Postmodernism and the Thomist Tradition. John Doe. Philosophy 101. December 13, Dr. Jane Smith

Similar documents
Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

WHY SHOULD ANYONE BELIEVE ANYTHING AT ALL?

Evidence and Transcendence

Against Plantinga's A/C Model: Consequences of the Codependence of the De Jure and De Facto Questions. Rebeka Ferreira

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

On the Relation of Philosophy to the Theology Conference Seward 11/24/98

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

BENJAMIN R. BARBER. Radical Excess & Post-Modernism Presentation By Benedetta Barnabo Cachola

The Advantages of a Catholic University

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Are Miracles Identifiable?

Well-Being, Time, and Dementia. Jennifer Hawkins. University of Toronto

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

DUALISM VS. MATERIALISM I

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

The free will defense

1 Hans Jonas, The Imperative of Responsibility: In Search of an Ethics for the Technological Age (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1-10.

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Chapter Summaries: Three Types of Religious Philosophy by Clark, Chapter 1

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Universal Injuries Need Not Wound Internal Values A Response to Wysman

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

Unrestricted Quantification and Reality: Reply to Kim. Takashi Yagisawa. California State University, Northridge

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

How Successful Is Naturalism?

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Free will & divine foreknowledge

How to Teach The Writings of the New Testament, 3 rd Edition Luke Timothy Johnson

In this paper I will critically discuss a theory known as conventionalism

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

True Liberation: Nonnegotiable Praxis. It is almost impossible to turn on the television or read a newspaper without being

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

OnceSaved, Always Saved? Ernest W. Durbin II

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Meanings from the Oxford English Dictionary

Plantinga, Van Till, and McMullin. 1. What is the conflict Plantinga proposes to address in this essay? ( )

According to Phrases and Epistemic Modals

ANSWERS TO THE QUESTIONS FOR DISCUSSION

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

METHODISM AND HIGHER-LEVEL EPISTEMIC REQUIREMENTS Brendan Murday

RECENT WORK THE MINIMAL DEFINITION AND METHODOLOGY OF COMPARATIVE PHILOSOPHY: A REPORT FROM A CONFERENCE STEPHEN C. ANGLE

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Henrik Ahlenius Department of Philosophy ETHICS & RESEARCH

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

Responses to Respondents RESPONSE #1 Why I Reject Exegetical Conservatism

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

A Wesleyan Approach to Knowledge

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Introduction to Christian Apologetics June 1 st and 8 th

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

After Philosophy. Thaddeus J. Kozinski

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

The problem of evil & the free will defense

Physicalism and Conceptual Analysis * Esa Díaz-León.

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

[MJTM 17 ( )] BOOK REVIEW

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

The Cosmological Argument

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Roman Madzia. Education and Culture 30 (2) (2014):

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

Florida State University Libraries

PROSPECTS FOR A JAMESIAN EXPRESSIVISM 1 JEFF KASSER

Epistemological Externalism and the Project of Traditional Epistemology. Contemporary philosophers still haven't come to terms with the project of

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

complete state of affairs and an infinite set of events in one go. Imagine the following scenarios:

READ: 1 Timothy 6:3-4a, with vv.6:4b-5, and 1:3-4,7, and 4:1-2, and 6:20-21 for additional context

Critical Thinking: Present, Past and Future 5 April, 2015

Video Reaction. Opening Activity. Journal #16

Faith and Philosophy, April (2006), DE SE KNOWLEDGE AND THE POSSIBILITY OF AN OMNISCIENT BEING Stephan Torre

C. Problem set #1 due today, now, on the desk. B. More of an art than a science the key things are: 4.

DRAFT. This document has been created as a supplementary resource supporting and extending The Five

Unit 1 Philosophy of Education: Introduction INTRODUCTION

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

Can logical consequence be deflated?

