David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002)

Similar documents

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

By J. Alexander Rutherford. Part one sets the roles, relationships, and begins the discussion with a consideration

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.


Theory of Knowledge. 5. That which can be asserted without evidence can be dismissed without evidence. (Christopher Hitchens). Do you agree?

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.


In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

The CopernicanRevolution

Hume, Probability, Lotteries and Miracles Bruce Langtry Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)



Commentary on Professor Tweyman's 'Hume on Evil' Pheroze S. Wadia Hume Studies Volume XIII, Number 1 (April, 1987)


The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

A Hobbist Tory: Johnson on Hume Paul Russell Hume Studies Volume XVI, Number 1 (April, 1990)

Platonic Idealism: Too High a Standard for Political Activity. As I have re-read Plato s Republic, and read for the first time Eric Voegelin s

Critique of Cosmological Argument

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

Ayer and Quine on the a priori


A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

Philosophy of Religion: Hume on Natural Religion. Phil 255 Dr Christian Coseru Wednesday, April 12

Rethinking Knowledge: The Heuristic View

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

1.6 Validity and Truth

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Inconsistency within a Reconciling Project Antony Flew Hume Studies Volume IV, Number 1 (April, 1978), 1-6.

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

The Paranormal, Miracles and David Hume

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Chapter 6. Fate. (F) Fatalism is the belief that whatever happens is unavoidable. (55)

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Welcome back to week 2 of this edition of 5pm Church Together.

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

David Hume ( ) and His Attack on Divine Action (Miracles) and Providence: From Empiricism to Skepticism and Naturalism

SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Part III SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY? David Tin Win α & Thandee Kywe β. Abstract

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

PHIL 155: The Scientific Method, Part 1: Naïve Inductivism. January 14, 2013

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

Varieties of Apriority

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

Writing Your Doctoral Thesis with Word This document is an example of what you can do with the POLITO Template

Of Skepticism with Regard to the Senses. David Hume

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophical Review.

1/12. The A Paralogisms

The British Empiricism

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

2013 Pearson Education, Inc. All rights reserved. 1

Chapter 2--How Do I Know Whether God Exists?

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Hume, the New Hume, and Causal Connections Ken Levy Hume Studies Volume XXVI, Number 1 (April, 2000)

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

The Quality of Mercy is Not Strained: Justice and Mercy in Proslogion 9-11

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Outline. The Resurrection Considered. Edwin Chong. Broader context Theistic arguments The resurrection Counter-arguments Craig-Edwards debate

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

Aquinas s Third Way Keith Burgess-Jackson 24 September 2017

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Does God exist? The argument from miracles

Hume s Critique of Miracles

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Task 1: Philosophical Questions. Question 1: To what extent do you shape your own destiny, and how much is down to fate?

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

The God Delusion by Richard Dawkins. Who Is Richard Dawkins and Why Is He Saying All Those Bad Things About Us?

The God Delusion by Richard Dawkins

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

The Power of Critical Thinking Why it matters How it works

Time, Self and Mind (ATS1835) Introduc;on to Philosophy B Semester 2, Dr Ron Gallagher Week 5: Can Machines Think?

We [now turn to the question] of the existence of God. By God I shall understand a

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

ECONOMETRIC METHODOLOGY AND THE STATUS OF ECONOMICS. Cormac O Dea. Junior Sophister

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

Transcription:

David O Connor. Hume on Religion H. O. Mounce Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 2 (November, 2002) 309-313. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.humesociety.org/hs/about/terms.html. HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the HUME STUDIES archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Each copy of any part of a HUME STUDIES transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. For more information on HUME STUDIES contact humestudies-info@humesociety.org http://www.humesociety.org/hs/

