suggested a variation of the standard Kripke model [Fagin and Halpern, 1988], named the logic of general awareness (abbreviated RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING 13

GAL). The underlying idea is to use awareness as a "sieve" to remove the undesired parts of the logic. Though an agent implicitly believes a fact, the agent may not believe it explicitly if it is not aware of it. GAL distinguishes between implicit belief and explicit belief by the following equation: Explicit Belief = Implicit Belief Awareness The model is endowed with function that act as a kind of sieve, filtering out explicit beliefs from the bulk of implicit beliefs. The model is a tuple M of the form where and have their usual meanings. For each possible world (cs) is an arbitrary set of formulas of the language, indicating the formulas that the agent is aware of in s. The language contains operators. which reflect awareness, as well as the implicit belief operators and explicit belief operators The semantics of the language is as usual, except for adding two clauses for the operators and Note that the one for is not expressed recursively. The explicit beliefs are just those implicit beliefs that belong to the awareness set. The sentence A6 is valid in the model. Fagin and Halpern showed in [Fagin and Halpern, 1988] that by adding A6 to KD45, the resultant system completely characterize the semantics of GAL. GAL, despite its simplicity, is a very flexible and powerful tool. Wansing exhibited in [Wansing, 1990] that a slight generalization of GAL (Let be any binary relation in S) can characterize every modal system that contains classical logic. GAL has also some disadvantages. Useful information is neglected in this semantics. There are two reasons that commit an agent not to explicitly believe a sentence one is that the agent is not aware of the other is that the agent does not implicitly believe. GAL cannot express these different situations. Even if we know the fact that an agent does not explicitly believe a sentence, we still do not know where it comes from. In our proposal, the difference between them is able to be distinguished. In GAL, it is possible for a sentence to be true even if the agent is not aware of some parts of the sentence. For example, consider the sentence "if an agent believes that it rains, it will take an umbrella." (formalized as The sentence can be true in a world s even if the agent is not aware of anything about "rain" in s. In a different opinion of belief and awareness, it may be argue that the above sentence seems nonsensical to the agent if it does not know what the "rain" is. From that opinion, the sentence can never be simply true. We will introduce a method such that different opinions of belief and awareness can be easily modelled. It is important to distinguish between objective truth and subjective truth. It is reasonable for the above sentence to be objective true (as a truth of fact), but not subjective true (from the point of view of the agent). We leave the item aside for the moment. We will present two logics below. The first logic only concern about subjective truth. The notion will be picked up in the second logic. We use a different way to add awareness sieve to doxastic logics. What we use is two-dimensional logics. In twodimensional logics, the value of a formula ranges over the set Each member of the set is called a truth-degree. Every truth degree has two dimensions. Intuitively, the first dimension of a truth-degree, called a truth-value, represents the truth value of and the second, called an awareness-value, keeps track of the value of the awareness condition (we will clarify the notion below) of Though the logic looks like a type of four-valued logic, it is in fact two-valued. Whichever way it is read, we are still left with two-values, with 1 as true and 0 as false. We got the idea of using two-dimensional logics in this way from theoretical linguistics, where two-dimensional logics are used to give the semantic concept of presupposition [Bergmann, 1991]. Usually, the sentence exists''' is looked upon as the presupposition of the sentence We interpret "an agent is aware of exists in the agent's memory". And then we treat the sentence as the presupposition of the sentence "the agent explicitly believe Here the presupposition is indeed the existence of a denotation of in the agent's memory. We call it the awareness condition. The denotation is subjective. It denotes things in the given memory, unlike in the case of the sentence "a exists", whose usual meaning is that a has an objective denotation. Another difference between them is that the subjective denotation is a denotation of a sentence other than a denotation of a term. Two-dimensional logics allow us to calculate the truth value of a sentence and its awareness condition independently. This