Probability: A Philosophical Introduction Mind, Vol July 2006 Mind Association 2006

Similar documents
Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

what makes reasons sufficient?

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Skepticism and Internalism

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Degrees of Belief II

Many Minds are No Worse than One

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Varieties of Apriority

How to Mistake a Trivial Fact About Probability For a. Substantive Fact About Justified Belief

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Reliabilism: Holistic or Simple?

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Is God Good By Definition?

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

FREE ACTS AND CHANCE: WHY THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT FAILS


McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

What Should We Believe?

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

Aboutness and Justification

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Introduction. September 30, 2011

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

5 A Modal Version of the

MAKING A METAPHYSICS FOR NATURE. Alexander Bird, Nature s Metaphysics: Laws and Properties. Oxford: Clarendon, Pp. xiv PB.

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Free Acts and Chance: Why the Rollback Argument Fails Lara Buchak, UC Berkeley

1 Why should you care about metametaphysics?

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason


The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Markie, Speckles, and Classical Foundationalism

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

PARFIT'S MISTAKEN METAETHICS Michael Smith

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

Bayesian Probability

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Realism and instrumentalism

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Comments on Lasersohn

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Williamson on Knowledge, by Patrick Greenough and Duncan Pritchard (eds). Oxford and New

A Priori Bootstrapping

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Evidential Support and Instrumental Rationality

Recursive Tracking versus Process Reliabilism

Review of Erik J. Wielenberg: Robust Ethics: The Metaphysics and Epistemology of Godless Normative Realism

Learning is a Risky Business. Wayne C. Myrvold Department of Philosophy The University of Western Ontario

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

What is a counterexample?

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

A Scientific Realism-Based Probabilistic Approach to Popper's Problem of Confirmation

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

(Appeared in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 40, August 2009, pp ).

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Understanding and its Relation to Knowledge Christoph Baumberger, ETH Zurich & University of Zurich

Transcription:

Book Reviews 773 ited degree of toleration (p. 190), since people in the real world often see their opponents views as unjustified. Rawls offers us an account of liberalism that explains why we should tolerate people even when we are certain their views are false or unjustified this seems to me to be a great virtue, one that Long s relativist approach lacks. Politics University of Manchester Oxford Road Manchester, M13 9PL UK doi:10.1093/mind/fzl769 jonathan quong Probability: A Philosophical Introduction, by D. H. Mellor. London and New York: Routledge, 2005. Pp. xi + 152. H/b 55.00, P/b 16.99. The philosophy of probability is a hot field, at least if the number of new introductory textbooks is any indication including the present volume, at least five have emerged in recent years (I am thinking of books by Richard Jeffrey, Ian Hacking, Donald Gillies and Maria Carla Galavotti). With such competition, any new volume must not only serve the purposes of an introduction, giving the canonical positions in the field, but must do so in an original and distinctive fashion. D. H. Mellor s Probability: A Philosophical Introduction rises to this difficult challenge admirably. It is philosophically the best of this recent crop of textbooks, by quite a way. But as it also serves to further Mellor s own position in the debate, it has much interest in its own right beyond its role as a textbook. As an introduction the book is thorough, though in places quite compressed. Mellor spends the first five chapters covering the main philosophical accounts of probability: classical, frequency, chance, and credence. He then covers a selection of further topics: confirmation theory, conditionalisation, the relation of credences to traditional epistemology, Bayesianism, and statistical inference. Mellor s slender book makes no claims to exhaustiveness in its coverage of these topics, and though seasoned probabilists may wish to see more on their favoured issues, as a philosophical introduction it is hard to fault. Indeed, in its emphasis on more strictly philosophical concerns, Mellor s book provides a welcome change from other introductions which seemingly regard probability as an issue in philosophy of science and foundations of statistics alone. But since the book is largely about how to give a philosophical account of probabilities, chances, and credences, and not about probability theory, readers hoping to learn the mechanics of statistical inference or confirmation theory should look elsewhere (as should those readers looking for detailed information about the history and development of the various theo-

