JAMES CAIN. wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting. or several distinct members into one body, is performed merely by

Similar documents
Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Summer Preparation Work

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

The Cosmological Argument

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Hardback?18.00 ISBN

The cosmological argument (continued)

A note on Bishop s analysis of the causal argument for physicalism.

Kant and his Successors

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Definitions of Gods of Descartes and Locke

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

5 A Modal Version of the

Cosmological Arguments

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

DO WE NEED A THEORY OF METAPHYSICAL COMPOSITION?

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Cosmological Arguments

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

The Kalam Cosmological Argument provides no support for theism

Is God Good By Definition?

THE RELATION BETWEEN THE GENERAL MAXIM OF CAUSALITY AND THE PRINCIPLE OF UNIFORMITY IN HUME S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

5 Cosmological Arguments

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Cosmological Argument, Sufficient Reason, and Why-Questions

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

A Reply to New Zeno. appeared in Analysis v.60, #2 (April 2000) S. Yablo

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

1. What is Philosophy?

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

Monday, September 26, The Cosmological Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

SWINBURNE ON THE SIMPLICITY OF THEISM

E L O G O S ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY/2008 ISSN Tracks in the Woods. F.A. Hayek s Philosophy of History.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

MATHEMATICAL ANTINOMIES.

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

IN THIS PAPER I will examine and criticize the arguments David

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

Copan, P. and P. Moser, eds., The Rationality of Theism, London: Routledge, 2003, pp.xi+292

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Intersubstitutivity Principles and the Generalization Function of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. Shawn Standefer University of Melbourne

The Cosmological Argument

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011


Maximality and Microphysical Supervenience

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

The Cosmological Argument

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

The Mind/Body Problem

Treatise I,iii,14: Hume offers an account of all five causes: matter, form, efficient, exemplary, and final cause.

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Christian Evidences. The Verification of Biblical Christianity, Part 2. CA312 LESSON 06 of 12

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

Religion and Science: The Emerging Relationship Part II

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Ultimate Naturalistic Causal Explanations

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

Confirmation Gary Hardegree Department of Philosophy University of Massachusetts Amherst, MA 01003

Transcription:

Rel. Stud. 31, pp. 323-328. Copyright? 1995 Cambridge University Press JAMES CAIN THE HUME-EDWARDS PRINCIPLE In such a chain too, or succession of objects, each part is caused by that which preceded it, and causes that which succeeds it. Where then is the difficulty? But the WHOLE, you say, wants a cause. I answer, that the uniting se parts into a whole, like the uniting of several distinct counties into one kingdom, or several distinct members into one body, is performed merely by an arbitrary act mind, and has no influence on the nature of things. Did I show you the causes particular of each individual in a collection of twenty particles of matter, I should think it very unreasonable, should you afterwards ask me, what was the cause whole twenty. This is sufficiently explained in explaining the cause parts. (David Hume1) The demand to find the cause series as a whole rests on the erroneous assumption that the series is something over and above the members of which it is composed_ If we have explained the individual members there is nothing ad? ditional left to be explained. (Paul Edwards2) In discussions cosmological argument for the existence of God, in particular the Leibniz-Clarke versions argument, the following gen? eral methodological principle governing causal is sometimes put forward : HEP: Given a collection of parts which jointly compose a whole, an which assigns a cause to each se parts provides a causal whole. I call this the Hume-Edwards Principle and abbreviate it as 'HEP', though it is perhaps somewhat broader ranging than the principle expounded in the above quotations from Hume and Edwards. We might usefully consider two more specific forms of HEP. First we might restrict consideration to cases in which the parts that make up the wholes are individuals. Call this restricted principle HEP(i). Alteratively, we might restrict consideration to cases where the parts are events. Call this principle HEP(e). Hume and Edwards seem to have HEP(i) in mind in the above quotations. HEP is intended to apply to cases in which the number of parts under consideration is either finite or infinite. In particular, Hume and Edwards argue that if a changing universe has always existed and what exists at any given time is caused by what previously existed, then it is mistaken to ask for a cause existence whole enduring process which extends infinitely - into the past at least this is a mistake if it is a request for a cause outside 1 Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, part ix. 2 'A Critique Cosmological Argument', in Louis P. Pojman (ed.), Philosophy of Religion: an Anthology (Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1987), p. 16; originally published Rationalist Annual for the Tear ig^g. in The

