Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 1-2, 2006 BOOK REVIEW

Similar documents
An Interview with Alain Badiou Universal Truths and the Question of Religion Adam S. Miller Journal of Philosophy and Scripture

COMMENTS ON SIMON CRITCHLEY S Infinitely Demanding

NOTES ON BEING AND EVENT (PART 4)

Affirmative Dialectics: from Logic to Anthropology

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

NOTES ON BEING AND EVENT (PART 5)

These definitions are built around the idea that

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

Chapter Summaries: Introduction to Christian Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

There might be nothing: the subtraction argument improved

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 1-2, BOOK Review. Jon Roffe

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Editor s Introduction

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

WHAT IS TO BE DONE? ALAIN BADIOU AND THE PRE-EVENTAL 1

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

Badiou's Ethics SAM GILLESPIE

Gilles Deleuze, The Logic of Sense, trans. Mark Lester (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990 [Logique du sens, Minuit, 1969])

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

2. A Roman Catholic Commentary

DESCARTES/LAGAN alain badiou :::. Alain Badiou, Descartes/Lacan, trans. Sigi Jöttkandt and Daniel Collins in Umbr(a): One, No. 1 (1996):

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

Heidegger Introduction

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

RE-THINKING INFINITY: ALAIN BADIOU S BEING & EVENT

Affirmative Judgments: The Sabbath of Deconstruction

[3.] Bertrand Russell. 1

THE PERSISTENCE OF THEORETICAL ANTI- HUMANISM, OR, THE POLITICS OF THE SUBJECT IN ALAIN BADIOU AND SLAVOJ ŽIŽEK 1

Ludwig Feuerbach The Essence of Christianity (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 10/23/13 9:10 AM. Section III: How do I know? Reading III.

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

3 Supplement. Robert Bernasconi

J. Aaron Simmons and Bruce Ellis Benson, The New Phenomenology: A Philosophical Introduction (New York: Bloomsbury, 2013)

John Scottus Eriugena: Analysing the Philosophical Contribution of an Forgotten Thinker

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Masters & Disciples: Institution, Philosophy, Praxis

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

Here and Now: Rethinking philosophy of education

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

15 Does God have a Nature?

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Between the event and democratic materialism

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

Difference between Science and Religion? A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding...

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

EUCHARIST AND KENOSIS

On The Existence of God Thomas Aquinas

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Virtue Ethics. I.Virtue Ethics was first developed by Aristotle in his work Nichomachean Ethics

Alain Badiou: A Pseudo-Maoist Obscurantist

Difference between Science and Religion? A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding...

A Summary of Non-Philosophy

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

The Anarchist Aspects of Nietzsche s Philosophy- Presentation

Difference between Science and Religion? - A Superficial, yet Tragi-Comic Misunderstanding

Simone Weil. Catherine McDonald.

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

The Insubordinate Multiple: A Critique of Badiou s Deleuze by Jonathan Roffe

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

A RESPONSE TO "THE MEANING AND CHARACTERISTICS OF AN AMERICAN THEOLOGY"

THE JOY OF LOVE. THE CHURCH AS THE GUARDIAN OF HUMAN LOVE Maryvale, 21 May 2016

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Count-as-one, Forming-into-one, Unary

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

The Character of Space in Kant s First Critique By Justin Murphy October 16, 2006

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

St. Thomas Aquinas Excerpt from Summa Theologica

The CopernicanRevolution

SOCRATES, PIETY, AND NOMINALISM. love is one of the most well known in the history of philosophy. Yet some fundamental

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

POLI 342: MODERN WESTERN POLITICAL THOUGHT

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Luce Irigaray. To Be Born. Genesis of a New Human Being

Introduction to Technical Communications 21W.732 Section 2 Ethics in Science and Technology Formal Paper #2

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

Further Reflection on True Successors and Traditions

Transcription:

Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 2, no. 1-2, 2006 BOOK REVIEW Keeping the faith: on being Good and how not to be Evil Alex Ling Alain Badiou, Ethics: An Essay on the Understanding of Evil, trans. Peter Hallward, New York, Verso, 2001. ISBN: 1-85984-435-9 Every truth, Badiou tells us in his Ethics, deposes constituted knowledges, and thus opposes opinions. For what we call opinions are representations without truth, the anarchic debris of circulating knowledge (E 50). Being then fully aware that the book review as little more than an at best vaguely nuanced species of opinion is fundamentally beneath the true and the false (E 51), it goes without saying that what follows is, veracity aside, not in the least bit true. That said, Ethics occupies a decidedly singular position within Alain Badiou s oeuvre. For starters, it s the only of his thus far translated major theoretical works which might be read, for the most part, without immediate recourse to Being and Event (although it does serve as something of a necessary addendum to his magnum opus). This rather welcome fact is due in part to Peter Hallward s introduction (which provides a concise overview of Badiou s ethical and philosophical project) and, more generally, to Badiou s concerted effort to eschew all overtly technical writing (Ethics was ostensibly written for a high school audience). Further, it is arguably (again, amongst his translated works) his most Lacanian book (or rather the book which thinks most closely alongside Jacques Lacan s antiphilosophy). Lastly, it is very probably, in a career distinguished by polemy and invective, his most immediately provocative work. Indeed, it is difficult not to be at least momentarily taken aback by a book which begins by launching into a virulent attack against the contemporary discourse of human rights and whose axial assertion is that the whole ethical predication based upon recognition of the other should be purely and simply abandoned (E 25). In point of fact the whole of contemporary ethics derisively designated by the author as the ethical www.cosmosandhistory.org 359

