The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor

Similar documents
Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Is it Reasonable to Rely on Intuitions in Ethics? as relying on intuitions, though I will argue that this description is deeply misleading.

ETHICS. V Department of Philosophy New York University Spring 2006 Tuesdays and Thursdays, 11:00am-12:15pm Kimmel Center 808

Virtue Ethics without Character Traits

Scanlon on Double Effect

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Course Syllabus. Course Description: Objectives for this course include: PHILOSOPHY 333

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

book-length treatments of the subject have been scarce. 1 of Zimmerman s book quite welcome. Zimmerman takes up several of the themes Moore

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Contemporary moral issues

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

INTRODUCTORY HANDOUT PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2004 INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY---ETHICS Professor: Richard Arneson. TAs: Eric Campbell and Adam Streed.

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press, Pp $90.00 (cloth); $28.99

Philosophy HL 1 IB Course Syllabus

Second Term,

(i) Morality is a system; and (ii) It is a system comprised of moral rules and principles.

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

The Singer and the Violinist: When Pro-Abortion Ethicists Are Out of Tune

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 4 points).

Perceptual Normativity and Accuracy. Richard Kenneth Atkins Presented at Central APA, 2011

Why there is no such thing as a motivating reason

Mistaking Category Mistakes: A Response to Gilbert Ryle. Evan E. May

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Quiz 1. Criticisms of consequentialism and Kant. Consequentialism and Nonconsequentialism. Consequentialism in practice. Must Choose Best Possible Act

Lecture Notes Rosalind Hursthouse, Normative Virtue Ethics (1996, 2013) Keith Burgess-Jackson 4 May 2016

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

AS Religious Studies. RSS01 Religion and Ethics 1 Mark scheme June Version: 1.0 Final

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Jeff McMahan, The Ethics of Killing: Problems at the Margins of Life. Oxford: Oxford University Press, xiii pp.

PHIL1010: PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS FORDHAM UNIVERSITY PROFESSOR ROBIN MULLER M/TH: 8:30 9:45AM OFFICE HOURS: BY APPOINTMENT

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

ZAGZEBSKI ON RATIONALITY

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

Problems of Philosophy

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

The Wharton School University of Pennsylvania. Legal Studies LGST 210: Corporate Responsibility and Ethics

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

Courses providing assessment data PHL 202. Semester/Year

Gerd B. Achenbach s Beyond-Method Method.

The Philosophical Review, Vol. 110, No. 3. (Jul., 2001), pp

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Stem Cell Research on Embryonic Persons is Just

Bayesian Probability

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

abstract: What is a temporal part? Most accounts explain it in terms of timeless

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Golden Rule Thomas Carson

Philosophy 1100 Honors Introduction to Ethics

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

2018 Philosophy of Management Conference Paper submission NORMATIVITY AND DESCRIPTION: BUSINESS ETHICS AS A MORAL SCIENCE

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

factors in Bentham's hedonic calculus.

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

Argumentation and Positioning: Empirical insights and arguments for argumentation analysis

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

The philosophy of human rights II: justifying HR. HUMR 5131 Fall 2017 Jakob Elster

An Introduction to Ethics / Moral Philosophy

The ontology of human rights and obligations

UBC - OKANAGAN. COURSE OUTLINE Summer 2013 PHILOSOPHY BIOMEDICAL ETHICS

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

IN THE ETHICS OF ABORTION: Women s Rights, Human Life, and the Question

MORAL DISAGREEMENT CONCERNING ABORTION 1

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

THE INTERNAL TESTIMONY OF THE HOLY SPIRIT: HOW DO YOU KNOW THAT THE BIBLE IS GOD S WORD?

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Critical Appreciation of Jonathan Schaffer s The Contrast-Sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions Samuel Rickless, University of California, San Diego

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Student Relativism: How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love the Bomb Brian Talbot

Writing Essays at Oxford

Psychological and Ethical Egoism

The knowledge argument

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

THEORY AND ANTI-THEORY IN ETHICS. A Two-Day Workshop on Philosophy and the Nature of Morality

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Transcription:

The Future of Practical Philosophy: a Reply to Taylor Samuel Zinaich, Jr. ABSTRACT: This response to Taylor s paper, The Future of Applied Philosophy (also included in this issue) describes Taylor s understanding of the problems that practical philosophy faces; describes Taylor s responses to these problems, and offers criticisms of his arguments. The Problem Taylor s analyses of the concerns brought against practical philosophy are illuminating and insightful. It is fully up to our best traditions. Although his essay begins by rehearsing the recent attention that applied philosophy merits, the paper s real focus is on several serious objections against practical philosophy. Despite the fact that the problems Taylor brings to our attention are perfectly frank and straightforward, they strike right at the heart of applied philosophy. I will list only the major ones. The first major concern points to the anxiety, even among philosophers themselves, that applied philosophy is not rigorous and philosophically shallow. Other worries accuse applied philosophy of utilizing philosophical techniques too removed from reality to employ. This second point especially pertains to those unacquainted with such techniques. The final objection is that applied philosophy has failed to make clear the important relevance moral theories have for everyday life. The unhappy consequence is that applied philosophy is charged with making use of theories that are too abstract. With problems like those just mentioned (and others not mentioned), there is no blinking the fact that applied philosophy faces a host of critics requiring accountability for its methods and techniques. Unfortunately, critics, like facts, are stubborn things. Therefore, it will be very 1

much to our advantage to address these worries straight ahead before they become too engrained in the minds of our critics. Taking up the fight is the purpose of Taylor s article. He attacks the following claims: 1. Practical philosophy lacks philosophical rigor and is shallow. 2. Practical philosophy has little to offer persons grappling with concrete ethical problems because its techniques are too removed from the problems. 3. Practical philosophy has little to offer person grappling with concrete ethical problems because ethical theory is too abstract. In the rest of this reply, I will briefly describe Taylor s objection to each claim. I will also offer, when applicable, criticisms to his objections. Taylor s Objections Taylor s attack of the first claim proceeds in the follow manner. He argues that if practical philosophy is intrinsically shallow or lacking in rigor, then there are no significant works of practical philosophy. However, as Taylor correctly points out, there are significant works of practical philosophy. In fact, as Taylor makes clear, the literature abounds with various examples of works of practical philosophy that exhibit the virtues of rigor and depth. Therefore, it is an unfair to maintain that practical philosophy is intrinsically shallow or lacking in rigor. Although it must be a very confirmed pessimist who would refuse to see the strength of Taylor s first objection, there are still two issues that need to be discussed before we grant Taylor his victory. The first question is this. What is practical philosophy? Taylor gives us four different examples of practical philosophy, but never tells us what it is. This issue needs to be cleared up. The second question is this: what does it mean to say that a work of philosophy is rigorous and not shallow? For example, although Taylor includes Thomson as an example of 2

rigorous philosophy, Michael Tooley accuses Thomson of something a kin to the lack of rigor. For example, from her landmark article, Thomson writes: I am inclined to think also that we shall probably have to agree that the fetus has already become a human person well before birth. Indeed, it comes as a surprise when one first learns how early in its life it begins to acquire human characteristics. 1 Tooley responds in this way: But what do such physiological characteristics have to do with the question of whether the organism is a person? Thomson, partly, I think, because of the unfortunate use of terminology, does not even raise this question. As a result, she virtually takes it for granted that there are some cases in which abortion is positively indecent. 2 Isn t this an example that qualifies as a lack of rigor? Taylor s second objection may be reproduced in this way. If practical philosophy has little to offer people not trained in philosophy, then the techniques philosophers employ are too removed from the problems to be useful to ordinary persons. However, the techniques philosophers employ are not too removed from the problems to be useful to ordinary persons. Therefore, practical philosophy has a lot to offer people not trained in philosophy. The problem with Taylor s second argument is this. Although Taylor makes clear why the examples Thomson uses, e.g., the unconscious violinist, clarifies the abortion issue in a unique way, he does not show why they are not too removed from the problems to be useful to ordinary persons. Here is why I think this is true. First, to truly appreciate Thomson s point, it requires a great deal of training, training not typically available to non-philosophers or even philosophers not trained in ethics. Second, as Taylor points out, although these examples are 1 Judith Jarvis Thomson, A Defense of Abortion, in The Problem of Abortion, ed. Joel Feinberg (Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, Inc., 1984), 173. 2 Michael Tooley, Abortion and Infanticide (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983), 60. R. M. Hare also brings forward a similar complaint just mentioned by Tooley. He argues that philosophers contribute nothing to the solution of an ethical problem by merely basing normative arguments on intuitions. See his article Abortion and the Golden Rule, Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (1975): 201-222. 3