774 Book Reviews ries of probability, as Mellor s book is almost exclusively focused on conceptual issues). Readers who think that an introduction must be an unbiased survey are advised to look elsewhere too: Mellor expresses firm opinions about the untenability of a purely epistemic probability, and about various problems for a pure (Bayesian) subjectivism about probability, and he defends a propensity theory that remains broadly along the lines of his earlier work (especially his The Matter of Chance, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971). But he is admirably evenhanded in his treatment of each position he addresses, and he is explicit about the motivations and arguments for and against his preferred position. The merits of Mellor s approach are clearly displayed in his discussion of the frequency theory (chapter three). Rather than simply laying out the various rival theories of probability as if they arose as independent responses to the mathematical calculus, Mellor situates all the theories as proposing answers to the fundamental question: in what sense do probabilities measure possibilities? If we adopt a Humean view of possibility, that p is possible iff p sometimes happens, then the frequency theory answers the fundamental question by connecting how possible p is with how frequently p occurs (p. 38). This simple move by Mellor casts the frequency theory in a quite new light. Rather than appearing to be a confusion of our evidence for chances with chances themselves, frequencies emerge as the best surrogate for genuine chances that this Humean account of the modalities can entertain. When the modal locutions appearing in the probability axioms are read in the Humean way (for instance, reading Pr(S) = 1 as necessary truths always occur ), the (actual) frequency theory turns out to validate the axioms of probability. This constitutes, Mellor argues, a Humean theory of chance, which fits well with Humean approaches to other natural necessities in causation and in laws of nature (pp. 35 7). As I read him, Mellor develops three problems for this frequency view. The first problem is that there are probabilistic laws of nature, but no single case chances (since every probability is a probability of an outcome type in a sequence of outcomes, not a token). Mellor points out that this leads to quite curious probabilistic laws, which unlike their universally quantified non-probabilistic counterparts have to take the form f(gx Fx) = p (p. 38). (Strangely, Mellor does not force the point home by questioning the modal status of probabilistic laws themselves: for it will not be always true that the frequency of Gs in the class of Fs will be p, and hence the laws can have no Humean or any other kind of necessity.) Regardless, Mellor pushes on to the second worry, which is that actual finite frequencies cannot be sufficient to deal with infinite reference classes (which exist, given the infinite divisibility of temporal durations). The normal response, to appeal to limiting frequencies, must be recognised as appealing to an additional fact over and above the available empirical facts: that such a limit exists (p. 41). The third problem is the most severe: as I construe him, Mellor points out that probabilities have modal properties that

Book Reviews 775 cannot be given a Humean reading (pp. 42 3). If we consider a fair coin that is tossed just once, the frequency is either 1 or 0. But because the coin is fair, the probability is not identical to the frequency. It is, perhaps, identical to what the frequency would have been: but this would have been cannot be a Humean modality, because at no actual time does the coin get tossed again. Other authors have observed this tension between frequencies and modality (notably Alan Hájek, Mises Redux -Redux: Fifteen Arguments Against Finite Frequentism, Erkenntnis 45, 1997, pp. 209 227), but amongst textbook authors only Mellor recognises the force of this objection. I hope this has been sufficient to show the merits of Mellor s discussion: starting with a simple and philosophically well motivated assumption about probabilities, we get an elegant rationale for the frequency theory and we also see the problems for that theory emerge from its own internal structure in a straightforward way. As with frequencies, so with most of the other familiar topics that Mellor deals with: recast in a striking framework and discussed with a minimum of fuss and a maximum of philosophical punch. In some ways, however, the book shows its qualities best when dealing with unfamiliar topics. This is in part because after reading Mellor one wonders why those topics haven t been seen as central to the philosophy of probability before. In particular, the chapters on the relationship of probability and modality (chapter four), and on the justification of prior credences (chapter eight) are extremely suggestive philosophically, and provide ample justification, if any were needed, for philosophical attention to these topics. Leading on from the discussion of frequencies, Mellor asks: what could explain hypothetical limiting relative frequencies, if a Humean theory cannot? Mellor s answer is that it is real dispositional properties of chance trials to produce certain frequencies that ground this modal claim propensities (pp. 49 50). These dispositions cannot be reduced to (counterfactual) conditionals about the trials, for that would make the explanation of the frequencies circular; Mellor therefore is a realist (anti-reductionist) about dispositions (pp. 51 2). Nevertheless, Mellor does think that dispositions supervene on non-modal intrinsic categorical natural properties (p. 53). This move allows probability to be compatible with determinism (p. 55), in much the same way as frequencies are compatible with determinism: many sets of categorical properties F ground propensities, and as long as F doesn t exhaust the properties than an object has, F can give rise to non-trivial probabilities even in deterministic situations. Several worries arise at this point; I will mention two (for others, see my Twenty-One Arguments Against Propensity Analyses of Probability, Erkenntnis 60, 2004, pp. 371 416). Firstly, if a given object can have more than one propensity, as Mellor seems to allow in his discussion of determinism, then which of these propensities governs the hypothetical frequencies? If there are to be single case chances, there must be a privileged propensity; but I strongly suspect that this privileged propensity s having a non-trivial value will turn out to be incompatible with determinism, contrary to Mellor s claims. Secondly, if

