Andrea Lavazza and Howard Robinson, eds., Contemporary Dualism: A Defense, Routledge, viii pp. ISBN

Similar documents
Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Life, Automata and the Mind-Body Problem

BEYOND CONCEPTUAL DUALISM Ontology of Consciousness, Mental Causation, and Holism in John R. Searle s Philosophy of Mind

BonJour Against Materialism. Just an intellectual bandwagon?

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Saul Kripke, Naming and Necessity

Chalmers, "Consciousness and Its Place in Nature"

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Panpsychism and the Combination Problem. Hyungrae Noh. A Thesis Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Arts

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Please remember to sign-in by scanning your badge Department of Psychiatry Grand Rounds

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? Cambridge University Press, 2006, 154pp, $22.99 (pbk), ISBN

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2018 Test 3: Answers

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

EPIPHENOMENALISM. Keith Campbell and Nicholas J.J. Smith. December Written for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Dualism: What s at stake?

Experiences Don t Sum

24.09 Minds and Machines Fall 11 HASS-D CI

Session One: Identity Theory And Why It Won t Work Marianne Talbot University of Oxford 26/27th November 2011

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Introduction to Philosophy Fall 2015 Test 3--Answers

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

BOOK REVIEWS. The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 4 (October 2002)

Bertrand Russell and the Problem of Consciousness

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

On the Prospects of Confined and Catholic Physicalism. Andreas Hüttemann

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCE DUALISM

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

William Meehan Essay on Spinoza s psychology.

Chapter 11 CHALMERS' THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS. and yet non-reductive approach to consciousness. First, we will present the hard problem

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Minds and Machines spring Hill and Nagel on the appearance of contingency, contd spring 03

Philosophy of Mind (MIND) CTY Course Syllabus

What is Physicalism? Meet Mary the Omniscient Scientist

The Mind/Body Problem

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

5 A Modal Version of the

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics. Lecture 3 Survival of Death?

ZOMBIES, EPIPHENOMENALISM, AND PERSONAL EXPLANATIONS: A TENSION IN MORELAND S ARGUMENT FROM CONSCIOUSNESS

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE SEARLE AND BUDDHISM ON THE NON-SELF SORAJ HONGLADAROM

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I

LEIBNITZ. Monadology

Realism and instrumentalism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Against the Vagueness Argument TUOMAS E. TAHKO ABSTRACT

The Alleged Hard Problem: A Pseudo Problem. Michael Prost. Fern Universität in Hagen

Reflections on the Ontological Status

THE CRISIS OF THE SCmNCES AS EXPRESSION OF THE RADICAL LIFE-CRISIS OF EUROPEAN HUMANITY

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 4 : I M M A T E R I A L I S M, D U A L I S M, & T H E M I N D - B O D Y P R O B L E M

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Is Property Dualism Better Off than Substance Dualism?

John Drury. Qualifying Exam in Philosophy for the Theology Department. May 30, 2007

Supervenience & Emergentism: A Critical Study in Philosophy of Mind. Rajakishore Nath, Indian Institute of Technology Bombay, India

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

Overcoming Cartesian Intuitions: A Defense of Type-Physicalism

Structure and essence: The keys to integrating spirituality and science

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

NEUROSCIENCE AND THE SOUL: CONTEXTUALIZED SCIENCE IN THE LIBERAL ARTS COLLEGE

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

CHRISTIANITY AND THE NATURE OF SCIENCE J.P. MORELAND

There are two explanatory gaps. Dr Tom McClelland University of Glasgow

The UCD community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters!

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Lecture 5 Philosophy of Mind: Dualism Barbara Montero On the Philosophy of the Mind

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 3 : N A T U R E O F R E A L I T Y

How Successful Is Naturalism?

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

1/8. The Third Analogy

Summary of Sensorama: A Phenomenalist Analysis of Spacetime and Its Contents

Karen Bennett Princeton University not very successful early draft, March 2005

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Subjective Consciousness: A Self-Representational Theory, by Uriah Kriegel. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp H/b 37.00, P/b

. INCONSISTENCIES IN THE ASSUMPTIONS OF CONSTRUCTIVISM AND NATURALISM: AN ALTERNATIVE VIEW 1. Nini Praetorius 2

The modal status of materialism

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Churchland(s) critique Dualism. (Paul Churchland here.)

