BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Similar documents
Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity Robert Merrihew Adams

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

DISCUSSION - McGINN ON NON-EXISTENT OBJECTS AND REDUCING MODALITY

On possibly nonexistent propositions

1. Introduction. Against GMR: The Incredulous Stare (Lewis 1986: 133 5).

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

IN his paper, 'Does Tense Logic Rest Upon a Mistake?' (to appear

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

What God Could Have Made

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

Postmodal Metaphysics

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

A note on science and essentialism

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Varieties of Apriority

Replies to Glick, Hanks, and Magidor

Unnecessary Existents. Joshua Spencer University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Vagueness and supervaluations

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Metaphysical Necessity: Understanding, Truth and Epistemology

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Maudlin s Truth and Paradox Hartry Field

Time travel and the open future

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

On David Chalmers's The Conscious Mind

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Horwich and the Liar

Principles of Plenitude (1986) Our chief concern is with actuality, with the way the world is. But inquiry into the actual may

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Postscript to Plenitude of Possible Structures (2016)

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

PHILLIP BRICKER. (Received 7 June 1996)

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Critical Study of Michael Jubien, Ontology, Modality, and the Fallacy of Reference

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

ACTUALISM AND THISNESS*

Temporary Intrinsics and the Problem of Alienation

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

Why Counterpart Theory and Three-Dimensionalism are Incompatible. Suppose that God creates ex nihilo a bronze statue of a

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Williams on Supervaluationism and Logical Revisionism

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Modal Realism, Still At Your Convenience

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

Privilege in the Construction Industry. Shamik Dasgupta Draft of February 2018

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Possibility and Necessity

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Leibniz and Krikpe on Trans-World Identity

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

Scope Fallacies and the "Decisive Objection" Against Endurance

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Boghossian s Implicit Definition Template

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Transcription:

manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best student will not be satisfied by anything less than full development and defense of views endorsed by teacher or author, in which case Aune's two objectives will converge. In view of the problems cited above, I am afraid that in such a setting this book will leave Aune (or his apologist) many hard questions to answer. Duke University MICHAEL FEREJOHN The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) THE METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY. By GRAEME FORBES. New York, N.Y., The Clarendon Press of Oxford University Press, 1985. Pp. x, 257. Forbes's book covers a wide range of topical issues in the metaphysics of modality. The book is well written, well informed, and interesting throughout. Although I have serious reservations about the soundness of some of Forbes's positions, I have learned much from reading the book, and I recommend it to anyone with an interest in the field. The first three chapters cover largely familiar terrain: possible-world semantics for propositional and first-order modal logic, the de relde dicto distinction, and the problem of transworld identity. Forbes's generally lucid exposition and judicious choice of topics make this material suitable for an introductory course in modal metaphysics. Chapter 3 contains a modified counterpart theory designed to invalidate the sentence, "everything necessarily exists." (On Lewis's theory, the natural translation of this sentence is a theorem.) To this end, Forbes stipulates that at worlds where an object has no existent counterparts, it nonetheless has a non-existent counterpart: the object itself. This has the desired result, but at a cost: it undermines the explanatory role of the semantics. Any such stipulation seems to conflict with Forbes's requirement that the semantics explain validity and invalidity (pp. 70-76).' Chapter 4 contains an interesting, although inconclusive, defense of anti-realism with respect to possible worlds. Forbes's anti-realism requires 'For further discussion of Forbes's counterpart theory, see David Lewis, On the Plurality of Worlds (New York, N.Y.: Basil Blackwell, 1986), pp. 8-13. 127

