LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

Similar documents
LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

1/10. Primary and Secondary Qualities and the Ideas of Substance

Primary and Secondary Qualities. John Locke s distinction between primary and secondary qualities of bodies has

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

Locke s Fallen Baconianism. Peter R. Anstey: John Locke & Natural Philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011, 256 pp, $65.


EMPIRICISM & EMPIRICAL PHILOSOPHY

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

out in his Three Dialogues and Principles of Human Knowledge, gives an argument specifically

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

The British Empiricism

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Unit 2. WoK 1 - Perception. Tuesday, October 7, 14

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

LOCKE ON REAL ESSENCES, INTELLIGIBILITY, AND NATURAL KINDS

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

Superaddition and Miracles in Locke s Philosophy of Science and Metaphysics

A Studying of Limitation of Epistemology as Basis of Toleration with Special Reference to John Locke

[JGRChJ 9 (2013) R28-R32] BOOK REVIEW

REVIEW THE DOOR TO SELLARS

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

John Locke. British Empiricism

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

Mind s Eye Idea Object

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

THE HISTORIC ALLIANCE OF CHRISTIANITY AND SCIENCE

Class #13 - The Consciousness Theory of the Self Locke, The Prince and the Cobbler Reid, Of Mr. Locke's Account of Our Personal Identity

The Problem of the External World

Locke's Primary Qualities

Philosophy in Review XXXII (2012), no. 5

spring 05 topics in philosophy of mind session 7

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Was Berkeley a Rational Empiricist? In this short essay I will argue for the conclusion that, although Berkeley ought to be

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2015

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Chapter 16 George Berkeley s Immaterialism and Subjective Idealism

To appear in The Journal of Philosophy.

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

1/8. Reid on Common Sense

Class 17 - Three Arguments for Idealism Berkeley s Principles, 1-33 (AW ) Three Dialogues, First Dialogue (AW )

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Class 18 - Against Abstract Ideas Berkeley s Principles, Introduction, (AW ); (handout) Three Dialogues, Second Dialogue (AW )

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I

A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

Elements of Mind (EM) has two themes, one major and one minor. The major theme is

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

Humanities 3 V. The Scientific Revolution

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

From Descartes to Locke. Sense Perception And The External World

Is the Skeptical Attitude the Attitude of a Skeptic?

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

Class #17 - Three Arguments for Idealism Berkeley s Principles, 1-33 (AW ) Three Dialogues, First Dialogue (AW )

Evidence and Transcendence

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

Section 2.2: Primary & secondary qualities

Epistemology and sensation


1/13. Locke on Power

A note on science and essentialism

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Kant and his Successors

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Idealism from A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge, Part I by George Berkeley (1720)

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Ever since W. V. O. Quine wrote his famous Two Dogmas of

Skepticism and Internalism

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Descartes to Early Psychology. Phil 255

The Self and Other Minds

The CopernicanRevolution

DEGREES OF CERTAINTY AND SENSITIVE KNOWLEDGE: A REPLY TO SOLES. Samuel C. Rickless. [Penultimate version of a paper published in Locke Studies (2015)]

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

You keep using that word. I do not think it means what you think it means. an analysis of Descartes Evil Genius conceivability argument

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Introduction to Philosophy

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

John Locke on Perception (1690)

Writing Your Doctoral Thesis with Word This document is an example of what you can do with the POLITO Template

Transcription:

LOCKE STUDIES Vol. 18 https://doi.org/10.5206/ls.2018.3525 ISSN: 2561-925X Submitted: 28 JUNE 2018 Published online: 30 JULY 2018 For more information, see this article s homepage. 2018. Nathan Rockwood Review of Locke s Image of the World by Michael Jacovides NATHAN ROCKWOOD (BRIGHAM YOUNG UNIVERSITY) Abstract: A book review of Michael Jacovides s recent book, Locke s Image of the World (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2017). Keywords: history of science, epistemology, corpuscularianism, John Locke, Robert Boyle, Isaac Newton Locke Studies is published by The John Locke Society. This is an open access article published under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International license, which permits use, distribution and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited and shared under the original license.