Hume Studies Volume 28, Number 2, November 2002, pp. 309 313 Book Reviews DAVID O CONNOR. Hume on Religion. London: Routledge, 2001, Pp. xvi + 227. ISBN 0415201942, cloth, $75.00; ISBN 0415201950, paper, $15.95. This book is a commentary on the Dialogues concerning Natural Religion, Hume s most famous work in the field of religion. O Connor is a fine expositor, commanding a clear and readable style. The Dialogues is covered in detail, so that students will gain a good sense of the structure. The weakness lies in O Connor s attitude as it inevitably appears in his exposition. I do not mean that this is wild or eccentric. Quite the contrary, it is the one which during the last fifty years has become conventional, reflecting the empiricist tradition one associates with Ayer and Flew. For example, O Connor hardly questions Hume s distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, implies indeed that he puts it to devastating use, though it is now widely criticized even by philosophers otherwise sympathetic to Hume. One wonders whether students need another version, however well expressed, of views already so familiar. If their intelligences are to be sharpened, they surely need to encounter some serious criticism not simply of Hume s opponents but of Hume himself. Having that in mind, let us consider what O Connor calls evidentialism, an assumption he treats as lying behind Hume s thought (9). This he explains as the view that we should proportion our beliefs to the evidence. The trouble with this formulation, however, is that it is ambiguous, being platitudinous in Volume 28, Number 2, November 2002

310 BOOK REVIEWS one sense and dubious in the other. It is platitudinous that one is not entitled to ignore evidence where that is required. No one has denied it. What has been denied is that every belief requires evidence in the implied sense. The reason is that it leads to an infinite regress. If every belief requires evidence, any belief advanced as evidence itself requires evidence and so on ad infinitum. In short, no belief can ever be justified. If any belief is justified, some beliefs must be fundamental, in the sense of not resting on further evidence. It is obvious, however, that fundamental beliefs are various and sometimes conflict. Such a conflict cannot be settled by reference to other beliefs more fundamental, for there are no such beliefs. It does not follow that all reasoning is at an end. But the reasoning must be dialectical rather than foundational. One can proceed only by considering whether there are difficulties or inconsistencies in one position which are avoided in the other, or, supposing difficulties in both, which are the greater. The relevance of the above points to the philosophy of religion should be obvious. The religious and the non-religious do not hold differing beliefs within a common system. They hold different views of the world. The difference between them is itself an instance of fundamental conflict. It follows that a serious study of religion is possible only to those who can occupy in thought both a religious and a non-religious view. It is impossible for those who cannot imagine that the other side may have an answer to difficulties that arise on their own. No one can be delivered from a false system by further reasoning based on the same system but only by having the imagination to conceive how that system may appear when viewed from another. The procedure, in short, must be dialectical not foundational. That, however, is very far from the procedure we find, during the last fifty years, in the philosophy of religion. The procedure, rather, is to consider whether there are difficulties in religion and then to dismiss it when they appear substantial. It is not thought necessary to consider whether on the other side there are difficulties as great or even greater. Indeed worse; the reasoning is precisely foundational not dialectical, the foundational view being the non-religious one. In short, religion is justified only if it can be deduced from the opposing view. A classic example of this fallacious procedure may be found in Hume s Essay on Miracles. His aim is to show that no miracle can serve as the basis for a religion. His argument is that a miracle is contrary to common experience. But it is common experience which determines what is reasonable to believe. What, however, if there is strong testimony that an event has occurred which would be deemed improbable when judged by common experience? Hume acknowledges that this is conceivable but argues that we still should Hume Studies