gives us flexibility to construct different models of actual belief. Intuitively, the awareness condition of a sentence should affect its truth value. However, it may be no agreement on what the effect should be. By amending its matrices, two-dimensional logics are flexible enough to characterize different concepts of actual belief. It is easy to see that GAL can be represented by a twodimensional logic. The only thing we need to do is to make the awareness condition of a sentence does not disturb its truth value. We would like to emphasize again that what we present in this paper is not only a more rigorous concept of actual belief than GAL's, but also a method by which different opinions to actual belief can be modelled readily. We will give two doxastic logics use two-dimensional logics in the rest of the paper. The first logic can be viewed as an example of using our method, in which a more limited concept of actual belief is presented. The second logic extend the first logic to a hybrid system. To be concise, we only consider one agent mode and use operators B,L,A substitute for respectively. It is easy to extend the results of the paper to multi-agent mode. We think many-dimensional logics may play an important role in may topics. The problems in many topics are in the following style: There are several factors that affect the outcome event's situation. To construct a logical structure of such problem, many-dimensional logics are preferred. Each factor or outcome is put in a different dimension of the truth 14 RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING

degree. In such a many-dimensional semantics, it can be clearly indicated that how the factors affect the outcome. Of course, it is an "out of focus" topic in the present paper. By the way, we got some ideas of this paper from our work on "Open Worlds". Interested readers may refer to [Shier and Hu, 21]. 2 Two-Dimensional Awareness Logics 2.1 Semantics By awareness different people can understand in quite different ways. In this section, we present a logic in which a sentence's awareness condition is considered as a very rigorous limitation to the sentence: If the awareness condition is not satisfied, then the sentence is nonsensical to the agent and is invariably false. We call the resultant logic two-dimensional awareness logic, abbreviated TDAL. The language of TDAL is the same as GAL's. A TDAL model is a tuple M =, where, S is a non-empty set of possible worlds; is a truth degree assignment function from the set of atoms to per possible world. By convention, the parentheses and commas of truth degrees are dropped; is a binary relation that is serial, transitive, and Euclidean; A is the awareness function, assigning each possible world a set of formulas. The matrices are: A AAB ~A AVB A B Notice that and can be defined from ~ and The latter two connectives are considered as primary. The truth degree conditions for the modal operators are: is satisfied in s if and only if denoted by M, 5 is valid if and only if M, f o r every model M and every possible world s, denoted by The semantics of TDAL needs some explanations. The assignment function is indeed two-valued. It assigns only two values, and, to each atom. The primary awarenessvalue is always assigned as 1. Only an occurrence of the B operator can introduce falseness as awareness-value. The reason is this: The awareness condition only makes sense when explicit belief is considered. An atom has no awareness condition at all. It is natural to assign atoms a trivial awareness-value, i.e. an always true value. It is easy to see that this definition is sound: an always true awareness-value does not disturb the calculation of truth value. This also explains the semantic definition of A and L operators, where the awareness-value of each formula of the form is always true. Awareness-value is contagious: the awareness-value of a sentence governed by one of the binary connectives is false if the awareness-value of one of its immediate components is false. If the awareness-value is always true, the truth-value is calculated classically. Clearly, TDAL is along skeptical lines. It characterizes a cautious agent: the agent deems a sentence to be true only if every propositional part of it has no uncertainty. Note that the semantics of TDAL can be reduced to a threevalued logic because the truth degree can never result, neither from logical connectives nor from modal operators. can be dropped safely from the matrices. At first sight, the resulting three-valued propositional logic looks the same as weak Kleene logic. If we substitute the truth values and for the truth degrees, and respectively, then we get the matrices of weak Kleene logic. However, the two logics are quite different. In TDAL, the assignment function is indeed two-valued, unlike Kleene's. can only result from application of the modal operator B. This characteristic makes TDAL very different than weak Kleene logic. For example, there are no propositional tautologies in weak Kleene logics, but in TDAL, some of them are preserved. 