2 Jacovides, Michael. Locke s Image of the World. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2017. 231 pp. $70 (hbk). ISBN 9780198789864. Reviewed by NATHAN ROCKWOOD The overarching theme of Locke s Image of the World, by Michael Jacovides, is that Locke s belief in the best science of his day shapes his philosophy in important ways. Jacovides contends that by understanding the scientific background to Locke s thoughts, we can better understand his work (1), including both his positions and his arguments for those positions. To a lesser extent, Jacovides s book also treats Locke as a case study in thinking about how much scientific theory should influence philosophy. While much of the science Locke relies on is incomplete or problematic, and so leads him into errors, Jacovides is sympathetic to Locke s approach of using the best scientific theories to help develop and justify his philosophical positions. There are three main sources of scientific theory that influence Locke. First, he was trained as a medical doctor and engaged in medical experiments. Second, he was a close associate of Robert Boyle who, along with René Descartes, convince Locke that corpuscularianism is the best scientific theory. Even then, however, Locke recognizes shortcomings of this theory. Finally, he later befriends Isaac Newton and becomes convinced that Newton s physics is, in some respects, incompatible with corpuscularianism. Jacovides shows how each of these scientific theories influence Locke s thinking on a variety of topics. The result is an impressive account of the history of science at a critical point in its development through the lens of one of the great philosophers of that time. Jacovides contends (chap. 2) that Locke s study of medicine made him skeptical that we can know the underlying causes of things. By 1664, Locke was engaged in research on respiration (5) and in the mid-1660s he posits the existence of ferments (a kind of matter) as an explanation of disease (6ff). Jacovides takes these scientific enterprises to be philosophically significant because they present alternatives to the reductive explanations of corpuscularianism that Locke would favor later in his career. In the late 1660s, Locke then meets Sydenham who advocates for treatments that have been empirically shown to be effective but for which we lack an underlying explanation as to why they work (9). At this point, according to Jacovides (10 11, 14), Locke becomes much more skeptical about our ability to know the underlying causes of natural phenomena. This skepticism becomes one of the hallmarks of Locke s epistemology (13). Another way in which Locke s medical research influences his philosophy is the discovery of the retinal image. Jacovides describes (chap. 7) how Locke became aware of the retinal image, a two-dimensional image on the back of the retina. Locke seems to think that, since the retinal image is two-dimensional, visual perception is of a two-dimensional array; only through experience do we come to associate certain patterns of color shading with three-dimensional shapes. According to Jacovides, this explains why, in his discussion of the Molyneux problem, Locke asserts that, when a globe is placed in front of a formerly blind person who just gained sight, the person would see a flat circle rather than a three-dimensional sphere (Essay, II.xiii.6). The trouble for Locke, Jacovides notes, is that visual perception is not generally experienced as a two-dimensional array. Jacovides suggests that Locke s scientific theory leads him to make the (probably sincere) claim that he perceives the world as two-dimensional. In this way, Locke s scientific