324 JAMES CAIN the process, for by giving causes parts a causal whole has already been given. HEP, of course, has had its detractors.3 A good example is Swinburne's discussion above passage from Hume. (Swinburne uses the term 'full cause of E" to refer to 'a set of factors which together were sufficient for the occurrence of...event i?.'4) One principle which might be proposed in this connection is that a cause occurrence of a collection of states is any collection causes of each. More a particularly, full cause occurrence of a collection of states is any collection of full causes of each. This principle clearly holds for any finite set of effects, where none causes of any member collection of effects is itself a member collection of effects... However, the principle must be modified if it is to take account of cases where the cause of some member of a collection of effects is itself a member of that collection. For when b is the cause of a, and c is the cause of b, we say that the cause of a + b is c, not b + c.5 ' Swinburne proceeds to modify the principle to say, a (full) cause occurrence of a collection of states, is any collection of (full) causes of each, whose states as they cause are not members former collection.'6 With this modified principle, Hume's contention that an causes parts of a whole will an provide cause whole will work (for full causes) in cases where there are a finite number of parts (at least if we grant that causation cannot go 'in a circle'7), for then the collection of causes for the parts must provide us with a subcollection outside the whole which will then explain the whole. But if there are an infinite number of parts, an of each part may not provide a causal whole ; in particular it will not if each part is explained by the causal activity of other parts functioning within the whole. Though I am rather sympathetic to Swinburne's line of thought here, I suspect that most people who initially support HEP (in either form) probably are not. I will attempt to show, by another line of reasoning, that there are grounds for holding that HEP (in both forms) fails to provide us with an intuitively obvious a priori methodological principle governing causal expla? nation. I will not try to show that it is in fact false, for, as was suggested above, if it turned out - by luck, so - to speak that there is not an infinity of effects, HEP might well come out true. We will begin by looking at HEP (e). Let's imagine that an explosion takes place. This event, E, consists rapid expansion of some material over an interval of time. Suppose that someone supplies the following of E. (Note that in assessing the 3 See William L. Rowe, 'Two Criticisms Cosmological Argument', The Monist, vol. 54, no. 3 (1970), and Chapter 3 of The Cosmological Argument (Princeton University Press, 1973). See also Chapter 7 of Richard Swinburne, The Existence of God (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992). 4 5 6 Ibid. p. 24. Ibid. p. 123. Ibid. p. 124. 7 ' For a discussion cosmological argument in which the supposition that causation cannot go in a circle' is abandoned, see Robin Le Poidevin, 'Creation in a Closed Universe Or, Have Physicists Disproved the Existence of God?', Religious Studies 27 (March 1991 ), pp. 39-48.

