To tell the truth about conditionals

Similar documents
Conditionals IV: Is Modus Ponens Valid?

Correct Beliefs as to What One Believes: A Note

Some questions about Adams conditionals

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

The myth of the categorical counterfactual

Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. Guido Melchior. Philosophia Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN

A Defence of the Ramsey Test

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Questioning Contextualism Brian Weatherson, Cornell University references etc incomplete

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

What God Could Have Made

Philosophy of Mind. Introduction to the Mind-Body Problem

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Phil 413: Problem set #1

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

A Priori Bootstrapping

Is it rational to have faith? Looking for new evidence, Good s Theorem, and Risk Aversion. Lara Buchak UC Berkeley

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

What should I believe? What should I believe when people disagree with me?

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

From: Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (2005)

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

The unity of the normative

Chapter Seven The Structure of Arguments

Inductive inference is. Rules of Detachment? A Little Survey of Induction

Jeffrey, Richard, Subjective Probability: The Real Thing, Cambridge University Press, 2004, 140 pp, $21.99 (pbk), ISBN

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Comments on "Lying with Conditionals" by Roy Sorensen

Contradictory Information Can Be Better than Nothing The Example of the Two Firemen

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Morgenbesser cases and closet determinism

WHAT IF BIZET AND VERDI HAD BEEN COMPATRIOTS?

SENSE-DATA G. E. Moore

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

Evidential arguments from evil

10 CERTAINTY G.E. MOORE: SELECTED WRITINGS

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

BEAT THE (BACKWARD) CLOCK 1

Reply to Robert Koons

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL?

History and the Christian Faith Contributed by Michael Gleghorn

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

THERE S NOTHING TO BEAT A BACKWARD CLOCK: A REJOINDER TO ADAMS, BARKER AND CLARKE

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

History and the Christian Faith

what makes reasons sufficient?

The Philosopher s World Cup

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

On Truth At Jeffrey C. King Rutgers University

THE BELIEF IN GOD AND IMMORTALITY A Psychological, Anthropological and Statistical Study

COACHING THE BASICS: WHAT IS AN ARGUMENT?

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

Hume s Law Violated? Rik Peels. The Journal of Value Inquiry ISSN J Value Inquiry DOI /s

The midterm will be held in class two weeks from today, on Thursday, October 9. It will be worth 20% of your grade.

Knowledge and Authority

Conditionals, Predicates and Probability

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Let s Bite the Bullet on Deontological Epistemic Justification: A Response to Robert Lockie 1 Rik Peels, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam.

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

Scientific Realism and Empiricism

Rational dilemmas. Graham Priest

Epistemic Freedom HUMANITIES

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

Comments on Lasersohn

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

CONDITIONAL PROPOSITIONS AND CONDITIONAL ASSERTIONS

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Different kinds of naturalistic explanations of linguistic behaviour

The Moral Evil Demons. Ralph Wedgwood

The Zygote Argument remixed

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Philosophy 1100 Introduction to Ethics

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

1. My thesis: the conditionals of deliberation are indicatives

A Puzzle About Stalnaker s Hypothesis

Mill and the Footnote on Davies

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Gettiering Goldman. I. Introduction. Kenneth Stalkfleet. Stance Volume

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

They were all accompanied outside the house, from that moment on nobody entered again.

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Lecture 1 The Concept of Inductive Probability

Transcription:

To tell the truth about conditionals Vann McGee If two people are arguing If p, will q? and both are in doubt as to p, Ramsey tells us, 1 they are adding p hypothetically to their stock of knowledge, and arguing on that basis about q; so that, in a sense If p, q and If p, ~q are contradictories. We can say they are fixing their degrees of belief in q given p. Ramsey s observation has proven so accurate that it has become the standard account of when English speakers are willing to assert or accept an indicative conditional; but it is not, I am sorry to report, unfailingly reliable. The counterexample, developed at length below, is a conditional If p, then q that we are willing to assert on the basis of the testimony of someone we regard as a highly reliable authority. Learning p would, however, sufficiently undermine our confidence in the authority that we would no longer have grounds for believing either the conditional or its consequent. So even though If p then q is assertable, the posterior probability that q would have once we learned that p, and hence our present conditional probability of q given p, is low. Unfortunately, the details are elaborate, so I must ask your indulgence as I set the example up. On the old TV game show To Tell the Truth, on the last game of each show, a well-known celebrity would appear as a contestant. Along with him were two other contestants, who pretended to be the celebrity. The celebrity guest was sworn, to the best of his ability, always to tell the truth, whereas the other two contestants were free to answer questions any way they liked. The aim of the game was to determine, by skilful questioning, which of the three contestants was the celebrity Let me tell you about a particular episode of To Tell the Truth in which the celebrity guest was none other than the illustrious detective Sherlock Holmes. Holmes appearance on the show happened at a time when there was widespread public discussion of a criminal case with which Holmes was intimately involved. A certain Rutherford Murdoch drowned under circumstances that somewhat suggested foul play. Suspicion fell upon Murdoch s business partner, Gingrich Brown, because, while there were others who might have had the opportunity to kill Murdoch, no one else appeared to have a motive to do so. Now imagine that, having followed the case closely in the newspapers, 1 P. 155n of General Propositions and Causality in F. P. Ramsey s Philosophical Papers (Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990), 145 63. Analysis 60.1, January 2000, pp. 107 111. Vann McGee

108 vann mcgee you have convinced yourself, although without great confidence, that, in spite of the public uproar, Murdoch s death was an accident. You regard it as rather unlikely that Brown killed Murdoch, and even less likely that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch. Thus, you are inclined to disbelieve the conditional: If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. Such, at least, was your state of belief before Holmes appearance on the game show. On the basis of questions that have been answered before the Murdoch case is discussed, you have convinced yourself, with near certainty, that Player Number One is Sherlock Holmes. When Player Number One is asked about the Murdoch case, he replies: Examining this case thoroughly, at the behest of Scotland Yard, I found utterly conclusive evidence that Murdoch was murdered. Investigating further, I found convincing evidence that the culprit was Brown. Thus I am virtually certain that Brown killed Murdoch. Moreover, independent of the evidence that points to Brown, the evidence that Murdoch s death was a murder is so compelling that I can state with complete assurance that, if Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. After you have heard Player Number One s answer, what should your new beliefs be? Holmes expertise in forensic investigations is legendary, and it would be foolhardy of you to oppose your own superficial opinion, based on what you read in the papers, to his expert view. Since you are convinced that the master detective Sherlock Holmes has told you that, if Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did, you now believe: If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. The greatest detective in the world, or, at least, someone you have good reason to believe to be the greatest detective in the world, has told you that he has incontrovertible evidence that Murdoch s death was a murder. Who are you to say he is wrong? Ramsey s account handily explains Holmes assertion of the conditional, If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. The evidence that Murdoch s death was a homicide is so strong that it would hold up even if Holmes were to learn, much to his surprise, that Brown wasn t the malefactor. According to the new subjective probability measure Holmes would have after he learned that Brown didn t kill Murdoch, the probability that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch would be close to one. That implies, according to the Bayesian theory of belief revision, that his present conditional probability that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch,

to tell the truth about conditionals 109 given that Brown did not, should be close to one, and so, on the standard account of indicative conditionals, If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did should be highly assertable. The standard account does not do as good a job accounting for your assertion of the conditional, If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. How would your beliefs change if you were to learn that Brown did not kill Murdoch? Player Number One has expressed virtual certainty that Brown killed Murdoch, and it is unlikely that Sherlock Holmes would be so badly mistaken about a case he has studied closely. The most likely explanation for Player Number One s assertion would be that Player Number One is not Holmes at all. But if Player Number One is not Holmes, his pronouncements about the Murdoch case don t mean a damn thing, so you fall back to the old belief you had before the contestant spoke, namely, Most likely, Murdoch s death was an accident, so that nobody killed Murdoch. Surely nobody other than Brown killed Murdoch. Were you, after having heard Player Number One s answer, to learn to your surprise that Brown didn t kill Murdoch, your conditional probability that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch given that Player Number One is Holmes would be, in deference to Holmes expertise, close to one. On the other hand, your conditional probability that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch given that Player Number One is someone other than Holmes would revert to the same small value the thesis that someone other than Murdoch killed Brown had before you turned on the television. Your subjective probability that Player Number One is Holmes would decrease drastically. The cumulative effect of all these changes is that your degree of belief that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch, while slightly greater than it was before you turned on the TV, would still be quite low. According to the Bayesian doctrine about belief revision, the fact that learning that Brown didn t kill Murdoch would result in your assigning a low probability to the thesis that someone other then Brown killed Murdoch means that your current conditional probability that someone other than Brown killed Murdoch given that Brown didn t kill Murdoch should be low. The doctrine in upheld in this case, inasmuch as the probability of Brown didn t kill Murdoch but someone else did is noticeably lower than that of Brown didn t kill Murdoch and no one else did. We find ourselves in a situation in which the conditional