2.2 Discussion And Formalization Definition 2.1 An occurrence of a B operator in a formula is bound if that occurrence is in the scope of one of the modal operators; otherwise, such an occurrence ofb is free. A formula is bound iff each occurrence in it of B is bound, and is free iff it is not bound. Some classical tautologies are not valid in TDAL. A limitation is required in order to make them valid. Proposition 2.2 The following sentences are valid in TDAL. (A 7) all bound classical tautologies. Proof Trivial. The next proposition shows that the axioms with respect to the properties of implicit belief are all preserved in TDAL, as they should be. Proposition 2.3 A2-A5 are all valid in TDAL. Proof The proof is as usual. Intuitively, the axiom A6, which characterize explicit belief, should not hold in TDAL because we have a different view to awareness condition here. It is just the case. This is easy to see by taking a model that contains a worlds s such that the agent is not aware of in s. Instead of A6, we have RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING 15

RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING

3 Hybrid Two-Dimensional Awareness Logic 3.1 Semantics Thijsse presented in [Thijsse, 1996] a noteworthy method of modeling actual belief. His so-called hybrid system consists of an inner partial logic (within the actual belief operator) and an outer classical logic. It is implemented by distinguishing two kinds of truth relations: a bivalent truth relation, reflecting objective truth and a trivalent truth relation, reflecting subjective truth. Our proposal is to take TDAL as the inner logic, unlike Thijsse's logic, where partial logic is adopted. There is a reasonable motivation to proceed TDAL into a hybrid semantics. As has been shown, "truth" discussed in TDAL is indeed subjective truth: In TDAL, the meaning of a sentence being said to be true is that from the point of view of an agent it is true. The semantics of TDAL is reasonable only if we understand it in this way. For example, it is intuitive that A6 should be objectively true; however, from the point of view of an agent, it may not be (subjectively) true. We call the resultant logic hybrid two-dimensional awareness logic, abbreviated HTAL. Formally, a HTAL model is a Proof. The proof is by induction on the structure of are left to the reader Details It directly follows from proposition 3.1(i) that TDAL is a sub-logic of HTAL. All provable formulas of system T are valid in HTAL. The necessity rule, R2, does not hold in general in HTAL. Instead, there is a limited version. R2': from to infer where is bound. It is easy to verify that R2' is valid in HTAL. The system corresponding to the semantics of HTAL consists of all axioms of KD45 and T, R1 and R2'. Call it the system H. To prove the completeness of H, the following proposition is needed. Proposition 3.2 When checking the truth value of a formula, one starts with a two-valued evaluation and is dragged into the multi-valued mode only by the belief operators. Within the belief operators, sentence's truth value is calculated by TDAL, reflecting subjective truth. Outside belief operators, it is calculated classically, reflecting objective truth. Except adopting different logic as inner logic, there is another significant difference between HTAL and Thijssc's logic. In the latter, partiality is specified by evaluation, and does not come from the limitation to actual belief. Its "hybrid" character when taken by itself is irrelevant to an awareness condition. While in HTAL, the jumping-off point is indeed two-valued, both for inner logic and outer logic. Atoms are always assigned values classically. The non-classical aspect appears only when a belief operator occurs. 3.2 Discussion And Formalization In contrast to TDAL, where limited versions of A6 and classical tautologies are present, A6 and all classical tautologies are valid in HTAL. This is reasonable because validity in HTAL is defined as over-all classical truth, which reflects objective truth. The two truth relations are closely related. Notice that a standard canonical model of H is indeed a classical Kripke model. So to prove the completeness of, a more complicated canonical model has to be considered. The model is similar to the H-canonical model presented in [Thijsse, 1996]. The set of worlds of the model contains just one H-maximal consistent set as its root, all other worlds are maximal consistent set. The root is not accessible from other worlds. Formally, for a given H-maximal consistent set The next lemma makes clear the benefit of H-canonical model. Lemma 3.3 Let M be an H-canonical model of any formula Then for RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING 17

