Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in

Similar documents
Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Disassembling actor-network theory

Review: The sacredness of the person: a new genealogy of human rights

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Daniel Little Fallibilism and Ontology in Tuukka Kaidesoja s Critical Realist Social Ontology

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Research and Analysis Paths between Positivism and Interpretivism: An Appraisal of Hay s Via Media

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Tuukka Kaidesoja Précis of Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Noonan, Harold (2010) The thinking animal problem and personal pronoun revisionism. Analysis, 70 (1). pp ISSN

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

UvA-DARE (Digital Academic Repository) A letter to Georg Kneer: replik Mol, A.

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

Problems of causation in world politics

what makes reasons sufficient?

ONTOLOGICAL PROBLEMS OF PLURALIST RESEARCH METHODOLOGIES

Review Essay: Humanism and sociology

Phenomenal Consciousness and Intentionality<1>

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Proof in mathematics education: research, learning and teaching

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

the paradigms have on the structure of research projects. An exploration of epistemology, ontology

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

Book Review Why We Disagree About Climate Change: Understanding Controversy, Inaction and Opportunity

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Centre for Public Policy Research Working Papers Series Paper No: 1. An Introduction to Critical Realism as a Meta-Theoretical Research Perspective

R. Keith Sawyer: Social Emergence. Societies as Complex Systems. Cambridge University Press

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

The Paradox of Positivism

appearance is often different from reality, and it s reality that counts.

Why Legal Positivism?

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

THE HUMAN QUEST: PHILOSOPHICAL PERSPECTIVES ON LIFELONG LEARNING

On Popper, Problems and Problem-Solving: A Review of Cruickshank and Sassower's Democratic Problem-Solving

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Not-So-Well-Designed Scientific Communities. Inkeri Koskinen, University of Helsinki

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

Crawford L. Elder, Familiar Objects and Their Shadows, Cambridge University Press, 2011, 222pp., $85.00 (hardback), ISBN

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Constructing the World

John D. Caputo s book is one in a new series from Penguin called Philosophy in

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Summary Kooij.indd :14

Review of The Monk and the Philosopher

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Postmodal Metaphysics

M.A. PROSEMINAR, PHIL 5850 PHILOSOPHICAL NATURALISM Fall 2018 Tuesdays 2:35-5:25 p.m. Paterson Hall 3A36

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

4/22/ :42:01 AM


Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Sentence Starters from They Say, I Say

Against Vague and Unnatural Existence: Reply to Liebesman

The Nature of Enquiry

The Philosophy of Consciousness Without an Object

Keywords: Knowledge Organization. Discourse Community. Dimension of Knowledge. 1 What is epistemology in knowledge organization?

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Meta-Debate: A necessity for any debate style.

DANCY ON ACTING FOR THE RIGHT REASON

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

THEOLOGY AND SCIENCE: CONVERGING ON REALITY

Realism and instrumentalism

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Philosophica 67 (2001, 1) pp. 5-9 INTRODUCTION

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

Review of Who Rules in Science?, by James Robert Brown

Suppressed Subjectivity and Truncated Tradition: A Reply to Pablo Schyfter

The Vocation Movement in Lutheran Higher Education

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

Philosophy 125 Day 13: Overview

On the Rationality of Metaphysical Commitments in Immature Science

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Instructor's Manual for Gregg Barak s Integrating Criminologies. Prepared by Paul Leighton (Boston: Allyn & Bacon, 1997) * CHAPTER 4

Journal Of Contemporary Trends In Business And Information Technology (JCTBIT) Vol.5, pp.1-6, December Existentialist s Model of Professionalism

Relativism. We re both right.

Normativity and Philosophical Naturalism - Peircean Lessons. Henrik Rydenfelt University of Helsinki

POLITICAL SECULARISM AND PUBLIC REASON. THREE REMARKS ON AUDI S DEMOCRATIC AUTHORITY AND THE SEPARATION OF CHURCH AND STATE

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Cogito Ergo Sum Christopher Peacocke and John Campbell

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Philosophy 125 Day 12: Overview

Index of Templates from They Say, I Say by Gerald Graff and Cathy Birkenstein. Introducing What They Say. Introducing Standard Views

GMAT ANALYTICAL WRITING ASSESSMENT

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

The unity of the normative

Naturalism and is Opponents

Truth and Realism. EDITED BY PATRICK GREENOUGH AND MICHAEL P. LYNCH. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. ix Price h/b, p/b.

Transcription:

Loughborough University Institutional Repository Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author. Citation: ELDER-VASS, D., 2017. Reflections on sociology's unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in. Journal of Sociology, 53 (4), pp. 753-755. Additional Information: Copyright c 2017 (The Author). Reprinted by permission of SAGE Publications. Metadata Record: https://dspace.lboro.ac.uk/2134/27868 Version: Accepted for publication Publisher: Sage c The Author Rights: This work is made available according to the conditions of the Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 International (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0) licence. Full details of this licence are available at: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Please cite the published version.

