Class 2 - Foundationalism

Similar documents
Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2010

Class 3 - The Cogito, Certainty, and Sense Experience Descartes, Meditations Two and Three

Descartes and Foundationalism

Class #5-6: Modern Rationalism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mathematics

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

The British Empiricism

Chapter 18 David Hume: Theory of Knowledge

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2011

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 1b Knowledge

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

Class #9: Kant Our in class discussion of these notes will be lamentably abbreviated, focused on the first three sections.

Hume s An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding

The CopernicanRevolution

Class #3 - Illusion Descartes, from Meditations on First Philosophy Descartes, The Story of the Wax Descartes, The Story of the Sun

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

PHILOSOPHY OF KNOWLEDGE & REALITY W E E K 7 : E P I S T E M O L O G Y - K A N T

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

David Hume ( )

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Intro to Philosophy. Review for Exam 2

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

Epistemology. Diogenes: Master Cynic. The Ancient Greek Skeptics 4/6/2011. But is it really possible to claim knowledge of anything?

PHILOSOPHICAL RAMIFICATIONS: THEORY, EXPERIMENT, & EMPIRICAL TRUTH

SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS Part III SCIENTIFIC EPISTEMOLOGY? David Tin Win α & Thandee Kywe β. Abstract

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Introduction to Philosophy

Reid Against Skepticism

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

Class #5: Modern Rationalism I, Descartes and Leibniz

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

Syllabus. Primary Sources, 2 edition. Hackett, Various supplementary handouts, available in class and on the course website.

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Hume. Hume the Empiricist. Judgments about the World. Impressions as Content of the Mind. The Problem of Induction & Knowledge of the External World

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Introduction to Philosophy. Spring 2017

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

CHAPTER III KANT S APPROACH TO A PRIORI AND A POSTERIORI

Definitions of Gods of Descartes and Locke

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

GROUP A WESTERN PHILOSOPHY (40 marks)

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2012

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

It is not at all wise to draw a watertight

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

1/9. Leibniz on Descartes Principles

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Kant s Misrepresentations of Hume s Philosophy of Mathematics in the Prolegomena

From Descartes to Locke. Consciousness Knowledge Science Reality

Critique of Cosmological Argument

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Introduction to Philosophy

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Unit 4 Notes Humean Skepticism (With Guest Appearances from Thomas Reid and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz)

Kant and his Successors

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

SQUARING THE CARTESIAN CIRCLE

History of Modern Philosophy. Hume ( )

What does it mean if we assume the world is in principle intelligible?

Notes on Bertrand Russell s The Problems of Philosophy (Hackett 1990 reprint of the 1912 Oxford edition, Chapters XII, XIII, XIV, )

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

FACULTY OF ARTS B.A. Part II Examination,

Cartesian Rationalism

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT David Hume: The Origin of Our Ideas and Skepticism about Causal Reasoning

The Copernican Shift and Theory of Knowledge in Immanuel Kant and Edmund Husserl.

CONTENTS. CHAPTER 1. CHAPTER II. THE PROBLEM OF DESCARTES, -

Cartesian Rationalism

Class 18 - Against Abstract Ideas Berkeley s Principles, Introduction, (AW ); (handout) Three Dialogues, Second Dialogue (AW )

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

The Problem of the External World

Kant s Transcendental Exposition of Space and Time in the Transcendental Aesthetic : A Critique

Hume, skepticism, and the search for foundations

From Brains in Vats.

Common sense dictates that we can know external reality exists and that it is generally correctly perceived via our five senses

A. Aristotle D. Descartes B. Plato E. Hume

Introduction to Philosophy

Course Description and Objectives:

René Descartes ( )

Transcription:

2 3 Philosophy 2 3 : Intuitions and Philosophy Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class 2 - Foundationalism I. Rationalist Foundations What follows is a rough caricature of some historical themes in epistemology. The account is not so much false as it is broad. But it will serve our narrative purposes. Some of this discussion will be familiar to most of you, but I hope to get us on equal footing to start the course. In the modern era, there were two kinds of foundationalist projects. The rationalists, epitomized by Descartes, sought to secure knowledge on the basis of human reasoning. The empiricists, epitomized by Locke and Hume, sought to secure knowledge on the basis of human sense experience. Both kinds of projects are, of course, failures. Our interest in the projects concerns, first, the methods and goals of their proponents, and, second, the specific reasons for the inadequacies of their approaches. We start with Descartes. Most students begin studying Descartes by reading the Meditations. Descartes motivates the Meditations by presenting three skeptical hypotheses: sense illusion, dreaming, the demon deceiver. Having called into doubt apparently all of his beliefs, Descartes seeks a single Archimedean point on which to construct his new edifice of knowledge. The starting point, as all readers of the second Meditation know, is his knowledge of his mind: I am, I exist, as long as I am thinking. This single starting point is well-known as the Cogito. In the rest of the Meditations, Descartes unpacks himself, peering into the mind which is his essence. In his mind, free of the distractions of his physical body, he finds, first, a method of securing all the rest of his knowledge, and, further, all the details of that new structure. Descartes s edifice, it turns out, contains elements of both the new Galilean science as well as some orthodox religious beliefs (though the religious dogma was not uncontroversial to the theologians of his era). Our central concern in discussing Descartes regards his method. Descartes s positive project is presented somewhat differently, and most accessibly for our methodological purposes, at the end of the replies to the second objections. Here, Descartes distinguishes between the analytic mode of presentation he used in the Meditations and the synthetic mode, with which we are most familiar in geometry and logic. Analysis shows the true way by which a thing has been discovered methodically, and, as it were, a priori, so that were the reader willing to follow it and to pay sufficient attention to everything, he will no less perfectly understand a thing and render it his own than had he himself discovered it. However, analysis possesses nothing with which to compel belief in a less attentive or hostile reader, for if he fails to pay attention to the least thing among those that this mode [ratio] proposes, the necessity of its conclusions is not apparent; and it often hardly touches at all on many things that nevertheless ought to be carefully noted, since they are obvious

Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 2 to anyone who is sufficiently attentive. Synthesis, on the other hand, indeed clearly demonstrates its conclusions by an opposite way, where the investigation is conducted, as it were, a posteriori (although it is often the case there that this proof is more a priori than it is in the analytic mode). And it uses a long series of definitions, postulates, axioms, theorems, and problems, so that if something in what follows is denied, this mode may at once point out that it is contained in what went before. And thus it wrests from the reader his assent, however hostile and obstinate he may be. But this mode is not as satisfactory as the other one nor does it satisfy the minds of those who desire to learn, since it does not teach the way in which the thing was discovered (92). The central difference between synthetic presentations of geometry and metaphysics, Descartes claims, is that the foundational claims in geometry gain universal agreement, whereas the metaphysical foundations are less obvious to the folk. The firmness of the foundation of Descartes s edifice is already in question. II. Euclid s Foundations To better understand the structure of Descartes s synthetic presentation, it might be useful to look at Euclid s Elements, on which it is based. There is an excellent, perspicuous version on line. The Elements starts with definitions, adding five geometric postulates and five more general logical axioms, or common notions. From the postulates and axioms, all the remaining propositions are derived. The definitions are mainly unproblematic, since they do not assert the truth or existence of any of the objects to which they refer. Definition 12 says that an acute angle is an angle less than a right angle. It does not claim that there are any acute angles or right angles. It can be taken as the claim that if there are such angles, then the acute ones are less than the right ones. This conditional (or Boolean) interpretation may be better seen in contemporary logic. ( x)( y)[(ax Ay Cx Ry) Lxy] The common notions in Euclid s Elements are not particularly geometric. They are more properly called logical. To call the common notions into question would be appropriate in a Cartesian project of founding all of our knowledge. But, since the logical axioms apply so broadly, any questions about them would not be worries about the geometry of the Euclidean project, but about our beliefs more generally. Concerns about the foundational project of The Elements really focuses, first, on the status of the geometric postulates, and, second, on the derivations of the myriad propositions from the definitions, postulates, and common notions. Geometers have studied both questions for millennia. Philosophers tend to focus on the former ones.

Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 3 In particular, Euclid s fifth postulate, the parallel postulate, tuned out to be not quite as secure as the others. Indeed, Euclid seems to have recognized worries about the parallel postulate. He does not invoke the fifth postulate freely; rather, he waits until he absolutely requires it. Euclid s parallel postulate states that if a straight line falling on two straight lines makes the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which are the angles less than the two right angles. We frequently study the parallel postulate in an equivalent form, known as Playfair s postulate, which says that given a line, and a point not on that line, there exists exactly one line which passes through the given point parallel to the given line. Both the parallel postulate and Playfair s postulate, it turns out, are equivalent to the claim that the sum of the angles of a triangle is 180 degrees (pi). Consider an interstellar triangle formed by the light rays of three stars, whose vertices are the centers of those stars. The sum of the angles of our interstellar triangle will be less than pi due to the curvatures of space-time corresponding to the gravitational pull of the stars and other large objects. Space-time is not Euclidean, but hyperbolic. In hyperbolic geometry, instead of there being one line that we can draw parallel to the given line in Playfair s postulate, there are an infinite number of lines. Hyperbolic geometry is just one of two classes of non-euclidean geometries. Riemannian, or spherical, geometry, results when one replaces Playfair s postulate with the claim that there are no lines parallel to the given line. Non-Euclidean geometries were developed in detail in the nineteenth century after two millennia of trying to prove that the parallel postulate follows from the other postulates. That is, geometers were uncomfortable taking the parallel postulate as a given. They wanted it to be derived from other givens. But, the other givens seemed pretty much unassailable. III. The Synthetic (Geometrical) Version of the Meditations The synthetic version of the Meditations was based precisely on Euclid s Elements. Like Euclid, Descartes provides definitions, postulates, common notions, and derived propositions. The resulting system looks different from the one in the Meditations, though the derived propositions are the same. Again, since our interest is in methodology, we need not focus on the content as much as the manner of presentation. Comparing the two systems might be salutary. Descartes starts with a set of definitions: thought, idea objective reality, formal reality substance, mind, body, God, essence, distinctness

Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 4 We can see, especially in the definitions of objective and formal reality, that Descartes is setting up the proofs of God s existence. Already in the definitions, we have worries. If, as in The Elements, the definitions do not beg questions of existence, then we can proceed to examine the postulates. On the other hand, if the definitions already assume the existence of anything, then the whole project is suspect. Some definitions are not contentious and, like Euclid s definitions, avoid begging questions of whether any objects have the properties defined. Two substances are said to be really distinct from one another when each of them can exist without the other (95) Definition 9, though, is worrisome. When we say that something is contained in the nature or concept of something, this is the same as saying that it is true of that thing or that it can be affirmed of that thing (95). If you have examined responses to the ontological argument, especially Caterus s response to Descartes, or even Gaunilo s response to Anselm, you know that this claim is contentious. (Here are some readings on the ontological argument. ) Caterus asks us to consider the concept of a necessarily existing lion, which contains existence necessarily, without entailing that there exist any lions. That is, we can not, on the basis of the concept containing existence affirm the existence of any lion. It is also worth noting that Definitions 1 and 2 have proved to be particularly contentious. By the word thought I include everything that is in us in such a way that we are immediately aware of it... By the word idea I understand that form of any thought through the immediate perception of which I am aware of that very same thought (94). The very possibility of unconscious thoughts clearly undermines any claims to obviousness, and thus acceptability, of these definitions. Freud, Adler, and Jung aside, contemporary cognitive scientists are interested in phenomena like blindsight, in which visual processing occurs unconsciously. Descartes takes seven postulates: 1. Frailty of the senses 2. Security of pure thought 3. Self-evidence of logic, including the logic of causation (but see the Common Notions, as well) 4. Connection between ideas and objects (compare to Definition IX) 5. The idea of God includes necessary existence. 6. Contrast clear and distinct perception with obscure and confused perception 7. Security of clear and distinct perceptions

He takes ten common notions: Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 5 1. We can ask about the cause of any thing. 2. Each instant is independent of every other, so that creation and preservation are indistinct. 3. Nothing can be uncaused. 4. Whatever reality is in a thing is formally or eminently in its first cause. 5. Our ideas require causes which contain formally the reality which exists objectively in the ideas. 6. There are degrees of reality: accidents, finite substances, infinite substance. 7. Our free will aims infallibly toward the good. 8. Whatever can make what is greater can make what is less. 9. It is greater to create (or preserve) a substance than an accident. 10. The ideas of all objects contain existence; only the idea of a perfect object contains necessary existence. Propositions 1. Ontological argument 2-3. Cosmological arguments 4. Distinction of mind and body Notice that the foundation in the Second Replies is quite different from that in the Meditations. In particular, the single, Archimedean point of the Meditations, the Cogito, is almost completely absent from the synthetic presentation. If we were to sketch the foundation as presented in the Meditations, it might look: Cogito - God - Clarity and Distinctness - Free Will - Mathematics - Mind/Body distinction The most-important standard objection to Descartes s project concerns how we know the truth of Descartes s claims. Descartes argues that he has a rule for determining whether he knows any given claim. A claim is known to be true if it is clear and distinct, like the cogito. Surely in this first instance of knowledge, there is nothing but a certain clear and distinct perception of what I affirm. Yet this would hardly be enough to render me certain of the truth of a thing, if it could ever happen that something I perceived so clearly and distinctly were false. And thus I now seem able to posit as a general rule that everything I very clearly and distinctly perceive is true (AW 47). Given any mark, or rule, for certainty, how do we know that we have the correct mark? Appeal to the mark itself is circular. We can not say that we clearly and distinctly perceive that clarity and distinctness is the right criterion without begging the question. Descartes argues that the goodness of God secures the criterion of clear and distinct perception. But that argument seems to rely on the use of the criterion in the argument for the existence of God. This problem, called the problem of Cartesian circularity, is one of the more vexing and interesting in Descartes scholarship. I believe that Descartes did not believe that circular reasoning is always fallacious; see my Embracing the Cartesian Circle.

Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 6 Whatever the fate of Descartes s project regarding circularity, the cogito does seem to contain some kind of undoubtable truth. If we can grasp what it is that makes the cogito unassailable, perhaps we can find such surety elsewhere. Still, the synthetic, geometric version of the Meditations hardly mentions mathematics or the cogito. Further, the order of the foundation is different. Remember that Descartes is presenting what he takes to be obvious and incontrovertible definitions and first principles as the foundation of all that will follow. These first principles are, as Euclid s postulates, supposed to be given to us immediately. We do not have time to discuss the weaknesses of all the postulates, common notions, or propositions. It is not in our interest, here, to spend time on all of them. Further, there are interesting exegetical questions about the different presentations. Our goal was to examine how Descartes relies on some immediately obvious and given principles. Whether those principles are the cogito or the definitions, postulates, and common notions, we can see both Descartes s foundationalism and the weakness of the foundations. IV. The British Empiricists Locke, while differing from Descartes in some aspects of his methods, also seeks firm foundations and clear and distinct knowledge. Rather than base that knowledge on rational insight, Locke bases it on sense experience. He takes the human mind to be a tabula rasa, a clean slate, on which is written all of our experiences. Some of our beliefs are directly derived from sensation. For example, I know that sugar is sweet because I taste it. Others of our beliefs are produced by reflecting on our ideas. Science and mathematics, for example, are the results of combining and abstracting ideas present in memory or consciousness. Locke thus avoids relying on Descartes s contentious proofs of God s existence, his allegations about the connections between ideas and objects, about formal and objective realities, and about causation. Hume agrees. These simple ideas, the materials of all our knowledge, are suggested and furnished to the mind only by those two ways above mentioned, viz. sensation and reflection (Locke, 34). But though our thought seems to possess this unbounded liberty, we shall find upon a nearer examination that it is really confined within very narrow limits, and that all this creative power of the mind amounts to no more than the faculty of compounding, transposing, augmenting, or diminishing the materials afforded us by the senses and experience (Enquiry, 2). The challenge for the empiricists was to account for all of our beliefs on the basis of this foundation. Some empiricists denied that we had as much knowledge as Descartes thought. Thus, what we must build on our foundation is in question. Berkeley, for example, denied the existence of a material world. Hume denied any knowledge of God, and other metaphysical claims.

Philosophy 427: Intuitions and Philosophy, Prof. Marcus; Class 2 - Foundationalism, page 7 When we run over libraries, persuaded of these principles, what havoc must we make? If we take in our hand any volume--of divinity or school metaphysics, for instance--let us ask, Does it contain any abstract reasoning concerning quantity or number? No. Does it contain any experimental reasoning concerning matter of fact and existence? No. Commit it then to the flames, for it can contain nothing but sophistry and illusion (Enquiry, 12). Hume s skepticism was widespread and profound. Scientific generalizations ordinarily do not limit themselves to past observations. They go beyond sense evidence by making universal claims. All such scientific generalizations are thus unjustified, for the strict empiricist. Physical laws like Newtonian gravitation or the gas laws go beyond experimental evidence. They posit causal connections between events, but we have no sense impressions of the terms used. We have experience of the events, but not their causes. Effects are distinct from their causes and we have no access to the causes. Thus, as a consequence of empiricism, we can not establish the truth of laws of nature. We do not know that the sun will rise tomorrow. The laws could suddenly shift, from what we think they are. Our inability to know physical laws, indeed anything about unobserved or future phenomena, on empiricist principles is generally known as the problem of induction. We can see the problem of induction in our desire to make inferences like PI. PI PI1. I have seen one billiard ball strike another many times. PI2. Each time the ball which was struck has moved, motion was transferred. PIC. So, the struck ball will move this time. The problem is that the conclusion of PI does not follow from its premises. You can see that PIC does not follow if you consider what would happen if the laws of physics shift. PIC could be false, while PI1 and PI2 remain true. To make the argument valid, we could add a third premise ensuring the uniformity of nature PI3 The future will resemble the past. If we add this principle of the uniformity of nature as a third premise, then PIC will follow. But, we can not learn PI3 on the basis of sense experience. By limiting the extent of what we call knowledge, the empiricists improved their chances of deriving all knowledge from sense experience. But, empiricist principles deny that we have very much knowledge at all. Perhaps the most secure area of knowledge, mathematics, seems most distant from sense experience. Mathematics seems especially distant from sensation in the post-cartesian world, since the development of analysis led to algebra replacing geometry as the foundation of mathematics. Descartes over-reached on his foundation, but was able to build a massive structure, including all of mathematics and the new science, as well as the old religion. The empiricists appear to have a firmer foundation, but a smaller edifice. The foundationalist traditions of the modern era had their last gasp in the early twentieth century, with the work of the logical positivists, which we will discuss on Thursday.