Human Values as a Source for Sustainin g the Environment

Similar documents
SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

TOWARDS A THEOLOGICAL VIRTUE ETHIC FOR THE PRESERVATION OF BIODIVERSITY

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Environmental Ethics. Espen Gamlund, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy University of Bergen

AN OUTLINE OF CRITICAL THINKING

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Clarifications on What Is Speciesism?

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Is It Morally Wrong to Have Children?

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Thinking Ethically: A Framework for Moral Decision Making

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Liberty of Ecological Conscience

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

Moral Theory. What makes things right or wrong?

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

The Pleasure Imperative

Phil 114, April 24, 2007 until the end of semester Mill: Individual Liberty Against the Tyranny of the Majority

Definitions: Values and Moral Values

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

Do you have a self? Who (what) are you? PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2014

Teleological: telos ( end, goal ) What is the telos of human action? What s wrong with living for pleasure? For power and public reputation?

24.03: Good Food 2/15/17

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

A primer of major ethical theories

24.03: Good Food 3 April Animal Liberation and the Moral Community

Justice and Ethics. Jimmy Rising. October 3, 2002

Explore the Christian rationale for environmental ethics and assess its strengths and weaknesses.

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

PHILOSOPHY. Chair: Karánn Durland (Fall 2018) and Mark Hébert (Spring 2019) Emeritus: Roderick Stewart

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

PROFESSIONAL ETHICS IN SCIENCE AND ENGINEERING

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

Final Examination Semester 2 / Year 2011 (Group 2)

Introduction to Ethics

MILL. The principle of utility determines the rightness of acts (or rules of action?) by their effect on the total happiness.

Mill s Utilitarian Theory

NORTH SOUTH UNIVERSITY DEPARTMENT OF HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY DHAKA, BANGLADESH

Lecture 2: What Ethics is Not. Jim Pryor Guidelines on Reading Philosophy Peter Singer What Ethics is Not

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Creative Genius and the Rights of the Individual: From Romanticism to Utilitarianism

Psychological Egoism, Hedonism and Ethical Egoism

Philosophical Ethics. Distinctions and Categories

Peter Singer, Practical Ethics Discussion Questions/Study Guide Prepared by Prof. Bill Felice

pa r t i i TYPES OF ETHICAL THEORY

Important to remember:

In this response, I will bring to light a fascinating, and in some ways hopeful, irony

Unified Teleology: Paul Taylor s Biocentric Egalitarianism Through Aristotle

Mary Anne Warren on Full Moral Status

National Quali cations

Ethical Theory. Ethical Theory. Consequentialism in practice. How do we get the numbers? Must Choose Best Possible Act

Rashdall, Hastings. Anthony Skelton

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

Ethics From Moral Intuition To Moral Theory

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 166 SPRING 2006

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

Short Answers: Answer the following questions in one paragraph (each is worth 5 points).

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

IN DEFENSE OF AN ANIMAL S RIGHT TO LIFE. Aaron Simmons. A Dissertation

Suppose a school were to set out deliberately to improve the mental

MGT610 Business Ethics

Contractualism and Our Duties to Nonhuman Animals. Matthew Talbert West Virginia University. Published in Environmental Ethics 28 (2006):

ETHICAL POSITIONS STATEMENT

Ethical non-naturalism

Consequentialism. Mill s Theory of Utility

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

J.f. Stephen s On Fraternity And Mill s Universal Love 1

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

Making Decisions on Behalf of Others: Who or What Do I Select as a Guide? A Dilemma: - My boss. - The shareholders. - Other stakeholders

RESOLVING THE DEBATE ON LIBERTARIANISM AND ABORTION

Topic III: Sexual Morality

Williams The Human Prejudice

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Introduction to Ethics

Humanities 4: Lectures Kant s Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

FINAL EXAM SHORT-ANSWER QUESTIONS PHILOSOPHY 13 FALL, 2007

Module 1: Vice, Crime, and American Law: Concepts and Relationships

Utilitarianism pp

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

The Trolley Problem. 1. The Trolley Problem: Consider the following pair of cases:

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

CRITIQUE OF PETER SINGER S NOTION OF MARGINAL UTILITY

Transcription:

Chapter 7 Human Values as a Source for Sustainin g the Environment Naomi Zack Every form of life has value regardless of its worth to human beings. -Earth Charter, Principle l a Due to the overwhelming dominance of homo sapiens, natural environments ar e no longer self-sustaining, and their continued existence will depend on huma n agreement to sustain them. Given present commercial historical realities, such agreement will require new kinds of moral reasoning about the relationship between human beings and ecological systems. The preservation of natural environments is obviously of great human utility as a source of valued things. But the sustenance of natural ecosystems and their inhabitants, on the basis of their intrinsic worth, does not yet have an effective theoretical defense against human speciesism, the continual expansion o f capitalistic systems, and the present dependence of humans on human-mad e physical and social environments. The intrinsic worth of natural ecosystems has been explained by proponents of deep ecology and maintained within traditiona l indigenous cultures, but such advocacy seems thus far to operate in a cognitiv e dimension separate from the rest of Western (i.e., "Northern/Euro-American/ secular-technological") moral reasoning. So the question is, How can we Westerners bring intuitions, insights, and traditions concerning the intrinsic worth of natural systems and beings into the discourse of recognized practical reason, or moral argument? The three dominant moral theories of utilitarianism or consequentialism, virtue ethics, and deontology are each plausible systems to apply to natural systems and beings. However, I shall argue that only deontology is capable of accomplishing the required theoretical goals, because only deontology could confer personhood on natural systems and beings. 69