Reflections on Sociology s Unspoken Weakness: Bringing Epistemology Back In Dave Elder-Vass Loughborough University This is a pre-publication version of a paper accepted for publication in Journal of Sociology. It may differ slightly from the published version. Please refer to the published version if citing, and cite as follows: Elder-Vass, D. (2017) Reflections on sociology s unspoken weakness: Bringing epistemology back in, Journal of Sociology 53(4) 753 755. Rob Stones s article raises an important challenge for contemporary social theory: the need for an epistemology for the social sciences that is as sophisticated and functional as the various ontologies that have been developed in recent decades. I share both his desire for adequate standards by which to judge knowledge claims in the social sciences and the realist orientation of his approach to the problem. He begins by posing this as a general problem for post-positivist social theory. Arguably, the problem arises from the post-positivist commitment to epistemological relativism: from the perspective of a sociology (or indeed an ontology) of knowledge, not only the conceptual assumptions built into knowledge claims but also the standards by which they are judged are local to particular epistemic/epistemological communities (or circles: see Elder-Vass, 2012, Chapter 11). If this is so, then the project of specifying more general standards by which to judge knowledge claims seems in danger of being hopelessly naïve. Yet for realists, some knowledge claims are sounder than others, and so there must be standards by which we can judge them. And indeed there are such standards: all epistemic communities have 1

their own standards by which they judge knowledge claims and even the same community may have different standards for different kinds of knowledge (Elder-Vass, 2012). But the challenge for epistemology is to provide reasons for preferring some standards over others. We have, I suggest, at least four resources that may be called upon to help us resolve this issue. First, there is experience: those standards that support knowledge claims that accord with our experience should surely be preferred over those that do not. Second, we have debate: in the spirit of Habermas s discourse principle, we may say that any standard to which the affected parties would agree in an open process of discussion oriented to reaching agreement should be preferred (Elder-Vass, 2010, p. 50; Habermas, 1996, p. 107). Third, this problem is never entirely free floating but rather is necessarily tied to a specific context. In the case at issue here this context is, first, the academic space of social theory itself, and second, the public sphere when social theorists seek to influence it. The challenge is not to identify some universal standard of epistemological value but only one that we could justify preferring in this particular context. Fourth, we have ontology itself: any epistemology entails a theory of knowledge that itself rests on a social ontology and an epistemology that fits with the most plausible social ontology should be preferred. Still, applying these resources to the problem is a far larger task than I can attempt in this brief note, and they may still not be enough to provide a solution. The last of them, however, may help to make further sense of the issues raised in the second half of Stones s paper. Here the question is re-posed, or perhaps illustrated, as a problem for John Law s version of actor-network theory in particular. A central feature of Law s work is his insistence on the existence of multiple realities. For him, for example, there is not one thing called alcoholic liver disease but many different diseases not in the mundane sense that there might be different medical conditions brought about by alcoholism that affect the liver but in the much more provocative sense that what most of us would think of as the same disease at the same point of time in the same person is actually a different reality for each different specialist that interacts with it (Law, 2004, Chapter 4). Ironically, given the powerful antipathy of Bruno Latour to postmodernism, this leads us back towards strong epistemological relativism. The direction of travel for Law is to recognise all of these different realities as equally real and thus all of the different understandings of them as equally valid. If there is a different reality for each specialist who 2

brings a different set of concepts to their understanding of alcoholic liver disease, then it is hard to see how one could judge any one of their views of that reality to be wrong. This is not, however, an issue that Law could consistently construe as soluble by strengthened epistemological standards. On the contrary, the problem arises from a key feature of actor-network theory s ontology. For Latour, and it seems for Law, the world is composed of assemblages, and the discourses, texts, and beliefs that are part and parcel of these assemblages are indissolubly wrapped up with its more objective dimensions (Elder- Vass, 2015). Stones, however, following Bhaskar, insists that it is both possible and essential to treat transitive aspects as having intransitive qualities, and also that it is possible to make a distinction between the transitive aspects within the object of study and the transitive dimension of the social science gaze upon the object of study. Social scientists, according to this argument, are able to make claims about the discourses, ideas, and beliefs that are part of the object of study, and about the more material or objective features of the object of study. They are also often able to distinguish between these two different dimensions within the object of study. The actor-network ontology refuses to countenance these moves. It simply holds that objects cannot be separated from claims about them and as a consequence the whole concept of epistemology ceases to be available, except as something that other people talk about. Claims about things cannot be judged because they are intrinsically part of the things that they are about. Latour replaces epistemology with rhetoric, and I mean that as a literal description of his position: he argues that scientists deploy epistemological devices as rhetoric to bolster their claims about the world, and takes an entirely neutral position as to the validity of those devices (Latour, 1987, Chapter 1). The epistemological problem facing Law, then, may not be just an example of the wider problem facing theory, but a far more serious problem that arises from a fundamental flaw in the ontology of actor-network theory: its conscious refusal to distinguish between the complex intransitive domain and the transitive domains of social science. This means it cannot begin to distinguish between the things and ideas that are the object of study and our social scientific propositions about them. 3

References Elder-Vass, D. (2010). Realist critique without ethical naturalism or moral realism. Journal of Critical Realism, 9(1), 33 58. Elder-Vass, D. (2012). The Reality of Social Construction. Cambridge: Cambridge UP. Elder-Vass, D. (2015). Disassembling Actor-Network Theory. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 45(1), 100 121. Habermas, J. (1996). Between Facts and Norms. Cambridge: Polity. Latour, B. (1987). Science in action. Harvard University Press. Law, J. (2004). After method: mess in social science research. London: Routledge. 4