theory shapes his account of visual perception. Scientific theory influencing how Locke perceives the world is a recurring theme in the book. Throughout the discussion of the medical science informing Locke s Essay, Jacovides skillfully describes both the scholastic background and, for Locke, the recent developments in medical science. The scholarship is always careful and interesting, though, in my view, the philosophical insight to be gained varies. Jacovides s account of the retinal image, for example, strikes me as persuasive and of great insight into explaining Locke s otherwise puzzling thesis that visual perception is experienced as twodimensional. It is much less clear to me that Locke s medical research in the 1660s had the same level of impact. Jacovides presents Locke s research as engaging in alternative traditions to corpuscularianism (5), yet, as he later concedes, Though Locke s speculations during the 1660s use non-corpuscularian concepts in a way that we don t find in his later work, they don t mark a sharp break with Boyle s work and thought [i.e., corpuscularianism] (8 9). Similarly, Jacovides points to Locke s association with Sydenham, and the latter s approach to looking for effective treatments while confessing ignorance about the underlying causes, as pushing Locke toward skepticism about our ability to know underlying causes. But notice that, again, this is compatible with Locke s contemporaneous commitment to corpuscularianism, and indeed such skepticism follows from corpuscularianism, since we cannot observe the tiny particles that explain natural phenomena. Most of the literature on Locke s philosophy of science, including the bulk of Jacovides s book, focuses on how corpuscularianism influences Locke s philosophy. According to corpuscularianism, observable objects are composed of imperceptibly small particles, and the size, shape, and motion of these particles explain the observable properties and behaviors of macroscopic objects (4 5). It is well known that Locke was influenced by corpuscularianism, and Jacovides s book adds new insight to this topic. Jacovides asserts that the connection [between science and Locke s philosophy] is most explicit in the chapter on primary and secondary qualities (2). After describing a corpuscularian theory of perception, Locke says, From whence I think it is easy to draw this observation, namely, that the ideas of primary qualities resemble properties in actual objects whereas the ideas of secondary qualities do not (Essay, II.viii.15). Here is a clear example of Locke using his favored scientific theory to make an inference about metaphysics and, as Jacovides goes on to explain, leads Locke to substantially revise the standard theory of mental representation. Jacovides takes Locke to accept the standard Aristotelian theory of mental representation for primary qualities but not for secondary qualities. Primary qualities are the properties that are fundamental and inseparable from material objects. This much is not controversial, but Jacovides s interpretation of Locke s account of primary qualities differs substantially from many other interpretations in two respects. First, he argues (chap. 5) that primary qualities are determinable properties such as having some shape (or other) and having some size (or other), rather than a determinate shape and size, such as being circular or being one inch in diameter, on the grounds that the latter are not inseparable from material objects. Second, and more radically, he argues (chap. 8) that our ideas of primary qualities resemble in virtue of, literally, having the same kind of property. For example, my idea of the statue of liberty is taller than it is wide, and hence my idea is literally extended and literally has a shape (165). The Aristotelian position, as Jacovides describes it, is that ideas represent by resembling the thing represented. 3

Jacovides suggests that Locke accepts this as the right account of representation with respect to primary qualities. But, famously, Locke denies that our ideas of secondary qualities resemble properties in objects and so, for these properties, he is in need of an alternative theory of representation. Here Locke turns to causation. Summing up the position he argues for in chapters 8 and 9, Jacovides says, Locke s account of secondary qualities describes how our secondary quality predicates work (181); namely, an object satisfies the predicate is white if and only if the object has a power to produce the idea of whiteness (182). Whatever regularly causes us to have an idea of whiteness counts as white. This move allows Locke to say that snow is white is true, for example, while avoiding a commitment to the thesis that ideas of secondary qualities resemble properties in objects. There is no mind-independent property of snow that resembles our idea of white. Yet, snow is white in the sense that if we look at snow, we have the sensation of whiteness, and Locke s semantics and theory of representation captures this fact. Jacovides takes Locke s account of secondary qualities as a shining example of successful philosophy. Locke provides a persuasive and influential solution to the problem of harmonizing modern science and ordinary judgments concerning these properties (185, 204). In perhaps the most interesting narrative of the book (chap. 3), Jacovides argues that what is conceivable, and as a result what is considered possible, is largely contextdependent on Locke s favored scientific theory. As a good corpuscularian, Locke takes action-at-a-distance to be inconceivable. According to Locke s empiricism, all ideas come from sensation or reflection, and if we do not get an idea of something from either of these sources then that thing is literally inconceivable (26; Essay, II.xxiii.29). We can observe objects acting by impulse, so Locke rightly takes the impulse of tiny particles to be a conceivable cause of observable phenomena. More surprisingly, he takes action by impulse to be the only conceivable kind of (body-body) causation. So, for example, the Aristotelian metaphysical explanations that appeal to forms and sensible species are not just false but positively inconceivable (34; Essay, III.x.14). They are inconceivable since, even if there were such things, we are unable to directly observe them through sensation. Any talk of such entities is thereby rendered meaningless on his theory of language. According to Jacovides, Locke constructs his theory of ideas, at least partly, so that it would rule out these Aristotelian metaphysical explanations as meaningless (40, 114). It is Locke s prior commitment to corpuscularianism, then, that leads Locke to conclude alternatives to corpuscularianism are inconceivable. But the story of inconceivability does not stop there. Under the influence of Boyle and corpuscularianism, Locke takes action-at-a-distance to be what Jacovides calls strongly inconceivable in that it conflicts with what we (supposedly) know with certainty is true. However, Locke later, under the influence of Newton and universal gravity, takes actionat-a-distance to merely be what Jacovides calls psychologically inconceivable in that we lack the ideas of how action-at-a-distance could occur. Once he adopts this latter position, the possibility of God super-adding gravitation to matter is opened up, even though it is inconceivable to us how he does so (see The Works of John Locke, 10 vols., [London, 1823], 4:467 68). In this way, Jacovides convincingly argues that what Locke takes to be conceivable and inconceivable depends, at least in large part, on the scientific theory he adopts (34). Jacovides does not disparage Locke for this; instead, he suggests, If we can base a framework of conceivability and intelligibility on our best-justified scientific theories, we will do as well as we can in tracking the true boundaries of possibility (203). 4