360 COSMOS AND HISTORY ideology appears in Badiou s eyes to be little more than a vast synonym for negativity: today s ethical ideology is a fundamentally statist edifice whose principle role is to [prohibit] any idea, any coherent project of thought, settling instead for overlaying unthought and anonymous situations with mere humanitarian prattle (E 32-33). The task is then, reductively speaking, to invent a new ethics which would radically circumvent the state s authority. And, by happy coincidence, it is precisely this sort of circumvention that Badiou s philosophy has been offering all along. Setting himself then firmly at odds with the dominant ethics of otherness Badiou contrarily asserts his own ethics as fundamentally of the subject and accordingly (it means the same thing) as not of the other but of the same. Of course we need remember here that for Badiou the subject is neither transcendental nor substantial, but is rather a finite local configuration albeit one touched by immortality convoked through an (aleatory, unknowable) event. This means precisely (once again, in Badiouian terms) that his subjective ethics is equivalent to an ethic of truth(s) which is what the event gives rise to or of the same which, emanating from the situational void (and thus from what is in-different to all situations and hence properly universal) is what truth is. To this effect Badiou s is a philosophy that strictly opposes any a priori concept of ethicality: there is no ethics in general he tells us, there are only eventually ethics of processes by which we treat the possibilities of a situation (E 16). Further, as Badiou s subject only comes into being by virtue of a singular event an event which is strictly immanent to a particular situation and subsists only by maintaining a militant fidelity to the truth of the event, his subjective ethics is then ultimately a situated ethics, that is, an ethics of the situation. In sum and in stark contrast to the contemporary understanding of ethics as natural, objective, a priori, a-situational and fundamentally of the other Badiou s ethics are of the event, of the subject, of truth, of the situation, and of the same. Clearly then the core of Badiou s ethics is nothing other than the evental prescription of the subject, that is, the absolute necessity to remain faithful to a fidelity to continue being a militant of truth which he rather nicely summarizes in a single imperative: continuez! (in which one should of course hear Lacan s ethical maxim ne pas céder sur son désir : don t give way on your desire). Simply and one cannot stress this point too strongly outside of the fact of the event, there is no subject, nor truth, nor ethics there is solely difference (which is simply what is) and an otherwise inconsequential biological species counted as human, a biped without feathers, whose charms are not obvious. (E 12) So then in light of his theory of subjectivation Badiou accordingly reinterprets Lacan s ethical imperative as the necessity to seize in your being that which has seized and broken you (E 47), to remain faithful to an event, to hold on at all costs to a truth and continue being a subject. Of course, the reader of Lacan would likely wonder precisely what is to be found here that is new? Certainly the literally exceptional status of Badiou s ethics resonates with Lacan s own distinction between the moral and the ethical between Creon s Law and Antigone s desire, between the good and the beautiful insofar as morality, for Lacan, fundamentally serves to reinforce/reinscribe the statist order (qua service of goods ) while ethicality is by contrast necessarily anti-statist (owing to the fact

