INTRODUCTION. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism.

Similar documents
Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Skepticism and Internalism

What is knowledge? How do good beliefs get made?

Semantic Externalism, by Jesper Kallestrup. London: Routledge, 2012, x+271 pages, ISBN (pbk).

DOUBT, CIRCULARITY AND THE MOOREAN RESPONSE TO THE SCEPTIC. Jessica Brown University of Bristol

G.E. Moore A Refutation of Skepticism

How and How Not to Take on Brueckner s Sceptic. Christoph Kelp Institute of Philosophy, KU Leuven

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

External World Skepticism

Sensitivity has Multiple Heterogeneity Problems: a Reply to Wallbridge. Guido Melchior. Philosophia Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

Lecture 17:Inference Michael Fourman

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Is Moore s Argument an Example of Transmission-Failure? James Pryor Harvard University Draft 2 8/12/01

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Internalism and Et Externalism

Warrant and accidentally true belief

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

The Externalist and the Structuralist Responses To Skepticism. David Chalmers

John Hawthorne s Knowledge and Lotteries

Theories of epistemic justification can be divided into two groups: internalist and

Introduction to Philosophy. Spring 2017

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

Nozick s fourth condition

The Problem of the External World

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

Belief Ownership without Authorship: Agent Reliabilism s Unlucky Gambit against Reflective Luck Benjamin Bayer September 1 st, 2014

Does Justification Aim at Truth?

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

SCEPTICISM, EPISTEMIC LUCK, AND EPISTEMIC ANGST

Common Sense: A Contemporary Defense By Noah Lemos Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. xvi

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

ACQUAINTANCE AND THE PROBLEM OF THE SPECKLED HEN

HOW I KNOW I M NOT A BRAIN IN A VAT * José L. Zalabardo University College London

Grokking Pain. S. Yablo. draft of June 2, 2000

The Dreamer. Does Descartes know what he is doing when he shakes his head and stretches out his hand? Descartes, Meditations, 1641

What is Justification?

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

Basic Knowledge and the Problem of Easy Knowledge (Rough Draft-notes incomplete not for quotation) Stewart Cohen

Sosa on Safety and Epistemic Frankfurt Cases

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

The Gettier problem JTB K

Review of Duncan Pritchard, Epistemic Luck

Indexical Reliabilism and the New Evil Demon *

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION

CONTENTS INTRODUCTION... 4

Scepticism, Rationalism and Externalism

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

The Gettier problem JTB K

Some Iterations on The Subject s Perspective Objection to Externalism By Hunter Gentry

The traditional tripartite account of knowledge as justified true belief

New Lessons from Old Demons: The Case for Reliabilism

Lecture 8 Property Dualism. Frank Jackson Epiphenomenal Qualia and What Mary Didn t Know

Content Externalism and the Internalism/ Externalism Debate in Justification Theory

The Problem of the Criterion 1

Constructing the World

Inference to the best explanation and the challenge of skepticism

Relativity. Should we suspend our judgment regarding everything that appears to the senses?

INTRODUCTION THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

The Rejection of Skepticism

To link to this article:

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Scepticism, brains in vats, and the matrix

Seeing Through The Veil of Perception *

An Empiricist Theory of Knowledge Bruce Aune

Recursive Tracking versus Process Reliabilism

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

Externalism, Self-Knowledge and Transmission of Warrant

Topics in Philosophy of Mind Other Minds Spring 2003/handout 2

3. Knowledge and Justification

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Evidentialist Anti-Skepticism

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Against Coherence: Truth, Probability, and Justification. Erik J. Olsson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xiii, 232.

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

In Defence of Single-Premise Closure

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

5AANA009 Epistemology II 2014 to 2015

PHILOSOPHY EPISTEMOLOGY ESSAY TOPICS AND INSTRUCTIONS

AGENT CAUSATION AND RESPONSIBILITY: A REPLY TO FLINT

Phenomenal Conservatism and the Internalist Intuition

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University

VARIETIES OF EXTERNALISM

Counter Closure and Knowledge despite Falsehood 1

KNOWLEDGE AND REASON

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

SCIENTIFIC REALISM AND EPISTEMOLOGY

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

Transcription:

GENERAL PHILOSOPHY WEEK 2: KNOWLEDGE JONNY MCINTOSH INTRODUCTION Sceptical scenario arguments: 1. You cannot know that SCENARIO doesn't obtain. 2. If you cannot know that SCENARIO doesn't obtain, you cannot know TARGET. 3. So, you cannot know TARGET. For example: 1. You cannot know that you are not a BIV. 2. If you cannot know that you are not a BIV, you cannot know that you have hands. 3. So, you cannot know that you have hands. This week: Moore's response, Nozick's response, Reliablism's response, Externalism v. Internalism. MOORE G. E. Moore argues against the sceptic's first premise, the claim that you cannot know that you are not a BIV. He thought you can know that you are not a BIV. Moore's argument: 1. You can know that you have hands. 2. If you can know that you have hands, you can know that you are not a BIV. 3. So, you can know that you are not a BIV. Moore's argument reverses the sceptic's: Moore's second premise is equivalent to the sceptic's. The sceptic employs modus ponens to infer that you cannot know you have hands. Moore employs modus tollens to infer that you can know that you are not a BIV.

So whose first premise should we prefer? Moore: you can know that you have hands Sceptic: you cannot know that you are not a BIV. Maybe we are more certain of Moore's. But why think this certainty is of any epistemological significance? Compare Hume's observation, last week, that we are psychologically incapable of giving up our belief in the external world. A natural reaction to this is, "So what? How can that be epistemologically significant?" The sceptic gives this argument for her premise: 1. BRAIN IN A VAT is subjectively indistinguishable from how things are. 2. If a scenario is subjectively indistinguishable from how things are, you can't rule out the possibility that it obtains. 3. If you can't rule out the possibility that a scenario obtains, you cannot know that it does not obtain. 4. So, you cannot know that BRAIN IN A VAT does not obtain. Where does Moore think this goes wrong? Moore says that, while he cannot prove that the dreaming scenario does not obtain, he thinks that he nevertheless has conclusive evidence that it does not. So he seems to deny the third claim, that to know that BRAIN IN A VAT does not obtain, one needs to be able to rule out the possibility that it does. One reason why Moore's response may seem unsatisfying: while he seems to reject the third claim, he gives us no explanation as to WHY it should be rejected. (Compare Moore here with the reliablist, below.) NOZICK KNOWLEDGE According to Nozick, S knows that P IFF 3. If P were false, S wouldn't believe that P 4. If P were true, S would believe that P More briefly, S knows that P IFF S has a true belief that P which TRACKS THE TRUTH. In meeting the third condition, S's belief that P is said to be SENSITIVE.

The third and fourth conditions are COUNTERFACTUALS. To check whether they hold, we need to consider how things would be in certain possible situations. "If I had dropped this glass, the water in it would have spilled" This seems true because in the CLOSEST possible situations in which I drop the glass (those most similar to the actual sitation), the water spills. It doesn't seem to matter that there are possible situations in which I drop the glass but the water does not spill - someone is hiding under the table, the water freezes. Those situations are less close. More generally, it seems that a counterfactual holds IFF, in the closest possible situations in which the antecedent is true, the consequent is also true: "If it were the case that P, it would be the case that Q" In these terms, Nozick's view is that S knows that P IFF 3. In the closest possible situations in which P is false, S doesn't believe that P 4. In the closest possible situations in which P is true, S does believe that P. SCEPTICISM What's this got to do with the BIV argument? Do you know the proposition that you are not a BIV (who is being deceived by a deranged scientist)? Nozick: No. Even if you truly believe that you are not a BIV, you don't know it. The closest possible situations in which it is false (in which you are a BIV) are ones in which, because you are being deceived, things seem to you to be the same as they actually seem. In those situations, you still believe that you are not a BIV. So your belief is not sensitive. Do you know the proposition that that you have hands? Nozick: Yes, assuming that you truly believe that you have hands.

The closest possible situations in which it is false (in which you don't have hands) are ones in which, say, you have been in an industrial accident. In those situations, you don't believe that you have hands. So Nozick's third condition is met. Your belief is sensitive. And the fourth condition? If the proposition that you have hands were true, would you have believed it? The closest possible situation in which it is true (in which you do have hands) is the actual situation. In that situation, you believe that you have hands. So Nozick's fourth condition is met too. So Nozick's fourth condition is met as well. According to Nozick, then, the sceptic's second premise is false: even though you don't (and in fact cannot) know that you are not a BIV, you can know that you have hands. We saw the sceptic's argument for this premise last week: 1. You know that the proposition that you have hands entails the proposition that you are not a BIV. 2. If you know that the proposition that you have hands entails the proposition that you are not a BIV, and you can know that you have hands, then you can know that you are not a BIV. 3. So, if you can know that you have hands, you can know that you are not a BIV. 4. So, if you cannot know that you are not a BIV, you cannot know that you have hands. Nozick accepts premise 1. (Homework: explain why!) But he denies premise 2. So Nozick thinks there are counterexamples to EPISTEMIC CLOSURE: If you know that P entails Q, and you can know that P, then you can also know that Q. Notice that, unlike Moore, Nozick explains not just where he thinks the sceptic's argument fails, but WHY. His account of knowledge is playing a crucial role. RELIABLISM According to reliablists, S knows that P IFF 3. S's belief was produced by a reliable process.

