RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

Similar documents
the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

Marquis. Stand-off in Abortion Debate

Does Personhood Begin at Conception?

When does human life begin? by Dr Brigid Vout

A Person s a Person. By Sharlena Kuehmichel. February 26, Abstract

THE HUMAN BODY SWORD KRIS BORER * LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 2, ART. NO. 20 (2010)

MORAL DISAGREEMENT CONCERNING ABORTION 1

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

A Social Practice View of Natural Rights. Word Count: 2998

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONAL IDENTITY

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION: A REPLY TO PROFESSOR NARVESON

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Philosophy and Theology: The Time-Relative Interest Account

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Political Science 103 Fall, 2018 Dr. Edward S. Cohen INTRODUCTION TO POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

On Humanity and Abortion;Note

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

A Framework for the Good

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

Phil 114, February 29, 2012 Sir Robert Filmer, Observations Concerning the Originall of Government

HAS DAVID HOWDEN VINDICATED RICHARD VON MISES S DEFINITION OF PROBABILITY?

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Case: 2:15-cv EAS-TPK Doc #: 2-3 Filed: 12/13/15 Page: 1 of 9 PAGEID #: 35

The Pleasure Imperative

) What is the law of bio-genesis, and how does that relate to the humanity of the pre-born childe?

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Anselmian Theism and Created Freedom: Response to Grant and Staley

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Ethical Relativism 1. Ethical Relativism: Ethical Relativism: subjective objective ethical nihilism Ice cream is good subjective

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Socratic and Platonic Ethics

Attraction, Description, and the Desire-Satisfaction Theory of Welfare

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Scanlon on Double Effect

Summary of Locke's Second Treatise [T2]

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Preliminary Remarks on Locke's The Second Treatise of Government (T2)

Intrinsic Properties Defined. Peter Vallentyne, Virginia Commonwealth University. Philosophical Studies 88 (1997):

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

EUTHANASIA EUTHANASIA NEWS IN CANADA

Lincoln-Douglas: The Inquistive Debate of Philosophy

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Rawls versus utilitarianism: the subset objection

Evaluating the New Perspective on Paul (4)

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Philosophy Pathways Issue nd October

PHIL 176: Death (Spring, 2007)

Reflections on the Ontological Status

Hobbes On Citizenship

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

In his essay Why Abortion is Immoral, Don Marquis asserts that,

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

Rawls, rationality, and responsibility: Why we should not treat our endowments as morally arbitrary

One of the central concerns in metaphysics is the nature of objects which

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

DOES CONSEQUENTIALISM DEMAND TOO MUCH?

Apostasy and Conversion Kishan Manocha

FAITH EVANGELICAL LUTHERAN CHURCH MEMORIAL PRAYER GARDEN 886 North Shore Drive Forest Lake, Minnesota RULES AND PROCEDURES

Is Morality Rational?

Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client

Consciousness Without Awareness

Students for Life of America 1

TEILHARD DE CHARDIN: TOWARD A DEVELOPMENTAL AND ORGANIC THEOLOGY

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

THE UNCOMFORTABLE QUESTION OF EVIL

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

On Making the Case for Life

The Confusing Moral Logic of Embryonic Stem Cell Research

In the preface to Law and Justice in Community the authors say:

Philosophical Review.

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

INTRODUCTION TO THINKING AT THE EDGE. By Eugene T. Gendlin, Ph.D.

THE ETHICS OF STRATEGIC COMMUNICATION: WINTER 2009

Law of the Russian Soviet Federative Socialist Republic on Freedom of Worship (25/10/1990)

THEY SAY: Discussing what the sources are saying

Government Neutrality toward. Conceptions of a Good Life: It s Possible and Desirable, But Perhaps Not so Important. Peter de Marneffe.

Transcription:

LIBERTARIAN PAPERS VOL. 8, NO. 2 (2016) RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION JAN NARVESON * MARK FRIEDMAN, in his generally excellent Libertarian Philosophy in the Real World, 1 classifies the abortion issue as one on which there is really no definitive, official libertarian view, despite the plank in the Libertarian Party platform calling for no government overseeing of the matter, leaving it to the conscience of each individual and thus enshrining what is usually called the liberal or pro-choice view. He states that this does not mean that the position flows naturally from one or more of the basic principles that undergird libertarianism (157). He goes on, quite correctly, to point out that everything depends on the question of just when at what point in its development, if any the fetus acquires moral status. In particular, if that point were early on in the nine months of fetal development, then it would be very plausible to argue that its right to life pre-empts whatever preferences its parents or maternal parent might have about it. My discussion (a) resoundingly denies Friedman s claim that no position flows naturally from the basic principles that undergird libertarianism, and (b) defends the choice of birth, for most contemporary societies, as the plausible point of departure for denying any basic intrinsic rights to pre-borns and possibly granting some indirect rights to post-borns. However, my argument does not try to discuss all dimensions of this issue. * Jan Narveson is professor emeritus of philosophy at the University of Waterloo. CITATION INFORMATION FOR THIS ARTICLE: Jan Narveson. 2016. Resolving the Debate on Libertarianism and Abortion. Libertarian Papers. 8 (2): 267-272. ONLINE AT: libertarianpapers.org. THIS ARTICLE IS subject to a Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License (creativecommons.org/licenses). 1 Mark Friedman, Libertarian Philosophy in the Real World (London: Bloomsbury, 2015). 267