SWINBURNE ON SUBSTANCES, PROPERTIES, AND STRUCTURES

REPLY TO BURGOS (2015)

3 The Problem of Absolute Reality

The Hard Problem of Consciousness & The Progressivism of Scientific Explanation

1/12. The A Paralogisms

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

Transcription:

Andrea Lavazza and Howard Robinson, eds., Contemporary Dualism: A Defense, Routledge, viii + 292 pp. ISBN 978-0-415-81882-7 Reviewed by Lynne Rudder Baker, University of Massachusetts Amherst This is a brave book. Dualism, the editors tell us, "has a bad reputation," and the the editors seek to revive mind-body dualism as a "progressive research programme." (Introduction 7, 5) Despite its "bad reputation" among mainstream philosophers today, dualism retains vibrancy that this book manifests. With fourteen different papers (including the introduction), the absence of a single specific thesis of dualism is not surprising. With some exceptions (e.g., Fürst 130, n.1), the authors seem to think that we all know what physicalism or materialism is, and they have various conceptions of what physicalism or materialism (allegedly) cannot explain. The collection is divided into four sections: The Limits of Materialism (Meixner, Lavazza, Lund); Dualism and Empirical Research (Manzotti and Moderato, Stapp, Fürst); Cartesian (Substance) Dualism (Swinburne, Robinson, Walker); Non-Cartesian Dualism (Taliaferro, Hasker, Skrbina, Lowe). Many of the papers have novel and thought-provoking claims and arguments. I shall discuss three at some length, and then the others more briefly. (I) One of the most intriguing papers is Neuroscience: Dualism in Disguise by Riccardo Manzotti and Paolo Moderato. Manzotti and Moderato argue that neuroscientists implicitly accept a view that they explicitly reject: dualism. They mention two assumptions of neuroscience (Manzotti & Moderato 85): 1 1

1. The mind is physical. (dualism rejected) 2. The part of the physical world which is sufficient for the mind is the brain (or some suitable proper part of the central nervous system CNS. (Neural Chauvinism) Every known neural process is such that it may occur in the absence of conscious experience. (Manzotti & Moderato 88) And even if we had a neural correlate for consciousness in general, we still would not know why a specific physical process leads to the occurrence of a specific phenomenal experience. (Manzotti & Moderato 88) From the beginning of modern science at the time of Galileo, phenomenal properties of consciousness were separated from quantitative qualities and expunged from the description of nature. (Manzotti & Moderato 89) So, neuroscience cannot tackle consciousness because the essential properties of the mind have been programmmatically and selectively set aside from the physical world. (Manzotti & Moderato 89) Some scientists turn to postulating some intermediate thing-like entity that is not exactly a physical thing but has some allure of scientific respectability like information, coding computation, maps, representations, and symbols (Manzotti & Moderato 91). However, postulation of such entities is ontologically empty: it does not add anything to the causal description of the world. (Manzotti & Moderato 92) The authors say: Consciousness is a real phenomenon. It needs to be grounded on ontologically real entities not just on epistemic entities. (Manzotti and Moderato 92-3) They argue that the grounding entities are just epistemic fictions, ontological promissory notes, that are never redeemed (Manzotti & Moderato 92). In the absence of physicalist redemption, 2 2

ontological promissory notes offer a dualistic picture of the mind-body problem. Along the way, Manzotti & Moderato discuss a number of philosophers and neuroscientists: Descartes, Melzack, Haynes, Haggard, Kentrick/Nasclaris/Gallant, Noë. A skeletal version of the argument for dualism, as I understand it, goes like this: Consciousness is a real phenomenon that requires a real physical basis assumed to be in the CNS; but no physical basis is found in the CNS, so an intermediate thing-like entity (symbols, information, etc.) is postulated by scientists. But the intermediate entity is only an epistemic entity that makes no difference in the physical world and hence cannot provide the physical basis of consciousness. Manzotti and Moderato conclude that there are only two options for neuroscience: reject the assumption that the physical basis of the conscious mind has to be internal to the CNS or explicitly accept dualism. (97) Although their argument ends with the disjunction either CNS or dualism what Manzotti and Moderato really want to argue for is dualism. Dualism follows only with the addition of nontrivial assumptions: that there is no physical basis at all (internal or external to the CNS), and that consciousness is a real phenomenon. The skeletal version, as I would amend it, is this: 1. Consciousness is a real phenomenon. (empirical premise) 2. If consciousness is a real phenomenon and dualism is false, then consciousness has a physical basis. (conceptual truth, given physicalism) 3. Consciousness has no physical basis (either internal or external to the CNS). (empirical investigation) 3 3