that all possible-worlds discourse worth preserving can be translated into a modal language that lacks explicit quantification over worlds (p. 80). I can mention only one problem here. By narrowly focusing upon a single use of possible worlds-the explanation of validity for S5 modal logic- Forbes has failed to take into account the full costs of rejecting possible worlds. Many of the uses to which possible worlds have been put will escape translation into Forbes's modal language, even allowing the controversial enhancements to the language that Forbes suggests.2 Chapters 5 and 7 contain, respectively, useful developments of modal set theory and a semantics of vagueness. Chapter 9, the final chapter, contains an interesting, although sketchy, discussion of the source of knowledge of necessary truths. Forbes holds that such knowledge arises entirely from the a priori analysis of concepts. He argues, correctly, that such a view need not conflate metaphysical and epistemological notions. But I cannot agree with Forbes's claim that knowledge of necessary truths arises solely from the analysis of non-modal concepts (p. 131). Such knowledge is based in part upon a priori principles of modal plenitude, principles that do not arise from the analysis of non-modal concepts alone. The heart of Forbes's book, Chapters 5 through 7, contains an evaluation of essentialist theses about sets, organisms, and artifacts. These chapters are marked by bold metaphysical theses; but also, I think, by arguments that are unconvincing or incomplete, and by a failure to face squarely implausible consequences of the view put forth. In presenting Forbes's view, I first focus upon worlds that branch from the actual world, where two worlds branch from one another if they "have some initial segment of their courses of history in common" (p. 151). On Forbes's account, sets and organisms are treated alike: a set or an organism can exist at two branching worlds, even if it exists in part after the time of branching; de re modal assertions about sets or organisms are interpreted according to Kripkean semantics with transworld identity; sets and organisms have non-trivial individual essences that determine necessary and sufficient conditions for transworld identity. An artifact, on the other hand, exists at two worlds only if the worlds branch and it exists entirely before the time of branching; de re modal assertions about artifacts are interpreted according to a counterpart theory with degrees of counterparthood; artifacts have fuzzy essences that determine fuzzy sets of counterparts. Why are organisms classified with sets, rather than with artifacts? Forbes holds that sets existing at different worlds are identical if and only if they have the same members. This cannot be justified, he argues, unless 2For a survey of some of the uses to which possible worlds have been put, see David Lewis, op. cit., pp. 5-69. 128

one assumes that the transworld identity of sets is in some sense grounded, and that intrinsic features of sets do the grounding. That seems right for sets. He then elevates this into a universal demand: all identity judgments must be intrinsically grounded. This demand, he claims, can be used to establish non-trivial necessary and sufficient conditions for the transworld identity of organisms. Forbes incautiously asserts that all identity judgments must be intrinsically grounded (pp. 140-145), although he provides no idea how this demand could be universally met without incurring a vicious circle or infinite regress. I focus only upon the relevant weaker claim, that all transworld identity judgments must be intrinsically grounded. By "grounded," Forbes apparently means grounded in qualitative features of worlds. In particular, Forbes holds that if a exists at world w, and w is qualitatively identical with world v, then a exists at v. (Compare Case 1, p. 128.) Forbes thus rejects a version of Haecceitism according to which "each individual [has] a primitive identity or thisness," and holds instead that "non-trivial conditions sufficient for transworld identity can be given" (p. 148). When Forbes adds that transworld identities must be intrinsically grounded, he apparently asserts that whether a existing at w is identical with b existing at v depends only upon intrinsic qualitative features of a at w and b at v. (Note that an object has intrinsic features only relative to a world, lest questions of intrinsic features presuppose questions of transworld identity.) In particular, Forbes holds (A) if b and c at v are qualitative duplicates, that is, have all their intrinsic qualitative features in common, and a at w exists in part after w and v branch, then a at w is identical with neither b nor c at v. (Compare Case 2, pp. 128-129.) Forbes also seems to hold (B) if a at w and b at v are qualitative duplicates, then a is identical with b. If this is Forbes's view, there is trouble. (A), together with the use of genuine transworld identity in evaluating de re assertions about organisms, requires that the following de re sentence be false for any organism a that has no qualitative duplicate: "a could have existed and had a qualitative duplicate." That seems wrong. The problem results from Forbes's unlikely mixture of anti-haecceitism with genuine transworld identity. Neither the Haecceitist with genuine transworld identity nor the anti-haecceitist with counterpart theory has any difficulty accounting for the truth of the sentence.3 There is worse trouble. (B) requires that the following de dicto sentence be false for any object a that has no qualitative duplicate: "There could have existed two qualitative duplicates of a." For if this sentence were true, 3In special cases, the anti-haecceitist solution will require that there be distinct possibilities for a within a single possible world. See David Lewis, op. cit., pp. 227-235. 129