BOOK REVIEWS 311 not accept the miracle. That is because the weight of the testimony is at least equally balanced by the improbability of the event itself. Notice that this argument works only if at no point are we allowed to appeal to religious considerations themselves. Suppose, as is conceivable, that we are torn between the weight of testimony and the improbability of the event. On the non-religious side, there is no clear way to resolve the conflict. But on the religious side, there is no conflict to resolve. If miracles are real, precisely what we should expect on some occasions is strong testimony in favor of an event which would be deemed improbable when judged simply by common experience. On such an occasion, the assumption of a miracle would be reasonable not simply for the religious but for the hitherto non-religious. Indeed so fallacious is Hume s procedure that it would exclude not simply miracles but any fundamental advance in the sciences. Take the conflict in astronomy between the Ptolemaic and the Copernican systems. The central claim of the Copernican system, when judged by the Ptolemaic, is wildly improbable. Consequently, for one who holds the Ptolemaic, whatever is advanced in favour of the Copernican will always be at least equally balanced by the improbability of its central claim. Given Hume s procedure, one who holds the Ptolemaic will never have reason to accept the Copernican. Procedures comparably fallacious run through the Dialogues. For Hume, reasoning is exhausted by its deductive and inductive forms. In the former, we may infer only what is already contained in our premises; in the latter, we generalize from experience. The inductive in fact is only a looser form of the deductive. As in the deductive we can infer only what is contained in our premises, so in the inductive, we can infer only what is contained in our experience. Thus, we can infer rain from dark clouds only because we have already experienced instances of dark clouds and rain. With these criteria in place, it is unnecessary even to consider any argument in natural theology. We may reject such an argument not because we have found it fallacious, when considered independently, but because it is excluded beforehand by our criteria. The arguments in natural theology seek to show that this world does not explain itself but may be explained only by what transcends it. It is therefore essential to natural theology that there should be principles of explanation which transcend their data. These are excluded by Hume s criteria. For him, an explanation must be inferred from what its data already contain. The inadequacy of these criteria will be evident to those who apply them impartially. Thus applied, for example, they will lay waste to the theoretical sciences. No theory in the sciences can simply be derived from its data, whether by strict deduction or generalization. Every theory thus transcends Volume 28, Number 2, November 2002

312 BOOK REVIEWS its data. Throughout the theoretical sciences it is only so far as we transcend in some measure what we seek to explain that we can in fact explain it. The chief fault in O Connor s book is that he does not examine the central weaknesses in Hume s approach. But there are others. In the main, they seem to me to reflect the fallacies or prejudices of our secular culture. Here are some examples. On page 7, the Scottish Calvinists are inevitably characterized as exhibiting a grim joylessness. The Calvinists no doubt had their faults, though in that they are hardly exceptional. But they were neither trivial nor foolish. Calvinism itself is one of the great formative movements in European history. For example, the Scottish tradition in philosophy, which is of the highest distinction, is evidently indebted to it. Indeed Hume s view of reason, as we find it in the Treatise, it itself indebted to Calvinism. On page 21, we are told that Darwin s theory of evolution by natural selection shows that nature is self-ordering. Perhaps this is loosely expressed. In any case, as it stands it is plainly false. Natural selection cannot explain natural order, for without natural order there would be nothing to select. It may explain why it is a creature with such and such features rather than some other which has survived. But it cannot be explained why it had those features in the first place. We may illustrate the point. The explanation why basketball players tend to be over six feet tall is that in basketball one tends to select only players of that height. But the explanation for their being that height is not that it gets them selected for basketball. They must already be that height before they get selected. We may note that although students who take philosophy invariably treat Darwin s theory as infallible truth they rarely have a precise idea of what it involves. The idea that natural selection explains natural order is in fact one of their commonest delusions. In Hume s work there figures a distinction between God s existence, which can be known with certainty, and his nature, which is unknowable. The distinction is a standard one in traditional theology. O Connor says it is incoherent, since we cannot know an object exists unless we can characterize it. But it is not incoherent, since an object may be characterized other than through its nature. For example, we may characterize it through its relations or consequences. The point will be evident to those who have studied traditional theology but it should be equally evident to those who have studied modern physics. For example, the electron is characterized through various models which were we to apply them to its nature would involve us in contradiction. Philosophy has been valued for its ability to criticize conventional pieties or orthodoxies. In our age, the orthodoxy, at least in academic circles, is Hume Studies

BOOK REVIEWS 313 certainly not religious. We find it rather in scientism and secularism, those being effortlessly acquired by so many of our colleagues. In that respect students will do well to study Hume s Dialogues, so long as they do it in a critical spirit. For it is this work as much as any in the last fifty years which has been used to reinforce that orthodoxy. H. O. MOUNCE Department of Philosophy University of Wales Swansea Singleton Park Swansea SA2 8PP, Wales Volume 28, Number 2, November 2002