268 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 8 (2), (2016) Friedman cites the familiar argument of Don Marquis 2 that murdering someone deprives him of his life at whatever point in his life that might be. But Marquis claims that as soon as the group of cells that becomes that person is sufficiently organized to be uniquely identifiable as a certain purely biological individual-to-be, which he says is about three weeks, we have sufficient reason to say that aborting that mass of tissues deprives of life the individual whose life is in question. But this begs the question on the main issue. Fetuses have none of the interactive psychological properties we ascribe to all human persons. There is no excuse for ascribing inherent liberty rights to things that have none of those features. You can only qualify for a right to general liberty if you have a will that can be thwarted by others actions. Of Marquis s account, Friedman says, Clearly, this verdict runs counter to the strong, widely held intuition that an organism so unlike a standard adult human (or even a newborn) should be entitled to Full Moral Status Quite obviously, this is a thorny issue (159; emphasis in original). But it is not a matter of trying to decide whether some organism is too unlike ordinary humans to be eligible for moral standing. Neither Marquis nor anyone else has reason to attribute rights to clumps of cells. Rights are for persons, not organisms or DNA encodings. Marquis s argument is not really an argument at all, but a groundless assertion: in context, it begs the question. Is X a person and thus entitled to moral standing? Marquis s answer is that X is a person when it is a clump of cells that we can identify as the individual human it will grow into. Such an answer is not just thorny it is dead wrong. We could never settle the question of who has rights if that was the only sort of argument to make. Any such answer is arbitrary if it fails to identify what it is about people that makes it plausible to extend to them the intrinsic rights that we (most of us) think they have. Now, the individual that a given fetus would become, if it does become one, of course would then have the rights that we all have. But if that fetus does not have those defining properties, then if there is an abortion, no such person exists as yet, and so no person has been deprived of his life. You cannot murder a clump of cells. Thus Friedman is wrong about this, as is Marquis. Libertarianism gives every person the right to run his or her own life. But fetuses are not able to run anything. They are not participants in the agreements among us that constitute morality, and not yet participants in communities. We of course 183 202. 2 Don Marquis, Why Abortion Is Immoral, Journal of Philosophy 86 (April 1989),

LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION 269 usually anticipate with joy the arrival of this organism into personhood but that is not to be confused with its having rights, nor does it give it such a status. It simply does not have the status of personhood, and it is not a matter of how much we love or care about the entities in question. There might be reasons why a given society would want to insist on carrying fetuses to term, but those reasons have no grounding in fetal rights, and it is difficult to think of any that would pass muster with libertarians, who (rightly) deny that society has any business coercing individuals for any other purpose than mutual protection. And in the case of society versus individual nonparents, that s certainly what it would be. We should remember that many societies have not even extended rights to newborns. 3 For example, they have routinely exposed to the elements newborns who were defective or even simply one too many for the limited resources available. Neither of those conditions is at all likely to apply nowadays, of course. Reasons for terminating the lives of infants are not of that sort. And there is in fact a major difference between fetuses and newborns, as any parent knows. Even very young infants begin to have some of the features that identify one as a person and not just a clump of cells. But even so, there is no fundamental basis for attributing rights to nonminded, nonpersonal beings. Morality is for people, not for organisms. Of course, we persons have bodies we are organisms, of a sort but it is not our organisms that have rights, but we. Among those rights is the protection of that organism from damage by others. You do not need to be a metaphysical dualist to say this. Rather, you only need common sense. Wherever the I constituting a given person is located or whatever gives us that right, it is our choices and agreements, not the physical thing that presumably is our operating substructure, that create and ground rights. Societies often feel that they need rules about such things as childbirth. (Contemporary China, e.g., long required that citizens have no more than one child. The policy was a mistaken reaction to a misperceived shortage of resources; but, given that misperception, it is easy to see why a society might impose the policy.) Philosophers and legislators, then, might press for a precise demarcation between the developing organisms about which parents may decide whether they live, and those that society will protect as valued members of the community. And a very plausible such demarcation is indeed 3 See, for example, Jared Diamond, The World until Yesterday (New York: Viking, 2012), pp. 177 79, for an insightful and highly informed discussion of primitive societies practices on this matter.

