Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Similar documents
Theories of propositions

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

An argument against descriptive Millianism

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Coordination Problems

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Analyticity and reference determiners

ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI Scope of Semantic Innocence

sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

Discovering Identity

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

Kripke s revenge. Appeared in Philosophical Studies 128 (2006),

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

PROPOSITIONAL ATTITUDE REPORTS

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

(2480 words) 1. Introduction

Predict the Behavior. Leonardo Caffo. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action. University of Milan - Department of Philosophy

15. Russell on definite descriptions

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Predict the Behavior. Propositional Attitudes and Philosophy of Action

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Frode Bjørdal ON BELIEFS. 1. Introduction

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Informative Identities in the Begriffsschrift and On Sense and Reference

Scott Soames: Understanding Truth

The Objects of Belief and Credence

Propositions and Attitude Ascriptions: A Fregean Account

Reflexivity NATHAN SALMON*

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Foundations of Logic, Language, and Mathematics

Direct and Indirect Belief

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. declarative sentence, or the content of a representational mental state,

The normativity of content and the Frege point

Propositions as Cognitive Event Types

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Keeping track of individuals

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

The Metaphysics of Propositions. In preparing to give a theory of what meanings are, David Lewis [1970] famously wrote:

Relative Thoughts. Dr. Sanna Hirvonen Junior visiting fellow, Universita Degli Studi di Milano

On possibly nonexistent propositions

Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts

SALMON TRAPPING. Takashi Yagisawa. [Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57.2 (1997), ] I. Introduction

Presupposition and Rules for Anaphora

Varieties of Apriority

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

COMPOSITIONALITY AND BELIEVING THAT

Marcus on Belief and Belief in the Impossible *

Response. Paul Johnson University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign

Sense, Communication, and Rational Engagement Imogen Dickie and Gurpreet Rattan, University of Toronto

Horwich and the Liar

Why the Traditional Conceptions of Propositions can t be Correct

Can We Think Nonsense? by Christian Michel

Believing Epistemic Contradictions

Subjective Logic: Logic as Rational Belief Dynamics. Richard Johns Department of Philosophy, UBC

Language, Meaning, and Information: A Case Study on the Path from Philosophy to Science Scott Soames

Russell on Denoting. G. J. Mattey. Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156. The concept any finite number is not odd, nor is it even.

Class 33 - November 13 Philosophy Friday #6: Quine and Ontological Commitment Fisher 59-69; Quine, On What There Is

Phil 413: Problem set #1

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Narrow Content and Utterance Meaning

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

A Liar Paradox. Richard G. Heck, Jr. Brown University

Russell: On Denoting

Epistemic Modals Seth Yalcin

russell s theory of propositions

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

The free will defense

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

Interpretation: Keeping in Touch with Reality. Gilead Bar-Elli. 1. In a narrow sense a theory of meaning (for a language) is basically a Tarski-like

Class #7 - Russell s Description Theory

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

Now consider a verb - like is pretty. Does this also stand for something?

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

On Identity Statements: In Defense of a Sui Generis View

The problem of evil & the free will defense

Chadwick Prize Winner: Christian Michel THE LIAR PARADOX OUTSIDE-IN

Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Constructing the World

Transcription:

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions Jeff Speaks phil 43916 November 3, 2014 1 The puzzle of necessary consequence........................ 1 2 Structured intensions................................. 2 3 Frege s puzzle..................................... 4 4 Kripke s puzzle.................................... 5 5 Richard s puzzle................................... 6 1 The puzzle of necessary consequence Our theory of attitude ascriptions so far holds that the semantic value of a that-clause is the intension of the embedded sentence. Given that the intension of a sentence is the set of worlds in which it is true (or, equivalently, the characteristic function of this set), it follows from this theory that the following principle is true: The closure of belief under necessary equivalence If S and S* have the same intension (are true in exactly the same worlds), then A believes that S is true if and only if A believes that S* is. Can you think of any plausible counterexamples to this principle? What pairs of sentences have the same intension? This is just the beginning of the problems. First, the following principle appears very plausible: The distribution of belief over conjunction If A believes that S and S* is true, then so is A believes that S and A believes that S*. But now suppose that we have a pair of sentences, S and S*, and suppose that S entails S*. Then the following two sentences will have the same intension: 1