70 Naomi Zac k Jeremy Bentham (1823) was the first to note that the test for inclusion in th e domain of those whose well-being counts is not the capacity for rationa l thought, but the ability to suffer. ("The question is not, Can they reason? Nor, Can they talk? But, Can they suffer?") So, we could extend a utilitarian calculu s to natural subjects. But, utilitarian insights do not tell us how to weigh the beneficial consequences to natural subjects, or what to do when human goods are maximized to a greater extent than nonhumans are harmed. Utilitarianism yield s a model of humane treatment of nonhuman life, which could result in the extinction of such life whenever humans believe that the pain suffered by nonhumans is too great. If nonhuman absence of pain is not sufficient for calculatin g maximal results for nonhumans, it is not clear how humans could define non - human flourishing. For example, do animals flourish if they are forced to subsis t in the margins of their ecosystems, or, do they flourish if new ecosystems ar e artificially created for them? But even if something like John Stuart Mill's concept of "higher pleasures" is applied to animals or ecosystems as a standard fo r sustainable conditions under which they flourish, the flourishing of nonhuman beings is still likely to be judged not as important as the flourishing of huma n beings. This would be particularly true when the nonhuman being is an entir e ecosystem likely to be jeopardized by development that will enhance huma n livelihood and happiness. Virtue ethics looks more promising because the moral ground is higher an d provides a perspective from which we can value natural beings in a way totall y apart from their use to us. We can value them and teach our children to value them as an expression and extension of what is best in our character. Indeed, our own flourishing may require an appreciation of, and respect for, natural being s in ways that treat such beings with the utmost moral and aesthetic seriousness. Thus, Thomas Hill (1983) explains how our behavior toward natural beings reveals the presence or absence of human traits such as sensitivity, humility, an d gratitude. The problem with the virtue ethics approach is that it seems to relegate the sustenance of natural environments and beings to the province of manners an d sensibility. This aspect of human life is personally and socially important onl y after pressing problems of survival have been solved, and it is not usually a priority in the face of human need and suffering. More problematic, the sustenanc e of natural beings as part of the development of human virtue remains an enter - prise in which humans, and not those natural beings, are central. On a good day, when I am not too pressured by concerns directly affecting my livelihood, I ma y make a contribution to the preservation of rain forests. And why, as a matter of virtue? Because it will reflect well on me in contexts where I have to account for myself, and more important, will strengthen my virtue of generosity. Somethin g stronger than this kind of rationale would seem to be necessary if sustenance o f natural environments is a serious moral issue. I now turn to deontology. I want to examine the radical view that we need to assent to a general principle which will admit natural beings to what Kant

Human Values as a Source for Sustaining the Environment 7 1 called "the kingdom of ends." This can be accomplished only if natural beings are granted the status of persons, in the same ways in which human beings ar e persons. Such recognition will require competent, adult human representatives, similar to the ways in which the human personhood of children and adults o f diminished capacity is represented by parents and guardians. Mere stewardship or trusteeship over ecosystems and their inhabitants will not succeed in protecting them from depredation and eventual destruction because that kind of representation is at best defensive. Once the defense is overcome, for example, once the land is wrested into the commercial domain, there is at present nothing illegal or broadly immoral about its destruction. By contrast, the parental rights o r guardianship of children and adults of diminished capacity can only be abrogated if children and wards grow up or acquire full capacity. Children and wards are not "adventured" to the fortunes of the marketplace if one particular guardianship comes to an end, because their need of guardianship is absolute. If an ecosystem had the status of a person, then depriving it of life or assaulting its inhabitants would be in principle no different from crimes of murde r or assault committed against human beings. One can imagine a situation in which killing members of an endangered species would be a far more serious crime than it is in most places at present, but this does not capture what is distinctive about personhood. Even if deliberately killing natural beings were a capital crime, as things now stand, so long as such beings are not persons, th e reason for the punishment would rest on something different from their inheren t rights. I once heard Winona LaDuke, a North American spokesperson for indigenist concerns, talk about a hydroelectric project that had required extensive flooding of land, so that, among other ecological results, 10,000 elk wer e drowned. "Who gave them the right," she asked, "to drown 10,000 elk?" (See also LaDuke 1999.) I think that is the kind of question which has to be addresse d in moral reasoning that is relevant to the sustenance of natural environments. In a secular capitalistic society, the rights of ecosystems and their inhabitants would have to be constructed. This could be done by basing such rights on the same kinds of moral sentiments and intuitions that motivate doctrines o f universal human rights. The twentieth century has not provided good reason t o be optimistic about such doctrines, but their worth as ideals remains indisputable. Thus, even if there were not universal agreement and compliance about including ecosystems and their inhabitants in the "kingdom of ends," the con - sensual and practical limits of the theoretical inclusion would not detract fro m its value as an ideal. (Human secular morality is an ongoing project.) The grounds for human secular morality are ultimately unreasoned in th e deontological sense. I cannot "prove" that it is wrong to drown 10,000 elk or t o allow twelve million children to starve to death. Unfortunately, either you "see" the wrongness of one or both of these things, or you do not. Similarly, there are reasons short of proof which can be given for granting the status of persons to no nhuman beings and I will now suggest five. (It should be noted that I am not