270 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 8 (2), (2016) birth certainly too early for a being to possess actual personality, but again, there might be other reasons why society would want to protect its newborns. The great advantage of birth for such purposes is that prior to birth, the fetus is in the mother s body and one would need to invade that body if involuntary eviction, say, were proposed; whereas, once born, the infant is separate from that mother and thus, can be transported without invading her body. Forcibly parting a mother from her fetus assaults that woman s body. It is not so for newborns or infants, who can be transferred without physical harm to their mothers (psychological harm is, of course, another matter). That forcibly taking an infant away from its mother would be an invasion of her rights, of course, is true, but is another matter at least, once it is born, no one needs to violate her body per se in order to remove the infant from her. Just what if anything would justify taking an infant from its parents is an interesting question. But it is important to realize that it is not a question that necessarily concerns the issue of abortion as such. Libertarians defend property rights, but do any of them think one s right to one s car, say, is more fundamental and more important than the right to one s very body? Newborns and infants are in great demand in contemporary societies. Do we have reason to insist on parental control over them to the exclusion of rival bidders who might well give them a better life? We may insist only that the parents brought an infant into existence, a fact creating a historical link to those particular parents a link that the infant does not have to anyone else. But if those parents are interested in the infant s well-being, and cannot or are disinclined to provide for it, one could argue that in extreme cases involuntary adoption might be called for. Do parents have the right to deposit newborns in garbage bags? Most people think not yet even today in places like America, the penalties meted out for such activities are far smaller than the penalties for killing more well-developed children. And this has been accepted practice in many societies. Indeed, in most or nearly all precontemporary societies, infant exposure to the elements was accepted and even routine if the child was not likely to grow up sufficiently well to sustain itself. But there would be no question of whether such parental rights were limited if the entity in question were not yet born, since then, in addition to what could be argued to be theft, there would be the much more basic problem of invasion of person. Thus any protections of infants are not due to fetal rights or newborn rights. They are due to special interests of society (perhaps): those beings do not have rights, but we adults have rights over our precious newborns rights that may come into conflict with the rights of other adults to self-

LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION 271 defense, broadly defined. For example, adults might object to a given parent s retaining control over her young ones if compelling evidence shows that children brought up the way the parent is bringing them up will before long become juvenile delinquents, menaces to their neighbors. And those neighbors, of course, do have a say in such things. No such issues can arise regarding fetuses, however. So Friedman, I submit, is wrong. There is an intrinsic basis for liberty rights, and it does not obtain in the cases of pre-borns or newborns. How long after birth it does obtain is a reasonable question. But after all, children are valuable indeed, essential if there is to be an ongoing society. If, like Friedman, we support a minimal state, then provisions for protections of newborns, and so on, are something we might want to consider. Whether any such protections can pass muster as libertarian is an important question, but not one I will explore further here. All I need do is emphasize that for society to invade the bodies of mothers is a far more basic and unarguable violation of individual liberty, the fight against which is the essence of libertarianism. Obviously outside parties might try to reason with potential mothers about the value of their continuing, or discontinuing, gestation. But invasion is another matter, of course. It is what libertarianism is about. Arguably, it is the rights of, first, parents and then those who would be affected by the new persons that are to be respected in these matters. That is why the Libertarian Party s statement is basically right: it is to be left to parents, and especially the female parent, whether to raise a given infant. If a woman has a child, but does not wish to care for it, then others may volunteer to take on the unwanted child. The initial parents can make an offer to those potential caregivers, and society must allow parents to consider such offers and accept or reject them. One might hope things would not get that far: expectant mothers who do not want their fetuses to come to term should, of course, be able to abort. They are not committing murder, as I have argued, since the fetus does not have the sort of capabilities that endow a being with rights the violation of which amounts to murder. Beyond that, we may insist that parents do reasonably well by their children; and the parents themselves normally would want to do better than that, if possible. But even here, there is little room for rational governmental intervention in those areas either, as Friedman himself would agree. Although this discussion has defended the modern liberal view on abortion in the context of libertarianism, my argument in fact is prior to libertarianism. It is instead about the fundamental idea of (social) morality of the rules by which we humans are to relate to each other. Those rules are

272 LIBERTARIAN PAPERS 8 (2), (2016) human-made, not natural in the way that the bark growing on trees is natural. And as such, the rules must be made by rational beings in their selfperceived interests and not by legislators or constitutional conventions. That is what gives credence to the claim that libertarian rights are natural rights. I have frequently defended the social contract as the basis of morals. We have nothing else on which to base a rational morality. And social contracts, the general agreements in accordance with which we all are to live with each other, can only be made by rational beings sufficiently well developed to understand the terms of that agreement. Any rights we attribute to anything else to property, for instance derive from the rights of the primary contractors. Fetuses and infants come under the same category. Most parents are very interested in parenthood, and very concerned for the good of their children. That is as it should be. But it does not allow us to ascribe intrinsic rights to things that simply are not capable of having them. 4 4 A more extensive discussion can be found in Jan Narveson, Moral Matters (2nd edition, Peterborough, ON: Broadview, 1999), ch. 8, pp. 157 80. See also my entry in Arguments for Liberty, forthcoming from The Cato Institute.