S S and S* Put all of this together, and what you get is: The closure of belief under necessary consequence If S entails S*, then if A believes that S is true, so is A believes that S*. Can you see how this follows from the closure of belief under necessary equivalence and the distribution of belief over conjunction? This closure of belief under necessary consequence is wildly implausible. The problem here (which, in this form, is due to Soames (1985, 1988)) can be brought out in two ways: (1) Necessary truths are necessary consequences of everything. So, anyone who has any beliefs at all believes all necessary truths. (So, for example, everyone believes every mathematical truth.) (2) Every proposition is a necessary consequence of a necessary falsehood. So, if anyone believed a necessary falsehood, they would believe every proposition. But no one believes every proposition. So no one believes any necessary falsehoods. (So, for example, no one has ever had any false mathematical beliefs.) Note that the problems here do not only arise for agents who fail to see what follows from their beliefs. The example of the paradox of the preface. It seems hard to deny that belief distributes over conjunction. So it seems that we must deny the closure of belief under necessary equivalence. But to do that within a compositional semantics, we have to deny that the semantic value of a that-clause is the set of worlds in which the embedded sentence is true. And to do that, we need to revise our lexical entry for that. 2 Structured intensions We have already discussed non-extensional contexts: nodes which are such that substitution of expressions with the same semantic value can change truth-value. What we have here, it seems, is a node which is such that substitution of sentences with the same intension can change truth-value. Such contexts are sometimes called hyper-intensional. Our former view of that was: [ CP that S] M,w,i,g ={w*:w* W and S M,w,i,g =1} 2

How might we do better? We already know how to understand the intension of a sentence. But we might also define the notion of a structured intension. Take a simple sentence like Pavarotti walks. The intension of this sentence is the set of worlds in which Pavarotti walks. But we also know the intensions of the words that make up this sentence: Pavarotti w = Pavarotti walks w = f:f(w) = {x : x walks in w} (Here for simplicity I ignore the role of time.) Then we might represent the structured intension of this sentence as the ordered pair <Pavarotti,f:f(w)= {x : x walks in w} > This is just a sketch of a theory; it will have to get more complicated to represent the structured intensions of sentences with more than two leaves. But even this simple sketch is enough to show how we might distinguish between the structured intensions of sentences which are true in just the same worlds, and hence share the same intension. And this promises to help with hyper-intensional contexts, if we revise our view that the meaning of that so that [ CP that S] M,w,i,g = the structured intension of S relative to M and g To state this more precisely, we d have to come up with some canonical way of deriving and representing structured intensions the informal sketch above will be enough for our purposes. To fix the problem, we also have to revise our lexical entry for believes. Our former view was that a belief ascription is true iff the embedded sentence is true in every world in the subject s belief set. But that view of believes leads immediately to the problems discussed above, whatever our view of that. Can you think of how we might state the lexical entry for believes to fit the view that belief is a relation between subjects and structured intensions? One might object that this view makes too many distinctions between beliefs, and hence fails to capture important generalizations which we might want to capture. Suppose, for example, that we want a theory which explains what it is rational for a given subject to believe or do, and suppose that we know that one subject believes the structured intension of S or S* and another believes the structured intension of It is not the case that not-s and not-s*. These will be different structured intensions. But it seems that the rational commitments of the two subjects will be the same. That is something that the intensions theory captures but which the structured intensions theory does not (at least not without further elaboration). 3

3 Frege s puzzle But a problem remains, which was noticed by Frege (1892/1960). The problem is that very similar attitude ascriptions, like Bob believes that Hesperus is visible in the morning. Bob believes that Phosphorus is visible in the morning. or Lois believes that Superman can fly. Lois believes that Clark Kent can fly. seem as though they can differ in truth-value. This is often called Frege s puzzle (though other, related problems also go by that name). Is this a problem for our attempt to explain that-clauses in terms of structured intensions? It is if two names which refer to the same object have the same intension; and, in the semantic theory we ve been using, they will. Could we revise that theory so that such names differ in intension? What would this involve? Frege tried to solve this problem by distinguishing between sense and reference, and explained this distinction as follows: The reference of a proper name is the object itself which we designate by its means; the idea, which we have in that case, is wholly subjective; in between lies the sense, which is indeed no longer subjective like the idea, but is yet not the object itself. The following analogy will perhaps clarify these relationships. Somebody observes the Moon through a telescope. I compare the Moon itself to the reference; it is the object of the observation, mediated by the real image projected by the object glass in the interior of the telescope, and by the retinal image of the observer. The former I compare to the sense, the latter is like the idea or experience. The optical image in the telescope is indeed one-sided and dependent upon the standpoint of observation; but it is still objective, inasmuch as it can be used by several observers. At any rate it could be arranged for several to use it simultaneously. But each one would have his own retinal image. ( On sense and reference ) How might we incorporate this distinction into our semantics? One idea, which is close to what Frege thought, is that we can think of the semantic values of that-clauses as structured entitites (as the proponent of structured intensions thought) but ones whose constituents are, not intensions, but Fregean senses. 4