THE HUME-EDWARDS PRINCIPLE I will not be concerned with whether it an provides empirically adequate in the sense that it would stand up to criticisms levelled by chemists or physicists. Rather I will be concerned with what we are to make of it in light of HEP (e).) The interval of time (whose end points we will arbitrarily label o and 1 ) over which E took place is the open-closed interval of time (o, i].8 Now this interval is the union of all open-closed intervals (a, b], such that o < a < b ^ 1. For any such interval (a, b] in (o, 1], there is an earlier interval (c, d] in (o, 1], (where o<c<d^a<b^ 1). Let us consider a particular sequence of such intervals, sx, s2, s3,..., where s? = (1/2, i], s2 = (1/4,1/2], s3 = (1/8, 1/4], etc. (o, 1] is the union se ^'s. Let ei be the part explosion which took place over the interval sv We can see that each part explosion ei+1 caused the next part explosion ei as follows_ Here follows an of how ei+1 caused ei which we leave out. I see no a priori reason why each ei+1 should not have caused eiy and so find nothing incoherent in this part account. Let us see how HEP(e) applies here. Note that even if we accepted the above account we might still ask the? question, What if anything brought about explosion??' HEP (e), however, tells us that this question is confused to the extent that it asks for an whole, E, that cannot be satisfactorily given merely by providing s parts, i.e. the ^'s. But surely this is an un? warranted restriction set down by HEP (e). Just as each ^'s is a process which is a part of a larger process, the explosion E, so it may well be the case that E itself is a part of an even larger continuous process (one in which, perhaps, the chemicals that exploded were first heated). And just as each of the??'s was caused by something outside of itself, so E may have an outside cause (the heating chemicals). The above causal s?i's fail to provide a cause for E's occurrence. It is perfectly reasonable to ask what, if anything, caused E to occur; in doing so we are asking for a cause whole (the sum e^s) which is not given in giving the above causes parts (the e^s). In saying this I am not saying that E must have been caused by something outside itself, I am only claiming that (1) we can reasonably ask whether E had a cause, and (2) a cause for E will not be provided by the s e^s in terms of previous ^'s. There may of course be problems in the account explosion sketched out above. Perhaps time is not infinitely divisible; perhaps events do not take place over open-closed intervals of time, and so on. Here I am not concerned to argue out the nature of time, rather my point is that if one is to defend HEP(e) as an a priori principle to be used in assessing calls for causal s, then one ought to be able to show on a priori grounds that these sorts of presuppositions of my example are really untenable. I do not think this is a trivial task, and so think that one would be hard pressed to defend HEP (e) as an intuitively obvious a priori principle. 8 By the open-closed interval of time (o, i], I mean all the moments of time after time o and up to and including time i, i.e. {t\o < t < i}. 325

326 JAMES CAIN We have been looking at HEP(e). Let us turn to HEP(i), which perhaps us presents with a more case. complicated We can set out examples par? alleling our explosion example where now instead of having a succession of parts of an event we have a succession of objects. Imagine that you leave your desk for a minute and are surprised to find a ball on it when you return. You are curious about this ball and its causal history. You make inquiries and someone provides the following causal. Note that nothing will hinge upon the correctness or even the plausibility proposed ; our concern will rather be with how we evaluate the in terms of HEP (i). The begins: Call your ball B0. We believe that there have previously existed an infinite succession of balls, B1,B2,B3,B4^? B0 was caused by B1; Bx was caused by B2, B2 by B3, Here follows an account, which we will leave out, causal mechanisms by which each ball was caused by its predecessor. The is worth our attention however: etc. following part A feature surprising succession of balls Bx, B2, Bz,... is that it only existed during the span of one minute. Our hypothesis is that Bx existed for 1/2 minute before B0; B2 existed 1/4 minute before B1; B3 existed 1/8 minute before B2, etc. That is, letting t be the instant of time one minute before B0 began to exist, for each n > 0, ball Bn existed from t+ (1/2)11 minutes until /+ (i/2)n_1 minutes. Thus none balls existed until after t, and the entire sequence of balls Bl9B2,B3...only existed until the moment, t+ 1, that to B0 began exist. This hypothesis, startling as it might be, appears at first glance to be consistent. What reaction might one have who did not simply dismiss the hypothesis? Let B be the whole succession of balls, B0,B1,B2,BS,_I think that one first questions the hypothesis raises is 'What, if anything, made B come into existence?' Of course in asking this we are asking for a cause not given in the above causal s i^'s. Note that I am not claiming here that B could not come into existence uncaused. I am only claiming that a causal question would arise as to whether B had a cause, and this causal question could not be answered by explaining the causes parts of B (the B^s) as was done above. But if HEP (i) were correct, this would be a confusion: a causal individual i^'s would give a causal whole. I said earlier that I thought HEP (i) might present a more complicated case than HEP (e). Here is why. It seems easy to conceive how a continuous process (as in our explosion example) can be part of a larger continuous process and can be brought about by an earlier part larger process.9 But, in the case of a succession of objects with no first member, it may be 9 Take, for example, high school physics problems where we are asked to determine the path a projectile will take over an interval of time given its previous trajectory and the gravitational forces involved. Here a process taking place over one time interval is seen to be causally explicable in terms of an earlier process. Here too we are comfortable with treating a process taking place over an interval of time, like the falling of a body, as being decomposable into subprocesses of arbitrarily small size.