776 Book Reviews propensities are themselves non-modal, how can they support the hypothetical frequencies? For it is possible that a chance device might have the same intrinsic categorical properties, hence the same propensities, and yet the outcome frequencies it gives rise to are quite different because of extrinsic factors. Although these factors are held fixed, and thus neutralized, at the nearest possible worlds, the worlds that support hypothetical limit frequencies are worlds with infinitely long sequences of outcomes. These worlds are quite unlike our own finite world, and so are not among the nearest worlds we have therefore no guarantee that the limit frequencies will come out correctly. Mellor proposes propensities to explain the connection between modality and chance, an important yet strangely neglected topic, and obviously of great philosophical import. Even though I do not think propensities are an adequate solution, Mellor is one of very few philosophers of probability to actually come to grips with the issue. Much of what he says is of considerable interest even separated from the discussion of propensities, particularly the illuminating yet brief discussion of chance and necessity (pp. 58 62). It would be wonderful if, thanks to Mellor, this explicitly philosophical topic were to be given a more central role in discussion of probability. Mellor also discusses more mainstream philosophical concerns in chapter eight, discussing the relations between credences and traditional epistemology. He develops a reliabilist theory of the justification of credences: as reliable perception justifies full belief, perceived frequencies justify credences by giving them a high enough chance of being close enough to the corresponding chances (pp. 107 8). This is not a Bayesian position, not only because of the role that chances play, but also because it demands that credences be justified before they can play a useful epistemic role. Again, though we should be grateful to Mellor for raising this topic to greater prominence, I think his position is problematic, from the perspectives of both probabilistic and traditional epistemologies. From a probabilistic perspective (quite apart from problems with pure externalism elsewhere in epistemology) Mellor s theory seems to slide from reliable perception of frequencies (a straightforward reliabilism) to frequencies reliably indicating the values of chances, which seems to address the quite different issue of inverse inference from frequencies to chances. From a traditional perspective, Mellor s view that full belief is credence at or very close to 1 (p. 101) is quite problematic. It is quite improbable that we demand unrevisability for beliefs, yet maximal credences are unable to be lowered by conditioning. If we drop to a lower threshold, we get problems with conjunction: p and q may have high enough credence, and thus be believed, while p & q may fall below the threshold yet we think full belief is closed under conjunction (see Mark Kaplan, Decision Theory as Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, chapters three to four). As we have come to expect, Mellor s writing is very clear, and a model of concision. He gives the main positions with a maximum of content and a minimum of distracting digression. Mellor s book requires little of the reader in

Book Reviews 777 terms of mathematical sophistication, but is quite demanding philosophically. The argument is dense in places perhaps too dense for the book to be used, unsupplemented, as a textbook in most undergraduate classes. The book might have been better subtitled a philosopher s introduction, because it is ideal for professional philosophers and graduate students who wish to find out what might be philosophically interesting about probability. I obviously have doubts about some of the claims Mellor defends; but I have no doubt about the importance and value of this book to the philosophy of probability. Exeter College University of Oxford Oxford, OX1 3DP UK antony.eagle@philosophy.oxford.ac.uk doi:10.1093/mind/fzl773 antony eagle Understanding People: Normativity and Rationalizing Explanation, by Alan Millar. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004. Pp Xvi + 262, H/b 40.00. Millar s aim is to defend the truth and compatibility of two propositions. First, that psychological explanations that rationalize the actions or states of mind they explain can be, and often are, causal. And second, that such explanations are often normative. To do this he has to provide a clear version of the muchthrown-around concept of normativity. He does this admirably: his reconstruction of what philosophers mean when they say that attributions of states of mind have a normative component is wonderfully unmysterious. And given this reconstruction the compatibility with causal explanation is convincing. I am less convinced that Millar is discussing a single phenomenon that we can usefully call normativity. The central idea is that of a commitment. A person in believing something commits herself to believing things that follow from it. In intending something she commits herself to intending means to it, and in wanting something to considering means to it. The normative aspect to commitment depends on the person s attitude to her own state: in believing something she must take herself to be committed to going along with its consequences, or withdrawing her belief. It does not follow that she ought to believe the consequences, since the belief may have been a foolish one in the first place, but as long as the person holds onto it she has put herself under the conditional obligation to give it up or accept what follows from it. To ascribe a belief to oneself or to someone else is to link up with practices of reasoning and attribution that require us to regulate our states of mind in accordance with its norms. If you deny the obvious consequences of your beliefs people will take you to be insincere; if you fail to take obvious means to ends that you want people will take you to be deceiving