The Early Church worked tirelessly to establish a clear firm structure supported by

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Religious Studies. Name: Institution: Course: Date:

Transcription:

Doe 1 Postmodernism and the Thomist Tradition John Doe Philosophy 101 December 13, 2012 Dr. Jane Smith

Doe 2 Postmodernism, defined as a style and concept in the arts characterized by distrust of theories and ideologies (Oxford), found its expression in philosophy as a rejection of theories based on objectivism. This deep skepticism poses a special problem for the realm of Christian philosophy, which has at its base the truth of an absolute and knowable reality. Tracey Rowland, in her book Culture and The Thomist Tradition, believes that she has found a way to reconcile the fundamental subjectivity of postmodernism and the liberal tradition with the necessary objectivism of Catholicism. In order to understand her argument, it is necessary to understand how, growing from the projectionist view of cognition, Rowland places herself among the postmodern theorists, and how she then subverts this subjectivity to make reality claims in favor of Catholicism. Once her position is understood, it can be evaluated in terms of the logical constraints of Christian philosophy. Does she independently come to her endorsement of Thomism, or does she allow herself to use Christian doctrine as a replacement for sound philosophical logic? I would argue that she does in fact rely too heavily on Christian ideas to make her argument, and in the end is unsuccessful in merging postmodernism with Catholicism. Her theory starts by delineating two possible theological responses to the liberal tradition. The first, Whig Thomism, embraces the Enlightenment thinking which characterizes the liberal tradition, and believes it to be ultimately compatible with, and perhaps even the necessary evolution of, religious faith. Followers of Whig Thomism place the seeds of the liberal tradition in the writings of Aquinas, and believe that a synthesis of Catholicism and modern culture is possible. This belief is founded in part upon the idea that modernity is theologically neutral, and thus poses no threat to the Church. Rowland, however, disagrees with this position. Believing modernity to be inimical to the development and success of Catholic values, she places herself among what she calls the Augustinian Thomists, who see no possibility for success if the Church attempts to modernize itself by developing a shared ideology with the liberal tradition. Rowland's objection to the modernization of the Church is based in part upon her belief in the expressionist view of language, which argues that language is inextricably linked to the culture in which it is used. The expressionist contends that an idea does not exist until it is expressed through language, and so is unique to that language, and hence that culture. This means that it is not possible to distill doctrines from the tradition which embodies them and then represent them in the idiom of an alternative tradition... without in any way changing the meaning of the doctrine (Rowland 121). To Rowland, the truth of this belief means the Church needs to acknowledge that it will not be possible to translate Catholicism into modern culture using the framework of the liberal tradition; any attempt to translate Catholic doctrine will alter the message beyond usefulness. In addition, the transposition of doctrine into liberal culture necessitates that the tradition of the doctrine and Church is left behind. In its place is a reinvention of the Catholic tradition that is weak and impotent without the power of its history. Although Rowland argues otherwise, this school of thought stands contrary to the implicit philosophy promoted by John Paul II in Fides et Ratio as the common ground between all cultures; each culture exists without a common language or philosophy with which to communicate its ideas to other. For this reason, Rowland argues, it is not possible to convert people entrenched in the liberal tradition using modified Church language; instead they must be