4. Either consciousness is not a real phenomenon or dualism is true. (2,3 MT) 5. Dualism is true. (1,4 DS) This argument is valid. Even so, its soundness may be questioned: One may, with Dennett, reject premise one that consciousness is a real phenomenon. (Rejecting premise one seems eminently implausible to me, but not to many physicalists.) Or, more plausibly I think, one may reject premise two, and hold instead that consciousness is real and dualism is false, and yet consciousness has no physical basis. (Taking a physical basis to be some specific physical configuration, I would reject premise two.) I do not know whether Manzotti and Moderato would accept my version of their argument, but it has the merit of be formally valid, and perhaps sound. (II) Another thought-provoking paper is Henry P. Stapp s Quantum Theory of Mind. Stapp is a quantum physicist at Berkeley. He argues that orthodox quantum mechanics as formulated by Von Neumann in 1932 should be interpreted as describing causal connections between our minds and their associated quantum physically-described brains. (Stapp 102) The theory can be consistently interpreted as describing a reality that has mental and physical aspects, with the mental aspects not determined by the physical ones. (Stapp102) The uninformed reader (as I am) would benefit from further explanation. For example, Stapp says that free choices are logically required by the theory in order to break a symmetry and allow our perceptions to have the character that they actually possess, rather than being continuous smears of possible experiences of the kind that actually populate our streams of consciousness. (Stapp 102) I would like to know what kind of 4 4

symmetry free choices break, and how these undetermined free choices accomplish the symmetry-breaking. Stapp says that quantum theory concerns empirically validated connections between the quantum mechanical description of atoms and certain happenings in our streams of conscious experience. (Stapp 99) Stapp uses this to show how quantum mechanics requires action-at-a-distance, which is inconsistent with classical mechanics. He also has a fascinating argument against interpreting Benjamin Libet s famous experiments as showing that the brain is in control of our bodily motions and that our decisions to move are merely side effects of what the brain has already done. (Stapp 109-111). I found this discussion very useful. Let me conclude with some questions about Stapp s notion of free choice or free will : Is the idea of free choice really the best interpretation of the mathematical formalism? Would interpreting the formalism as random event work just as well? Is free choice as used in the interpretation of quantum mechanics the same phenomenon as free will used by libertarians? (I ask this because free choice is exercised in a highly specific and constrained setting in Stapp s interpretation of quantum mechanics hardly in the broad way that libertarians take to be a requirement of moral responsibility.) These questions leave me wondering about the extent to which Stapp s view of quantum mechanics really supports dualism. (III) One of the most intriguing papers in the collection is EJ Lowe s Why My Body Is Not Me: The Unity Argument for Emergent Self-Body Dualism. Taking a self or person 5 5

(Lowe uses the terms interchangeably) to be a self-reflecting subject of thought, Lowe asks what is the fundamental ontological category of a self or person? After arguing that thoughts are partly individuated (Lowe, 248) by their subjects, Lowe sets out what he calls the unity argument, the conclusion of which is this: [A]ll and only my thoughts have just one thing, me, as their unique subject. Furthermore...all of these thoughts depend upon me for their very existence. (Lowe 251) So, all and only my thoughts depend upon me for their very existence. (Lowe 252) So, we now have a crucial test for something s being identical with me: X is identical with me if and only if X is such that all of my thoughts depend upon it and, indeed, that no thought of mine depends [anything not identical with X]. (Lowe 259) Lowe came up with a general argument to show that no bodily thing neither entire animal, nor brain, nor part of a brain, nor system (like the CNS) nor part of a system can be identical with me. The reason is that the way that thoughts depend on, say, the brain is different from the way that they depend on me. My thoughts depend in a distributive fashion on various different overlapping parts of my brain, but this not they way that they depend on me, their subject. Rather, they all depend collectively on me, such that were I to cease to exist, then so would they each and every one of them. (Lowe 260) This structural difference between the way that my thoughts depend on my brain (or any other bodily thing) and the way that they depend on me guarantees that no bodily thing can be identical with me. So, what fundamentally am I? I am just a self or person a subject of thought and agent of actions. (Lowe 260) In this case, we seem to have self or person as a basic ontological category. But then Lowe goes on to argue, from 6 6