Ethics 361 that, as an ethical subject, we must first give ourself over to the cause that animates us, a cause desire; drive which is in itself radically antithetical to order as such). Clearly then we are once more presented with those familiar divisions between ethical radicality and moral stasis, between revolutionary praxis and conservative polity, between truth and the knowledge through which it punches a hole. And yet it also at this precise point that we discern a clear break with Lacan who we should remember is not only for Badiou an antiphilosopher par excellence (witness the role played here by desire and drive) but also the term s true father (le nom du père) insofar as Badiou, by virtue of his decidedly non-lacanian (non-cartesian) conception of the subject, necessarily presents something of a recession of orders, seeing the ethical as coextensive with (indeed, equivalent to) the good, thereby leaving morality (which is in Badiou s thinking implicitly tied up with that truthless realm of opinions ) lying necessarily beneath both good and evil. Thus the beautiful descends to the good and the good to invoke Badiou s reading of that other archetypal antiphilosopher Saint Paul falls from grace. If this however seems something of a negative gesture, we should remember that one of the great virtues of Badiou s philosophy is on the contrary its fundamental positivity, which is something we can (unexpectedly perhaps) clearly discern in his conception of evil as an effect of the power of truth (E 61). 1 Indeed, this simple progression from good to evil stands in marked opposition to the ethical ideology he so despises, in which good might be solely derived as an after-effect of evil (such good depriving itself of positive content in its reduction to the sole function of preventing evil) and which accordingly thinks the only thing that can really happen to someone is death (35) (such negative movement accounting for the intrinsic nihilism of, for example, the discourse of human rights). Simply, if the good is ultimately truth, then evil is at base that which has a negative effect on truth; it is the corruption, in one way or another, of truth. This of course means that, as with the good, evil is knotted to the evental subject, or, to paraphrase Voltaire, Badiou s ethics of truth means in the end that every subject is guilty of all the good he did not do. Thus the human animal, along with its concomitant predilections be they munificent, disinterested, or just plain nasty exists, outside of the embrace of the event, fundamentally beneath good and evil. On the plus side (at least for those aspiring immortals among us) Badiou has kindly gone ahead and determined there to be but three dimensions three faces of evil, which he designates, not without a certain dramatic flair, as betrayal, terror and disaster. Without going into too-lengthy an exegesis, the first face of evil (betrayal) denotes the failure of a subject to live up to a fidelity which is it should be noted not simply renunciation but rather the determined act of becoming the enemy of that truth (E 79) while the second (terror, or simulacrum) presents itself as the gross imitation of the event, involving the convocation not of the void (whose in-difference allows for the universality of a truth) but rather of the plenitude of a situation. Badiou s detailed example here is the 1. As Badiou states, my philosophy desires affirmation. I want to fight for; I want to know what I have for the good and to put it to work, On Evil: An Interview with Alain Badiou, Cabinet, no. 5, 2001, <http:// www.cabinetmagazine.org/issues/5/alainbadiou.php>.

362 COSMOS AND HISTORY Nazi National Socialist Revolution which aimed to bring a particular community i.e. the German people as an abstract whole toward their true destiny (thereby avoiding the situational hole to instead consider its whole, or rather, its full particularity), the construction of such a whole being only possible by literally voiding what surrounds it. (E 74) The third and final face of evil that of disaster, or totalization involves the ontologization of the event : put simply, no truth-process can name all the elements of the situation, for there must always remain at least one point that the truth cannot force (E 85), which is precisely the unnameable element (of a truth), the pure real of the situation (E 86). Evil is then in this third instance the forcing of the unnameable. 2 In sum, evil exists, après l événement, in three guises: betrayal the negation of the ethical imperative in the form of evental treachery terror the convocation of the plenitude of the situation (as distinct from its void) and disaster or the totalization of a truth through the forcing of its unnameable. In the final analysis then Badiou s ethics combines under its imperative ( continuez! ) those resources of discernment (do not fall for simulacra), of courage (do not give up), and of moderation (do not get carried away to the extremes of Totality). (E 91) Of these resources which, we might note in passing, are fundamentally both subjective (that is anobjective) and asubject-ive (that is human) the first, discernability, presents the most immediate problem: insofar as the event is radically unknowable there remains the dilemma of precisely how to discern when we are truly immortalized in its wake, which is to say, how do we know when we are subject to good (truth) or subject to evil (the simulacrum of truth), or, conversely, to neither (and hence unsubjected )? This problem has in one way or another been raised in most considerations of Badiou s Ethics, 3 and indeed Badiou himself implicitly questions the resource of discernability at the same time as he raises it when he proposes something of an extended ethical maxim in the form of keep going even when you have lost the thread, when you no longer feel caught up in the process, when the event itself has become obscure, when its name is lost, or when it seems that it may have named a mistake, if not a simulacrum. (E 79) Let us then reconsider the problem in terms strictly immanent to evil: do we not encounter in the intricately linked evils of betrayal and terror a potential paradox insofar as in our mili- 2. In the amorous situation for example it is sexual jouissance which cannot be named. Likewise, in the scientific situation non-contradiction is the unnameable (as Gödel s theory of incompletion dictates). Incidentally, one finds here another fundamental distinction between Badiou s philosophy and Lacan s antiphilosophy: whilst Lacan s truth procedure (i.e. the act proper) involves the foundation of a radically new situation, for Badiou a truth must be the truth of a given situation, that is, it must retain ties to the original situation (an absolute overhaul being nothing other than this third instance of evil, i.e. the totalization of a truth). 3. For example Jean-Jacques Lecercle remarks that I can find hardly anything within his system to protect me from Heidegger s mistake, when he took the National Socialist revolution for an event, and thought that a new process of truth had started. The risk is that the eventuality of the event will eventually be left to individual decision, Cantor, Lacan, Mao, Même Combat: The Philosophy of Alain Badiou, Radical Philosophy, vol. 93, 1999, p. 12. Simon Critchley likewise asks how and in virtue to what is one to distinguish a true event from a false event? That is, I don t see how one the basis of Badiou s criteria we could ever distinguish a true event from a false event, Demanding Approval: On the Ethics of Alain Badiou, Radical Philosophy, vol. 100, 2000, p. 23.