THE HUME-EDWARDS PRINCIPLE harder to fathom how there can be an outside cause whole. After all, we do not generally think in terms re being an infinite succession of objects over a finite time span (as opposed to there being infinitely many subintervals in a finite interval). And if there could be an infinite succession of objects over a finite time, like the B?s, it is perhaps more difficult to see how it could have an outside cause. Call a succession of objects self-contained iff it is an infinite succession of objects containing no first (i.e. unpreceded) member and in it each member is caused by one or more preceding members. If we could rule out a priori either the existence of an infinite succession of objects over a finite span of time or an outside cause for a self-contained succession of individuals, then HEP (i) would be immune to my objection. I will 327 present a prima facie case for holding that these cannot be ruled out a priori. I begin by noting that sometimes individuals are on supervenient pro? cesses. An example will indicate what I have in mind here. We can imagine someone investigating chemical processes taking place on the sea floor. One might investigate a very complex process in which molecules are constructed, broken down, spatially arranged, etc. This investigation could be carried out ' ' without recognizing the macroscopic features environment at the level of biological organisms. It might later be noticed that some complex continuous chemical process (involving the construction and interaction of proteins, lipids, nucleotides, etc.) in fact constituted the generation of, let us say, one sea anemone from another by budding. Here the existence of certain individuals, as well as the generation of one individual from the other, is on supervenient the chemical process.10 I have already suggested that there is no a priori reason to rule out there being a process, P, such that ( i ) P takes place over a finite interval of time, (2) P is infinitely subdividable into subprocesses P1,P2,P3,..., where Pi+1 precedes P?, (3) each Pi is caused by Pi+1, and (4) P itself has an outside cause, C. I suggest further that it is not to be ruled out a priori that a self-contained infinite succession, S, of individuals,?l3 S2, S3,... (Si caused by Si+1), might be supervenient on just such a process, P, where each Si in S is supervenient on the subprocess Pv If that were to be the case then the self-contained succession of individuals, S, would have an outside cause, namely C, the outside cause of P. But then HEP (i) cannot be defended from my example on the basis of a supposed incoherence in either the notion of an externally caused self contained succession of objects or the notion of an infinite succession of objects spanning a finite length of time. Thus I think we should not accept HEP in either form as an intuitively obvious a - priori principle that is, we should not accept it unless it is bolstered with a priori arguments which show that the sorts of cases I have sketched out are impossible. 10 I am assuming for the argument that sea anemones do not have an immaterial part. Also, I am not claiming that all individuals are supervenient on processes.

Before ending 328 JAMES CAIN I will say something about how this relates to the cosmo? logical argument. There is a feature explosion, E, and the succession of objects, B, that makes it natural to raise the questions 'What made E happen?' and 'What caused B to exist?', namely E and B are things that came into existence. These questions lead us to a more general metaphysical question : If there were actually to be such infinite successions as E and B were hypothesized to be, would they have to be caused? They would have to be if the following is correct : can come Nothing into existence unless it is caused. Whether this is a correct metaphysical principle is a perhaps tough question, but it is one that needs to be addressed freed from extraneous problems raised by HEP. Now let us turn to the Leibniz-Clarke version cosmological argu? ment. Basically it says that even if this universe has existed forever and even if what happens at one time can be explained in terms of what happened previously, the universe as a whole is nonetheless something contingent and nothing contingent can exist uncaused. Here we have two principles at work: can Nothing contingent exist unless it is caused. The universe as a whole is contingent. Whether or not these are true is again a tough problem, but they need to be investigated apart from confusions arising from HEP.11 Department University Louisville, of Philosophy, of Louisville, Kentucky 40292 11 And Hume does independently address these claims in the very section Dialogue in which we find HEP propounded.