5 Another interesting theme in the book is that Locke takes the fundamental laws of nature to explain natural phenomena even though we lack a natural explanation for how those laws work. As just mentioned, Locke thinks we literally have no idea how gravitation works, yet he still appeals to the law of gravitation as a fundamental principle that explains other natural phenomena (Works, 3:282). Similarly, earlier in his career, Locke appeals to action by impulse to be the fundamental principle of nature, yet he even at that time also thinks that we literally have no idea how motion transfers from one object to another (chap. 4). This theme reappears (chap. 6) in relation to the mind-body problem. Locke insists that the properties of matter alone cannot explain how we are able to think and perceive (Essay, IV.x.10). However, as Jacovides points out, Locke still appeals to anatomy and the motion of particles in order to explain our sensations (127; see Essay, II.viii.12 13). So, Locke thinks that we can make progress in explaining natural phenomena even when the fundamental laws are themselves inexplicable. In each of these cases, according to Jacovides s interpretation, God arbitrarily determines the fundamental laws of nature, though we cannot conceive of how he does so (47; see Essay IV.iii.28 29). Locke nonetheless considers these laws explanatory because, though the laws depend on God s will, the laws are systematic and God s intervention is limited (126). The best a scientific theory can do, then, is offer intermediate explanations of natural phenomena. On Locke s view, even with the best scientific theory, we are left with only an incomplete and obscure idea of how the world works. Jacovides, unfortunately, has relatively little to say about Newton s influence on Locke s philosophy. The last two topics canvased, conceivability and intermediate explanations, represent most of what Jacovides has to say about Newton s influence on Locke. He does argue, though, that it is by Locke s influence that Newton adopts Rule 3 for making inductive inferences (89-91). Another omission is any sustained discussion of Locke s view on the method of doing science. In this respect, more discussion of Newton s influence may have been especially appropriate. Peter Anstey (among others) has argued that Locke starts out as a proponent of a Baconian natural history method, but then the success of Newton s physics leads Locke to shift his view about how science should be done to what Anstey calls a mathematical method (Peter Anstey, John Locke and Natural Philosophy, [Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press, 2011]). It is somewhat disappointing, then, that Jacovides does not address this topic at any length. With that said, Locke s Image of the World is an impressive feat of scholarship. The exposition of late scholastic science and the then developing science, along with how these scientific theories influence Locke, is meticulous, clear, and engaging. Jacovides succeeds in his goal to show how the science of Locke s day influences his philosophy. And, because developments of science are advancing so rapidly during the time in which Locke was writing, Jacovides is right to think that Locke represents an especially useful case study for thinking about the extent to which philosophers should be influenced by current science. As a result, the book will be of interest not only to Locke s interpreters but also to those engaged in intellectual history, the history of science, and philosophy of science more generally. Brigham Young University