Ethics 363 tant desire to be ethical subjects might we not all too easily betray a truth for fear of it being a simulacrum or contrarily remain faithful to a simulacrum for fear of betrayal? In point of fact the question is less one of discernability and more properly one of indiscernability, for insofar as truth need by definition be radically subtracted from knowledge it is accordingly relegated to the realm of pure subjectivity, which is to say, pure faith the subjective faith involved in declaring an indiscernible event to be or not to be and this pure faith is ultimately one and the same as that faith which constitutes the bond between betrayal and terror (namely the conviction or lack thereof that an event is in fact an event and not its simulacrum). Let us put it yet another way: truth, Badiou tells us, as contradistinct to knowledge, is utterly unforeseeable and solely a matter of forcing; the true becomes so only by virtue of a tireless militancy, the direct result of which (this absolute reliance on forcing) being that Badiou s ethics under those resources of discernment and courage seems to have a decidedly an-ethical element (namely the potential indiscernability between event and simulacra, between betrayal and terror), which is finally to say that ethics is in a certain sense beneath itself. 4 So where does this leave Badiou s Ethics? Certainly he exposes and brings the reader a long way from the fallacy of our contemporary ethical doxa (where ethics appears objective, natural, a priori, of the other, etc.) as an ideology incapable of any conception of the good yet flush with the knowledge of suffering. And yet his own ethics (of the same, of the event, of truths, of the subject, of the real, of the good, of the situation, etc.) seem to rest on to give a different accent to those final, immortal words of Samuel Beckett s The Unnamable the indiscernibly fine line which separates I can t go on from I ll go on. 5 Perhaps then it all finally comes down, as Deleuze might have said, to a matter of taste, for when all is said and done Badiou s properly decisive elements both subjective (in deciding an answer to the question to betray or not to betray? ) and constitutive (in his philosophy s overall militant immediacy) are arguably major drawcards of his thought. Indeed, insofar as Badiou ultimately presents little to no room for hesitation there is no what should I do?, only this is what I will do the fact that there is an element of ethical indiscernability or an ethical real appears to be at worst a necessary evil supplementary to a greater good (truth, creation, affirmation, etc.), at best the locus of 4. In her Ethics of the Real: Kant, Lacan, Alenka Zupančič makes a similar point regarding this an-ethical element: the heart of all ethics is something which is not itself ethical (nor is it non-ethical ) that is to say, it has nothing to do with the register of ethics. This something goes by several different names : for Lacan, it is the Real ; for Badiou, the Event, Alenka Zupančič, Ethics of the Real: Kant, Lacan, London, Verso, 2000, p. 235. It seems to me, however, that the real importance of the an-ethical kernel of the ethical lies properly in its subjective component, and thus not in the event itself but in its retroactive subjective recognition (i.e. the evental decision). 5. Samuel Beckett, Three Novels by Samuel Beckett: Molloy, Malone Dies, The Unnamable, New York, Grove Press, 1991, p. 414. Of course, as his philosophy has evolved Badiou has made a number of rectifications to his ethics (L éthique was after all published in France in 1993). The reactionary and obscurantist figures, for example, have to an extent respectively replaced those of treachery and disaster as properly subjective positions, whilst the unnameable has since been abandoned as being a [concession] to the pervasive moralism of the 1980s and 1990s, Alain Badiou, Beyond Formalisation: An Interview, Angelaki, vol. 8, no. 2, 2003, p. 133.

364 COSMOS AND HISTORY freedom itself. Indeed, this indiscernible element in truth complements rather nicely the idea of evil as totalization, an evil whose origins might be (theoretically, at least) traced all the way to Badiou s fundamental axiom (contra Parmenides) that the One (qua absolute) is not. Put plainly, truth, insofar as it obliges subjective indiscernability, is simply nothing without risk. Indeed if indiscernability, forced through an act of pure decision, marks Badiou s rigorous and, not insignificantly, axiomatic philosophical enterprise with a certain freedom (admittedly tempered somewhat by one s subsequent slavish devotion to the event and indifference to self-interest), it is only because his doctrine of the event stamps his world with an element of chance: his is a Mallarméan philosophy of dice-throws, of infinity and immortality, one that thinks radical newness and absolute change. And fundamentally necessarily his is a hazardous philosophy, a philosophy of risks. Indeed, in the final analysis, it is perhaps this fact, this absolute unknown, which alone endows the immortal subject with a certain humanity. Alex Ling University of Melbourne