Proof. Since the sub-model of M obtained by restricting it to ST is just a canonical model of the system T, the proof of (i) has already been given in Theorem 2.7. The proof of (ii) is by induction on the structure of The basic steps, is an atom and are direct. Because H contains all classical tautologies, the induction step for ~ and is carried out by the standard techniques of propositional reasoning. Notice that the axioms A3-A5 are contained in all worlds of the H-canonical model. So by proposition 3.1(i), for all worlds s in M, where. Thus the relation K defined in the H-canonical model is indeed transitive, Euclidean, and serial. Theorem 3.4 System H is sound and complete for the semantics ofhtal. Proof The soundness is easy to check. To show completeness, suppose does not hold. Then there exists a H- maximal consistent set such that Construct a H- canonical model of with designated world By lemma 3.3, does not hold. 4 Conclusion Many doxastic logics have been suggested in the literature, reflecting quite different concepts of actual belief. One may wonder why there are so many proposals. Were all of us to agree on what human belief is, an "unique right" model of belief would be possible. However, it is not the case, as can be seen from philosophical controversies continuing from long ago. Thus all of the logics have their own claim to "correctness", if they have clear explanations. The method using two-dimensional logic to model awareness and actual belief has, in our opinion, particular benefits. Processing awareness condition independently gives us more flexibility in controlling the model that is constructed. Different opinions about the relation between awareness and actual belief will be reflected in different models, which can be obtained by amending the underlying two-dimensional logic. Of course, there are other, maybe many, alternatives to the logics presented in this paper. For example, it is possible to give a doxastic logic with the two-dimensional logic presented by Bergmann in [Bergmann, 1991], in which the logic is intended to be along Russellian lines. Examination of this or other forms of doxastic logics and the relations among them would call for further research. There has begun to be use of awareness logic for net protocol verification [Accorsi, 21]. We think the method presented in this paper may be useful in that purpose. This also calls for further research. 5 Acknowledgements We would like to thank Nuel Belnap for his detailed reading of the earlier version of this paper and numerous pertinent comments and criticisms. References [Accorsi, 21] R. Accorsi, D. Basin, and L. Vigano. Towards an awareness-based semantics for security protocol analysis. In Post-CAV Workshop on Logical Aspects of Cryptographic Protocol Verification, 21. [Bergmann, 1981] Bergmann, M., Only, even, and clefts in two-dimensional logic, in th Internat. Symp. Multiple-valued logic, Oklahoma 1981, Proceedings, IEEE, Long Bench, 7-123, 1981. [Bergmann, 1991] M. Bergmann. Presupposition and twodimensional logic. In Meaning and Truth: The Essential Readings in Modern Semantics, eds. Jay L. Garfield and K. Murray, New York: Paragon House, 189-2, 1991. [Fagin and Halpern, 1988] R. Fagin and J. Y. Halpern. Belief, awareness and limited reasoning. Artificial Intelligence, 34, 39-76, 1988. [Fagin and Halpern, 1995] R. Fagin, J. Y. Halpern, Y Moses and M. Y Vardi. Reasoning about Knowledge. MIT press, 1995. [Gottward, 21] S. Gottwald. A treatise on Many-valued Logic, research studies press, 21. [Hintikka, 1962] J. Hintikka. Knowledge and Belief. Cornell University Press, 1962. [Konolige, 1986] K. Konolige. What awareness isn't: a sentential view of implicit and explicit belief. In Proceedings of the First Conference on Theoretical Aspects of Reasoning about knowledge, 241-250, 1986. [Levesque, 1984] H. Levesque. Logic of implicit and explicit belief,. In Proceeding of the Fourth National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAA 184). Menlo Park, CA, 198-202, 1984. [Rantala, 1982] V. Rantala. Quantified modal logic: nonnormal worlds and propositional attitudes. Studia Logica, 41,47-67, 1982. [Shier and Hu, 21] J. Shier, L. Hu. The logical structure of open worlds.. Proceedings of 863 plan on intelligent computer. Tsinghua University Press, 21. [Thijsse, 1992] E. Thijsse. Partial Logic and Knowledge Representation. Eburon Publisher, 1992. [Thijsse, 1996] E. Thijsse. Combining partial and classic semantics: a hybrid approach to belief and awareness. In Partiality, Modality, and Nonmonotonicity, Doher(eds.), 223-249, 1996. [Wansing, 1990] H. Wansing. A general possible worlds framework for reasoning about knowledge and belief. Studia Logica, 49, 523-539, 1990. 18 RESOURCE-BOUNDED REASONING