Doe 3 made to reject their own tradition and adopt the Thomist tradition wholesale. Rowland, then, rejects the liberal tradition in its entirety, and thus must find a means to pull people from the liberal into the Thomist tradition without the use of a common cultural language. What is cross-cultural, she contends, and so can be used to bring an understanding of Catholicism to other cultures, is the need possessed by all peoples to strive toward rationality and wholeness, a condition she terms the 'integrity of the self.' The liberal tradition, as stated above, does not fulfill this need, and leaves those who embrace it fractured and dissatisfied. It is this kernel of dissatisfaction that Rowland believes offers a window for the Catholic tradition to reach in and pull people into its fold. Following the example set out by Alexander MacIntyre, people can, through a dialectic process, eliminate all traditions which do not foster integrity of the self. They will then be left only with the Thomist tradition. Indeed, Rowland makes the claim that the Thomist tradition can be rationally demonstrated to be the only tradition which offers any hope for the formation of an integral self (134). Rowland then takes this argument a step further, making that the singularly success of Thomism is a very strong argument for... the truth of the tradition (134), so that her model for the Church's reaction to liberalism becomes an intellectual defense of Christianity itself. While this can seem an enticing argument for the benefits and validity of Thomism, there are several suppositions upon which it is based that are suspect. The crux of Rowland's argument is that it is possible to reach conclusions about not only the effectiveness of the Catholic tradition, but also its inherent truth, through both a logical rejection of other traditions and the consequent immersion in the Catholic tradition that reason can inspire faith. Since Rowland's is a reason-based argument for faith, it must be evaluated for its ability to exist without suppositions based on faith and to stand separate from the Christianity it promotes. There are two parts of her argument where Rowland allows the end goal of the primacy of the Thomist tradition to act in place of reason. The first of these is the supposition that a reasonable elimination of ineffective traditions will leave only Catholicism. The root of the problem with this supposition is her definition for an effective tradition one that maintains an integrity of the self. Rowland is working from inside the Catholic tradition, and so is using its values to delineate the categories of success and failure. In short, she falls prey to her own belief in the degree to which persons are influenced in their moral development by the culture of the community into which they have been born (Rowland 1). She is basically using the ideals of her own tradition as a measuring stick for others, which clearly means they will fall short, since their values are not her own. Her argument takes for granted that the primacy of the values of the Catholic tradition will draw people to it. To this end, she offers a long and acute attack on the liberal tradition and the ways in which it falls short of the values she is promoting. However, despite the power of this argument, she does nothing to follow that up with any stand-alone argument for the Thomist tradition. Instead, she only contends that because the others are wrong, hers must be right. It becomes a circular argument: Catholic values are the most effective, which means all other traditions will fall short, which proves that Catholic values are the most effective, etc. Given the basic inability of cultures to communicate effectively with each other, without having experienced all cultures, Rowland cannot make a claim as to which one is the best.

Doe 4 The second noticeable flaw in her logic is her assertion that the success of the Thomist tradition is suggestive of its veracity. This is the part of her argument where reason is supposed to give way to faith, where a methodology that does not begin with the principles of Christian Revelation (Rowland 134) nonetheless leads to a belief in their truthfulness. This truthfulness is supposed to spring from the Catholic tradition's unique ability to heal the self. There is no logical basis, however, for claiming that because something is helpful then it must be true; efficacy cannot be equates with veracity. If she is indeed promoting a kind of rationalism, in which the tenets of faith can be reached through reason alone, then this mis-logic creates a crucial missing link. If, as it seems more likely, she is promoting reason as only a road to faith, which is needed to complete an understanding of Christian Revelation, then her argument is acknowledging the necessity of a kind of intervention: reason based on what is the best for the self may lead a person to the Catholic tradition, but only faith can allow them to truly believe in its premises. She does not make clear which view she espouses, and so does little to explicate this stance. In the end, Rowland is hampered by the beliefs upon which she bases her arguments. Professing herself to be a part of the Genealogical tradition, she criticizes the Church's refusal to acknowledge of the role of culture in the formation of the self and its relationship to theology, and herself acknowledges the inherent and possibly insurmountable difficulties is purveying the Church's messages into other cultures. Despite this barrier, she claims it is possible to come to embrace the Thomist tradition through a rational rejection of all other traditions, and thus to effectively leave one tradition for another. The test for this argument needs to be whether it is still valid after taking away its theological basis to see whether it can stand without the need to reference its Christian end game. Separated from its Catholic roots, her assertion that Thomism is the only workable tradition falls short: only one already imbued with and looking for Catholic values will find them so clearly in that tradition. Finally, her assertion that Thomism's success at maintaining an integrity of the self is an endorsement of its truth is, at its core, a faith-based argument. Reason may, however unlikely it may be due to culture barriers, bring a person to Thomism, but only faith can prove its truthfulness.

Doe 5 Works Cited Oxford English Dictionary, http://www.oed.com/ Rowland, Tracey. Culture and The Thomist Tradition: After Vatican II. Oxon: Routledge, 2003.