Do you know the proposition that you have hands? Reliablist: Yes, assuming that you truly believe that you have hands. Your belief that you have hands is produced by a reliable process: perception. Do you know the proposition that you are not a BIV? Reliablist: Yes! Your belief that you are not a BIV is produced by applying a reliable process, deductive inference, to your belief that you have hands, which is itself produced by a reliable process. According to reliablists, then, the sceptic's first premise is false: you CAN know that you are not a BIV. Consider again the sceptic's argument for this: 1. BRAIN IN A VAT is subjectively indistinguishable from how things are. 2. If a scenario is subjectively indistinguishable from how things are, you can't rule out the possibility that it obtains. 3. If you can't rule out the possibility that a scenario obtains, you cannot know that it does not obtain. 4. So, you cannot know that BRAIN IN A VAT does not obtain. Like Moore, the reliablist rejects premise 3. To know that a sceptical scenario does not obtain, you do not need to be able to rule out the possibility that it does, i.e. prove that it does not. But unlike Moore, the reliablist offers an explanation as to WHY premise 3 fails: an account of knowledge on which it requires only reliably produced true belief. EXTERNALISM V. INTERNALISM Here are two (connected) worries one might raise about Nozick's and the reliablist's responses to the sceptic. FIRST WORRY In different ways, both Nozick and the reliablist argue that your belief that you have hands constitutes knowledge, given the assumption that you have hands. Doesn't this beg the question against the sceptic? No. The sceptic doesn't deny that your belief that you have hands is true. She argues that it cannot constitute knowledge. But if the reliablist's or Nozick's analyses of knowledge are correct, your belief that you have hands can constitute knowledge - and does constitute knowledge if it is true.

Another way of putting this: both Nozick and the reliablist try to show that it is possible that we do know that we have hands. But they try to do this without proving that we know we have hands. So both Nozick and the reliablist allow for the possibility that we know that we have hands even if we do not know that we know that we hands. So they both deny the KK PRINCIPLE: One knows that P only if one knows that one knows that P. SECOND WORRY On both Nozick's and the reliablist's analyses, whether S's true belief that P constitutes knowledge that P depends on factors that may be external to S's mind: whether S's belief is sensitive (Nozick), or reliably produced (the reliabilist). This is EXTERNALISM about knowledge. By contrast, consider: S knows that P IFF 3. S is able to produce an argument for P. On this analysis, whether S's true belief that P constitutes knowledge that P depends only on factors that are internal to S's mind. This is INTERNALISM about knowledge. Bonjour (1980) 'Externalist Theories of Empirical Knowledge', p. 62. Laurence Bonjour raises a potential problem for externalism about knowledge: Norman, under certain conditions that usually obtain, is a completely reliable clairvoyant with respect to certain kinds of subject matter. He possesses no evidence or reasons of any kind for or against the general possibility of such a cognitive power, or for or against the thesis that he possesses it. One day Norman comes to believe that the President is in New York City, though he has no evidence either for or against this belief. In fact the belief is true and results from his clairvoyant power, under circumstances in which it is completely reliable. Norman's true belief is both sensitive and reliably produced. But does Norman know that the President is in New York City?

We might insist that Norman does know that the President is in New York City. But what if we amend the case, and give Norman lots of evidence that he is not clairvoyant? SUMMARY Moore's runs the sceptic's argument in reverse, and denies the sceptic's first premise, the claim that we cannot know that we are not BIVs. If we are dissatisfied with Moore's response, that may be at least partly because he doesn't explain WHY the sceptic's argument fails. Nozick denies the sceptic's second premise, the claim that we cannot know we have hands if we cannot know that we are not BIVs. He therefore denies EPISTEMIC CLOSURE. This follows from his account of knowledge as true belief that TRACKS THE TRUTH. Reliablists deny the sceptic's first premise, the claim that we cannot know that we are not BIVs. This follows from their account of knowledge as true belief that is RELIABLY PRODUCED. Both Nozick and the reliablist offer EXTERNALIST accounts of knowledge and deny the KK PRINCIPLE. Laurence Bonjour's CLAIRVOYANT case presents a challenge for externalism.