the fact that persons are distinct from and irreducible to bodies and bodily systems, to dualism of person and body. (Lowe 261) Lowe makes his dualism as palatable as possible to nondualists: He leaves it open whether mental properties can only be exemplified at all if they are co-exemplified with suitable physical properties and he acknowledges strong arguments for the causal autonomy of selves or persons. (Lowe 261) However, Lowe s argument, as clever as it is, does not lead to dualism without a further assumption namely that distinctness of person and body suffice for dualism. If you think that there is a relevant kind of unity other than identity, you may applaud Lowe up until he opts for dualism of self or person and body. Now I shall try to suggest, all-too-briefly, the flavors of the other papers in the volume and point to aspects that struck me as notable: (1) Martina Fürst, in A Dualist Account of Phenomenal Concepts, is very well-versed in the relevant literature of arguments concerning physicalism that are based on the phenomenal character of consciousness, and she is a careful writer. Focusing on Jackson s well-known knowledge argument, Fürst gives a fine survey of physicalists efforts to explain away anti-physicalist conclusions; then she gives an account of the formation and cognitive role of phenomenal concepts, and finally, she argues that phenomenal concepts have the explanatory power to imply non-physical referents. (Fürst 121) Fürst s own account of phenomenal concepts is similar to the physicalists up to a point, but is crucially different in a way that becomes a clever argument against physicalism. The article is noteworthy for its clarity and argumentative detail. 7 7

(2) Andrea Lavazza s argument in Problems of Physicalism Regarding the Mental, although difficult, points out the implications for physicalism of the tension between the necessity of logical laws and the contingency of the way that the human brain is wired. The argument involving discussions of Davidson, Kant and Kripke is quite complex. If logical laws are necessary, the conclusion, as I understand it, is that we must admit the existence of some type of Fregean Platonism, which is incompatible with strong physicalism. (Lavazza 49) If I am anywhere near the mark, Lavazza s argument is new to the literature. (3) In Materialism, Dualism, and the Conscious Self, David Lund sees occurrent consciousness to be the obstacle to nondualism. He surveys several forms of materialism and finds them all lacking (as do I). He goes on to say: Given the constraints of the materialist framework, what such terms as awareness or consciousness may seem to pick out must in the end be seen either as a linguistically generated illusion, and thus eliminable, or as reducible to behavioral dispositions perhaps in conjunction with states of the non-dispositional base (i.e., brain states). (Lund 67) Like Lund, I think (and have argued extensively) that consciousness experience is neither reducible nor eliminable; nevertheless, I think that his statement in the previous paragraph falters on a narrow conception of materialism: Why can t occurrent consciousness simply have evolved slowly over many species, ending with us? If our world came to be inhabited by conscious beings by natural evolution, why couldn t we be material things? After all, dogs are subjects of conscious experiences, and dogs are material things, aren t they? 8 8

(4) Uwe Meixner s Against Physicalism takes physicalism to be the thesis that Every non-abstract individual is completely physical (Meixner 17), where physicalism is taken to be the token-identity theory. (Meixner 19) Unlike some physicalists and nonphysicalists alike, Meixner explicitly rejects the construal of physicalism in terms of dependence of the mental on the physical (or supervenience). Meixner has a battery of arguments against our being completely physical. (Interestingly, the token-identity theory plays no role in Meixner s arguments.) Agreeing that properties are abstract entities, I wonder: Does having properties essentially make an otherwise physical object not completely physical? In particular, if I am made up wholly of physical particles, but I have certain properties essentially (roughly, my view), am I not completely physical? I d like to know more. (5) Richard Swinburne s paper defending substance dualism has an intriguing title, What Makes Me Me? and I wish more philosophers would ask and answer this question. Swinburne s answer to the question is that my soul, which has its own thisness, different from the thisness of anything else. We persons, says Swinburne, are pure mental substances, who can exist logically independently of physical substances. (Swinburne 150) A point on which I think that Swinburne is right is this: What makes me me is not any of my qualitative properties: not my mental life, and not my bodily life. (6) Howard Robinson in Naturalism and the Unavoidability of the Cartesian Perspective quotes Dennett on the unavoidability of the intentional stance. Robinson takes the inevitability of the intentional stance to be the inevitability of the Cartesian perspective on oneself, the unavoidability of the thought, I think therefore I am. (Robinson 156) Then he argues that this Cartesian perspective is not consistent with 9 9