(B) would require that a be identical with two objects not identical with each other. This result, I think, is intolerable, and a reductio of Forbes's position. It is tantamount to accepting the necessity of the identity of indiscernibles in its strongest, least plausible, form.4 Does Forbes really hold (B) as well as (A)? Consider Forbes's main argument for the essentiality of origin with respect to organisms that come from "propagules" (pp. 138-140). (A propagule is an "organic antecedent," such as a zygote or acorn, that "directs the development of an organism.") Forbes argues that it is essential to any such organism to come from the propagule from which it actually came. His argument has us consider an oak tree at the actual world, w*, that comes from an acorn c, and a world w at which no oak tree comes from c but at which an oak tree (almost) indistinguishable from the actual oak tree except with respect to origin comes from a different acorn c'. Suppose, contrary to the essentiality of origin, that the tree in w is the actual tree. Forbes claims this is inconsistent with the demand that identity judgments be intrinsically grounded. For consider a world u at which c' produces a tree intrinsically indistinguishable from the c'-tree in w, and at which c also produces a tree. According to Forbes, any answer to the question-which, if any, of the two trees in u is identical to the actual tree?-must posit ungrounded identities. The first part of his argument goes as follows: Suppose... the c-tree in u is the actual tree. Then, since the trees in u are distinct, the c'-tree in u is not the actual tree, and so the c'-tree in u is not the same tree as the c'-tree in w, which.. Zis the actual tree. But there is no difference whatever between these c'-trees... Hence [the supposition requires] a transworld numerical difference where there is nothing [intrinsic] in virtue of which this difference obtains (p. 139). Here, and at later stages as well, the argument clearly rests upon (B). That, I think, is ample reason to reject the argument. Even if one did not reject (B), the argument would fail by proving too much. If 'oak tree' is everywhere replaced by 'snow crystal' and 'acorn' by 'condensation nucleus' (that is, dust particle, etc.), the argument demonstrates the implausible thesis that it is essential to ariy snow crystal to have condensed around the nucleus that it actually did.5 Forbes would presum- 4For an anti-haecceitist position that is not committed even to weak forms of the identity of indiscernibles, see David Lewis, op. cit., pp. 220-227. Lewis does not reject haeccez'ties, non-qualitative properties of "thisness." 51ndeed, Forbes's argument is a fleshed-out version of a much-discussed argument of Saul Kripke's designed to prove the essentiality of origin for material objects; see Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1980), n. 56. Of course, Kripke would not accept Forbes's way of fleshing the argument out. 130

ably block the snow crystal argument by invoking counterpart theory: the actual snow crystal could have come from a different nucleus than it did in virtue of having an appropriate counterpart at another world w. The identity between the snow crystal in w and the actual snow crystal need not be accepted, and the argument cannot get off the ground. But, in the same way, the counterpart theorist can block the argument as applied to organisms. Forbes needs to argue that counterpart theory is illegitimate when applied to organisms, though perfectly legitimate in other cases. This he does not do. He claims only that counterpart theory need not be applied to organisms because organisms, unlike artifacts (and snow crystals?), are not susceptible to modal sorites such as Chisholm's paradox (p. 190). But is this claim true? It requires that if a single gene of my zygote had mutated, then I would not have existed. That seems wrong. Forbes has offered no convincing reason for analyzing modal assertions about organisms one way and modal assertions about artifacts another. What about worlds that do not branch from the actual world? Forbes seems to think that the demand to ground transworld-identity judgments will require that non-branching worlds never have objects in common (except in special cases involving "separable" courses of events) (p. 151). This follows from the assumption that transworld-identity judgments must ultimately be grounded in intraworld-identity judgments. But this notion of grounding is quite different from the anti-haecceitist notion considered above. Assuming Forbes accepts (B), these two notions conflict rather badly: they jointly require that if w and v are non-branching worlds, then a at w and b at v are never qualitative duplicates (except for the special case), and that is wrong. Moreover, the branching constraint on transworld identity is implausible in its own right if de re assertions are analyzed in terms of transworld identity. It requires, for example, that the matter of this world could not have been differently arranged throughout the entire past. Indeed, it seems to require that if anything different had happened to one of my ancestors before the time I came into existence, then I would not have existed. Any theory with these consequences has failed to capture our ordinary ways of thinking about modality. Yale University PHILLIP BRICKER 131