intended to clarify intuitions, one might still ask whose intuitions these examples intend to clarify? Although they may clarify an individual s intuitions that are familiar with techniques like this, my experience has been that such techniques are viewed with suspicion even among individuals who are intelligent. In fact, I have spoken with other philosophers (philosophers whose training is not specifically in ethics) that do not seem to appreciate Thomson s unconscious violinist example. These concerns lead me to think two things. First, the techniques employed by Thomson are too removed for people not trained to understand how they work, and these techniques are not useful to clarify the intuitions of people who do not possess training in practical ethics. Therefore, I conclude that Taylor s second objection is unsound and the second claim stands. Before I move on to the third argument, there is one more minor concern. Taylor remarks that the far-out, cleverly contrived examples are extremely useful in aiding persons to discover what they really think about concrete moral issues, free from the distractions of peripheral concerns or emotional response. I understand and agree with his point about peripheral concerns. However, I don t understand his point about emotional response. My point is this. Typically, when a concrete example is too difficult to understand, the problem may be aggravated by one s own conflicting emotions. However, it has been my own experience that when a cleverly contrived example clarifies my intuitions, it also clarifies, at the same time, my emotions as well. So, whenever I deal with examples like this, I am never free from my emotional responses. Taylor s third objection proceeds in this way. If practical philosophy has little to offer persons not trained in philosophy, then ethical theory is too abstract to be useful to ordinary 4

persons. However, ethical theory is not too abstract to be useful to ordinary persons. Therefore, practical philosophy has a lot to offer persons. Before I discuss why this third argument is unsound, there are two comments about this argument. First, in his defense of the premises of this argument, Taylor makes two points. The first point is something a kin to what may be called the traceability requirement. The idea is this. There are two different kinds of moral principles: basic and derived. This distinction is attributed to Amartya K. Sen. 3 Consider the statement that adultery is wrong. 4 To say that this statement is a derived statement is to say that a person accepts it because he thinks it follows from some other principle. For example, suppose someone believes it is wrong because, and only because, God forbids adultery. Or perhaps it is wrong because, and only because, he believes adultery causes unhappiness, and what causes unhappiness is wrong. Or still, maybe adultery is wrong because adultery breaks a marriage vow promise, and such violations cannot be consistently maintained. The difference between these moral principles is reflected in Taylor s paper. He argues that principles like autonomy or well-being should be based upon a theoretical foundation that justifies and explains such acceptance. In other words, as I understand Taylor, the truth-value or the acceptance of principles like autonomy and so forth, are derived, and must be traced back to a basic moral theory, e.g., Kantianism or utilitarianism, that justifies them. Taylor s second point is this. First, as I mentioned earlier, Taylor again points out that ethical theory should be used to determine which concepts are morally important. Second, Taylor adds that once we establish which concepts are morally important, we must analyze these 3 Amartya K. Sen, The Nature and Classes of Prescriptive Judgments, Philosophical Quarterly 17, no. 66 (1967): 50-51. 4 I borrow the adultery example from Michael Tooley who employs Sen s distinction between basic and derived moral claims. See Tooley, Abortion and Infanticide, 14. 5

concepts to determine what constitutes an autonomous act. Finally, once we have, in a sense, analyzed the concept, we return to our ethical theory to make sure if the initial ethical appeal of such concepts remains. If so, then, as Taylor points out, one can determine what one should do in particular concrete cases. Although there is certain clarity about Taylor s discussion, there are two problems as I have analyzed it. First, if we assume that Taylor s discussion is true, a discussion that I have a great deal of sympathy with, it does nothing to support his argument. Taylor s objection from abstraction is that ethical theory is not too abstract to be useful to ordinary individuals. Unfortunately, his discussion, in a sense, side steps the true focus of his argument. In other words, instead of focusing on why ethical theory is not too abstract to be useful, he focuses on just its usefulness, the usefulness that practical philosophers enjoy. This leads me to my second and final comment. In the elucidation of a moral theory s usefulness, Taylor undermines his own position. Taylor correctly reminds us of just how complicated it is to use an ethical theory. Not only that, he reminds us of how much is required to learn how to properly use an ethical theory, a requirement not so easily attained by non-philosophers or even philosopher s not trained in ethical theory. Because of these concerns, I conclude that Taylor s third objection is unsound, and, as a result, the third claim he analyzes survives his attack as well. Conclusion The aim of this essay was to discuss Taylor s attack of the unfounded suspicion of the goals and techniques of practical philosophy. Although there are problems with his arguments as I have analyzed them, the virtues of his essay are many. Let me elucidate two. Taylor identifies the major objections brought against practical philosophy. This is important in order to clarify 6

what practical philosophy is up against. Additionally, Taylor s critique makes significant strides in the unfounded suspicion that practical philosophy is not a legitimate branch of philosophy. I am relieved that he is on our side! References Hare, R. M. Abortion and the Golden Rule. Philosophy and Public Affairs 4 (1975): 201-222. Sen, Amartya K. The Nature and Classes of Prescriptive Judgments. Philosophical Quarterly 17, no. 66 (1967): 46-62. Thomson, Judith Jarvis. A Defense of Abortion. In The Problem of Abortion, edited by Joel Feinberg, 173-187. Belmont, California: Wadsworth Publishing Company, Inc., 1984. 7

Tooley, Michael. Abortion and Infanticide. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983. 8