We would then have to revise our view of the lexicon. The lexicon will now assign to expressions, not intensions, but Fregean senses. Those Fregean senses will determine intensions so much of our semantics can continue to work as it has. It is reasonable to ask for more information about what Fregean senses are, and about when two expressions have the same sense. Frege answered the latter question using (roughly) the following principle: Frege s criterion If it is possible to understand two sentences S and S while (after reflection) taking different attitudes toward their truth-values, then S and S differ in sense. Then we can say that e and e differ in sense iff there are two sentences S and S, which differ only in the substitution of e and e, and differ in sense. How would you give the intension of believes and that, on a Fregean view? A problem: Frege s theory might explain substitution failures while failing to explain much more common cases of substitution success. 4 Kripke s puzzle However, even if we make use of Fregean senses, and these are otherwise unproblematic, a puzzle presented by Kripke (1979) remains. We can think of the puzzle as based on the following four initially plausible principles: 1. Weak disquotation: If a competent speaker on reflection sincerely assents to S, then that speaker believes that S. 2. Reverse disquotation: If a speaker believes that S then, on reflection, that speaker will (if given the chance) sincerely assent to S. 3. Translation: if a sentence expresses a truth in one language, then its translation into another language also expresses a truth (in that language). 4. Contradiction: if you have a pair of contradictory beliefs, it is always possible to discover this on the basis of reflection on those beliefs. Using the example of puzzling Pierre, Kripke argues that (1)-(3) are inconsistent. By (1), we can derive the truth of Pierre croit que Londres est jolie. Then by (3) we can derive the truth of the translation of this sentence, namely 5

Pierre believes that London is pretty. But by (2) we can derive the truth of Pierre does not believe that London is pretty. which is a contradiction. So one of (1)-(3) must be false. One might think that this is problem to do with translation, and hence that we can solve the problem by rejecting (3). There are two problems with this response to the puzzle: (3) is very plausible. Kripke s example of Peter and Paderewski shows that we can generate the puzzle without (3). A second version of the puzzle: the case of Pierre shows that (1) and (3) are inconsistent, not just with (2), but with (4). Kripke does not himself take a stand on how to resolve these puzzles. One plausible reply to the puzzles is to reject (2) and (4). But if we do this, that weakens the case for a Fregean approach to that-clauses for three reasons: (a) It seems that the examples which we used to argue against the structured intensions approach, and for the Fregean approach, relied implicitly on principles like (2) and (4). (b) It seems that Frege s criterion is going to lead to the implausible result that London is pretty and Londres est jolie differ in meaning. (c) The problem of substitution success returns with a vengeance. Imagine trying to report Peter s Paderewski beliefs. 5 Richard s puzzle Richard (1983) gives an example in which Bill is in a phone booth which, unbeknownst to him, is being approached by a steamroller. Sally is talking in the phone to Bill while looking at the phone booth but does not realize that Bill is the person in the phone booth at which she is looking. Sally accepts He is in danger but rejects You are in danger. Then, by Fregean lights, it looks like (i) is true and (ii) false out of Sally s mouth, despite he and you both having Bill as their semantic value: 6

(i) I believe that he is in danger. (ii) I believe that you are in danger. But suppose that Bill tells Sally that someone is looking at him gesturing wildly (unbeknownst to him, this is Sally). Then the following seems true out of Sally s mouth: (iii) The person waving at you believes that you are in danger. But (iii) entails (ii) which means that (ii) must, contra our earlier view, be true. Does the fact that (ii) is true pose a problem for the Fregean? References Gottlob Frege, 1892/1960. On Sense and Reference. In Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, edited by Peter Geach and Max Black, 56 78. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Saul Kripke, 1979. A Puzzle About Belief. In Meaning and Use, edited by Avishai Margalit, 239 283. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company. Mark Richard, 1983. Direct Reference and Ascriptions of Belief. Journal of Philosophical Logic 12(4):425 52. Scott Soames, 1985. Lost Innocence. Linguistics and Philosophy 8:1:59 72. Scott Soames, 1988. Direct Reference, Propositional Attitudes, and Semantic Content. In Propositions and Attitudes, edited by Nathan Salmon and Scott Soames, 197 239. Oxford: Oxford University Press. 7