110 vann mcgee If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did is highly assertable (and acceptable and probable) even though the conditional probability of the consequent given the antecedent is low. This is contrary to what the standard theory predicts, so the standard theory is wrong. Or so, at least, I want to claim. Admittedly, the data that support this drastic conclusion aren t many. The only evidence to support the contention that, in the circumstances described, we would be willing to assert the conditional is my own intuitions, and the intuitions of a few friends to whom I have shown the example. But though the data are few in number, they are high in quality. The intuition that, under the circumstances described, I would be willing to assert and accept the conditional is firm and unmistakable. The contestant I take to be Holmes has said, If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did, and, by golly, if he said it, I believe it. When Holmes tells us that, if Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did, he does so as a way of reporting to us that there is further evidence that supports the thesis that Murdoch s death was a homicide in addition to the evidence that points to Brown as the malefactor. On the basis of the putative Holmes testimony, I too have evidence, albeit indirect evidence, that supports the thesis that Murdoch s death was a homicide, in addition to my reasons for believing that Brown was the malefactor. I would presume that it is this further evidence that I report when I say, If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did. Were I to learn, however, that Brown didn t kill Murdoch, Player Number One s testimony would lose most of its evidentiary value, so that I would no longer have good reason to suppose that Murdoch s death was a homicide. Notice that, throughout all the actual and hypothetical changes of belief, our disbelief in the subjunctive conditional If Brown hadn t killed Murdoch, someone else would have remains undisturbed. Thus, whatever else may be going on in this example, it s not a case of an indicative mood conditional acting like a counterfactual. The empirical hypothesis that we accept and are willing to assert an indicative conditional when and only when the conditional probability of the consequent given the antecedent is close to one has been upheld through a vast array of examples, both commonplace and exotic, both simple and sophisticated. The present example appears to be an exception to the pattern. Frankly, I don t know what to make of it. The probabilistic analysis of conditionals seems to be stymied here, and the possible-worlds account doesn t do any better. Stalnaker 2 extended his 2 Indicative Conditionals in W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, and G. Pearce, eds., Ifs (Dordrecht, Holland: D. Seidel, 1981), 193 210.

to tell the truth about conditionals 111 theory, originally devised to describe subjunctive conditionals, to encompass indicative conditionals by requiring that, in evaluating an indicative conditional, the only worlds we look at are epistemically possible ones. In the present situation, the actual world, so we have reason to believe, is a world in which Player Number One is Holmes and in which Brown killed Murdoch. The nearest world in which Brown didn t kill Murdoch is a world in which Player Number One is Holmes and in which nobody killed Murdoch; that s why we regard the counterfactual If Brown hadn t killed Murdoch, someone else would have as false. But that world isn t epistemically possible, since it s a world in which Holmes is mistaken. Moreover, worlds in which Murdoch is still alive are epistemically impossible. Among the worlds that remain, the world in which Brown does not kill Murdoch that is most similar to the actual world is a world in which Murdoch simply lost his footing on the dock, and so a world in which no one killed Murdoch. Thus, on Stalnaker s account, the conditional If Brown didn t kill Murdoch, someone else did is false; yet we accept it. What I would like to do now is to provide an adapted version of the standard theory that corrects the deficiency the example illustrates. Unfortunately, I don t have one to offer. 3 Department of Linguistics and Philosophy Massachusetts Institute of Technology Cambridge, MA 02139, USA vmcgee@mit.edu 3 I would like to thank Ernest Adams, Aldo Antonelli, Horatio Arlo-Costa, Ned Hall, Richard Jeffrey, Krister Segerberg, and Brian Skyrms for helpful discussions.