72 Naomi Zac k proposing fictitious personhood, as in the case of corporations, but real personhood.) 1. Ecosystems and their inhabitants are living beings, like human beings, and they are entitled to the same rights that human beings are supposed to have. (I am simply asserting the consequent here, not claiming that it follows from th e antecedent.) 2. As living beings, it is possible to say that some states of affairs, primaril y their ongoing life, or their sickness and death, are better or worse for natura l beings. It follows from this that natural beings have positive interests as do human beings. 3. The interests of natural beings, while dependent on the forbearance and assistance of humans, are not in particular cases dependent on particular huma n beings. This independence of natural beings is analogous to the independence of a human child, in distinction from the dependence of fetuses, who require th e support of particular individuals. 4, Many human beings have compassionate sentiments for natural beings, as they do for other humans. They suffer when natural beings are injured and ar e satisfied and pleased when they flourish. If compassion as a motive is also a reason to curtail the suffering, and promote the flourishing, of humans, then th e same holds for natural beings. 5. There is good reason to believe that natural beings suffer when they ar e injured or destroyed and this similarity to human life is an important qualification for admission to the realm of persons because the one secular basis for universal human rights is the capacity to suffer. What would be the consequences of person status for nonhuman beings? First, they would have a fundamental right to life. They would also have political rights, expressed through their human representatives, as well as rights t o "free speech," expressed in the same way, and other rights, such as freedom o f association. There would be a presumption of their liberties, chief of whic h would be the negative right not to be bought or sold. This last right is perhap s the key benefit of personhood for vast numbers of extant nonhuman beings. One confusion in the view I am proposing is that it is not clear what the individual unit would be if nonhuman beings were persons. In the case of ecosystems, size and density might be variables. In the case of so-called lower life - forms, swarms, schools, and flocks might be single persons. I am not sure that a dog would qualify as a person (I know that many would disagree here) althoug h I am quite certain that a single elephant, dolphin, or chimpanzee would. I have presented an extreme view which many would consider absurd an d utopian. My hope is that reasoned objections to such a view will pinpoint th e kinds of reasons which underly present legal policies and moral oblivion concerning natural beings. I anticipate three main lines of objection to including nonhuman beings in the domain of persons : religious, commercial, and speciesist. The religious objection sanctifies human dominance over the land, its resources and animals, on

Human Values as a Source for Sustaining the Environment 7 3 the grounds that a (for the most part, Christian) God created human beings t o subdue and rule the Earth. There is no empirical foundation for this objection. The commercial objection is an unfortunate result of the historical ways in which the Western technological project seems to have acquired the capacity to monetize everything on the planet. This project appears to have no bounds and i t even has a poor record for the sustenance of human life in situations of conflic t with market values. The speciesist objection is difficult to sustain on secular grounds, as a moral position, and it is theoretically weak in the face of geneti c engineering and cyborg technologies which are now on the horizon, that is, bot h hereditary and morphological material from other species may become ordinar y components of human beings. Furthermore, should there ever be encounters with extraterrestrial intelligent life, human speciesism will be even more difficult to defend. The most general values of human development and flourishing would b e served by granting personhood to ecosystems and natural beings. It would make us all more virtuous and, in the long run, the quality of human life would b e better. But these utilities to humans would be secondary gains, so to speak, and not primary reasons for including natural beings in the domain of persons. Reference s Bentham, Jeremy. 1823. "Value of a Lot of Pleasure or Pain, How to be Measured, " XVII, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation. London : W. Pickering. The Earth Charter Initiative. 2002. "The Earth Charter." San Jose, Costa Rica: Earth Council. <http ://www.earthcharter.org/earthcharterlcharter.htm> (January 12, 2002). Hill, Thomas E. 1983. "Ideals of Human Excellence and Preserving Natural Environ - ments," Environmental Ethics 5 : 211-24. LaDuke, Winona. 1999. All Our Relations: Native Struggles for Land and Life. Cam - bridge, Mass.: South End Press.