physicalism and any kind of naturalism. In addition to discussing Dennett, Robinson discusses, at least briefly, an interesting array of contemporary philosophers: Kim, Loewer, Fodor, Davidson, Quine; then at greater length, McDowell, Price, Rorty. However, along the way the focus changes from the Cartesian point of view, which is first-personal, to the point of view of the special sciences and the human level (which is third-personal). (Robinson168) Since the special sciences are formulated in the third person, there seems to be an interesting and important slide in the argument. (7) In On What We Must Think, Ralph C.S. Walker starts with the Kantian view that rational beings must... think of themselves as capable of being moved by reason itself, and not always reacting to causal forces. (Walker 172) Walker argues that we must think of ourselves as able to respond to the demands of reason, and that, if so, we need not take seriously the mere logical possibility that we are under an illusion. (Walker 179) This, he says, establishes that we are indeed capable of thinking and acting in response to our awareness of rational principles, and that therefore there is something importantly nonphysical about our minds. (Walker 173) Walker goes on to argue further that the mind is a non-physical substance, as Descartes argued. Indeed, we must think of ourselves as subjects of experience, as persisting (immaterial) selves. This is too hasty. Although I lack room for an argument here, let me say just this: To be committed to think of oneself, as Walker holds, as a subject that thinks or as being able to think and act in response to reason (Walker 187) does not commit one to think of oneself as non-physical. 10 10

(8) In The Promise and Sensibility of Integrative Dualism by Charles Taliaferro tries to meet three challenges of physicalists: (i) their belief in the primacy of the physical and the third-person point of view; (ii) their belief that dualism involves a radical bifurcation; and (iii) their charge that there can be no dualist causal interaction. Taliaferro argues for the primacy of the mental (against (i)), the functional unity of the embodied person (against (ii)), and a recommendation to reverse standard approaches to mental-physical interaction by beginning with the mental (against (iii)). One intriguing theme of dualists, including Taliaferro, is that, without dualism, a person in particular a neuroscientist cannot understand her own actions when she is conducting research on the brain. On my view, the problem of understanding what one is doing is solved by reference to the robust first-person perspective without reference to two kinds of entities at all. (9) In The Dialectic of Soul and Body, William Hasker looks first to Thomas Aquinas and then to J.P. Moreland for accounts of the soul-body relation. Both are ultimately found wanting. Hasker presents his own view of emergent dualism, according to which the soul develops naturally from the structure and functioning of the organism. (Hasker 215) His view escapes the difficulties in Aquinas s and Moreland s accounts. In particular, it does not court vitalism, nor does it posit immutable natural kinds of living creatures; Hasker s view thus has the virtue of being ready to be incorporated into an evolutionary story. (Hasker 216) The dialectic of soul and body is neatly developed. (10) David Skrbina, in Dualism, Dual-Aspectism, and the Mind, urges us to do justice to the ideas of both mind and body, ideas that he says have been in play since the 11 11

Egyptians around 2350 BCE. Skrbina proposes what he calls dual-aspectism that describes a monist reality in terms of two distinct aspects, mental and physical, that have equal standing. (Skrbina 228) Skrbina takes it that there is the mind-body problem, (my emphasis) to be found throughout the history of philosophy. He finds variations on the theme of dual-aspectism in the thought of many figures throughout history, almost all of whom were panpsychists or at least strongly sympathetic to it. (Skrbina 238) He suggests that panpsychism may be our best hope for resolving some of our most-long standing philosophical problems. (Skrbina 238) However, when Skrbina presents his version of dual-aspectism, the panpsychism fades into parallelism. He takes matter-mind as the monistic reality, in which there is a one-to-one matching of all physical states and all mental states. (Skrbina 239) However, since parallelism is compatible with occasionalism, but panpsychism is no, parallelism and panpsychism are not compatible positions. Or so it would seem. To conclude, overall these papers exhibit a forceful battery of arguments for various kinds of dualism. Some of the papers here are not as clearly or succinctly written as they should be. (I found the Introduction difficult to follow.) Some papers are repetitious. Other papers, however, e.g., Uwe Meixner s, are clear and straightforward, and therefore, easy (even exciting) to contend with. In the current intellectual climate, where physicalism and naturalism hold sway, it is useful to have a volume that surveys a number of contemporary dualistic positions, and this book is a good start. 12 12