The Ontological Argument

Similar documents
Anselm of Canterbury, Proslogion, chapters 2-5 & replies

Descartes' Ontological Argument

The Ontological Argument

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

Alvin Plantinga addresses the classic ontological argument in two

The Ontological Argument

THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

Class 2 - The Ontological Argument

Ontological Argument page 2

St. Anselm s versions of the ontological argument

NECESSARY BEING The Ontological Argument

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

Anselm s Equivocation. By David Johnson. In an interview for The Atheism Tapes, from the BBC, philosopher Colin McGinn briefly

A level Religious Studies at Titus Salt

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

DESCARTES ONTOLOGICAL PROOF: AN INTERPRETATION AND DEFENSE

[1968. In Encyclopedia of Christianity. Edwin A. Palmer, ed. Wilmington, Delaware: National Foundation for Christian Education.]

The Ontological Argument. An A Priori Route to God s Existence?

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

The Modal Ontological Argument

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

MEDITATIONS ON THE FIRST PHILOSOPHY: THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

THE JOuRNAL OF PHILOSOPHY

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Puzzles for Divine Omnipotence & Divine Freedom

The Problem of Divine Foreknowledge and Human Freedom

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

Theme 1: Arguments for the existence of God inductive, AS

What does it say about humanity s search for answers? What are the cause and effects mentioned in the Psalm?

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Up to this point, Anselm has been known for two quite different kinds of work:

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

5 A Modal Version of the

Kirschner's Modal Ontological Argument

The free will defense

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

Searle vs. Chalmers Debate, 8/2005 with Death Monkey (Kevin Dolan)

Exemplars. AS Religious Studies: Paper 1 Philosophy of Religion

Introduction to Philosophy

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Have you ever sought God? Do you have any idea of God? Do you believe that God exist?

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

1/5. The Critique of Theology

Permissible tinkering with the concept of God

CHAPTER III. Of Opposition.

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

12. A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)

(Some More) Vagueness

PHIL 251 Varner 2018c Final exam Page 1 Filename = 2018c-Exam3-KEY.wpd

Trinity & contradiction

Introduction to Philosophy. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Proofs of Non-existence

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

TWO NO, THREE DOGMAS OF PHILOSOPHICAL THEOLOGY

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Does God exist? The argument from evil

16. Universal derivation

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

Concerning God Baruch Spinoza

Logic clearly dictates that the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few or the needs of the one (Spock and Captain Kirk).

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

Philosophy 3100: Ethical Theory

9. Plantinga. Joshua Rasmussen. Forthcoming in Ontological Arguments, ed. Graham Oppy (OUP)

What Everybody Knows Is Wrong with the Ontological Argument But Never Quite Says. Robert Anderson Saint Anselm College

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

ON THE COMPOSSIBILITY OF THE DIVINE ATTRIBUTES

PHLA10 Reason and Truth Exercise 1

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

Chapter IV KANT: THE PHYSICO-THEOLOGICAL PROOF

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In this section you will learn three basic aspects of logic. When you are done, you will understand the following:

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic

COMPLETE PHILOSOPHICAL AND THEOLOGICAL TREATISES of ANSELM of CANTERBURY. Translated by JASPER HOPKINS and HERBERT RICHARDSON

McTaggart s Proof of the Unreality of Time

THEISM AND BELIEF. Etymological note: deus = God in Latin; theos = God in Greek.

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

A DEFENSE OF HARTSHORNE'S NEOCLASSICAL THEISM

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The Ethics. Part I and II. Benedictus de Spinoza ************* Introduction

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Immanuel Kant, Analytic and Synthetic. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics Preface and Preamble

On A New Cosmological Argument

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Religious Studies A new cosmological argument. Additional services for Religious Studies:

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Transition: From A priori To Anselm

Transcription:

The Ontological Argument Saint Anselm offers a very unique and interesting argument for the existence of God. It is an a priori argument. That is, it is an argument or proof that one might give independent of experience i.e., in order to be convinced by Anselm s proof, we will not need to perform any experiments, or have any experiences of the world, etc. Rather, all we need to do to be convinced is contemplate the meaning of the word God. The basic idea behind the ontological argument is that, simply by understanding the CONCEPT of God, we come to the conclusion that God must exist. 1. Essential properties: Before understanding Anselm s argument, one should grasp what it means for something to be an essential property. Imagine a triangle. Is it possible to imagine a triangle without 3 sides? Of course not. If you are imagining a figure that has some other number of sides, you are simply NOT IMAGINING A TRIANGLE. But, is it possible to imagine a triangle whose interior angles do not add up to 180 degrees? No. Once again, if you are imagining a figure whose interior angles do not add up to 180 degrees, you are simply imagining something that is NOT a triangle. But, this is just to say of 3-sidedness and having interior angles that add up to 180 degrees that these properties are ESSENTIAL to triangles. In other words, these things are a part of the ESSENCE of BEING a triangle; and, if you try to imagine a triangle without one of its essential properties, you are simply imagining something that is not a triangle. 2. The Ontological Argument: As we saw last time, God is typically defined as a supremely perfect being. Anselm uses the term something than which nothing greater can be thought. Anselm takes this to mean that God possesses ALL of the properties that make one great. Being the GREATEST or MOST PERFECT being is a part of the very concept of God. Now, God is like the triangle in that certain concepts are ESSENTIAL to the concept of God; namely, all of the properties that make one great, or perfect. In order to determine what properties are essential to God, we can simply ask the question, Would God be greater if He had that property, or greater if He did not? If God would be greater if He HAS some property, then He must have it (since God is the greatest possible being). 1

For instance, consider knowledge: It seems like God would be greater if He has some knowledge than if He does not. Then, it must be that the concept of God the GREATEST conceivable being includes something like being that has some knowledge. But, He must not just have SOME knowledge. Rather, He must have PERFECT knowledge, since God is the greatest, and it would be greater to have ALL the knowledge that one could have, rather than just some limited amount of knowledge. It follows that the concept of God includes omniscience (absolute knowledge). We can use similar reasoning to determine that the concept of God must also include omnipotence (absolute power) and omnibenevolence (moral perfection). But, wait. It seems like it is better to exist in reality than merely exist in the mind alone. If I told you that I had two awesome pizzas at home, one real and one imaginary, and asked you which one it would be better to have, it would make sense for you to say, The real one. The imaginary one doesn t sound all that great. But, in that case, existence (like knowledge, power, and moral goodness) is ALSO a great-making characteristic. So, it must follow that existence (in reality, rather than in the mind alone) is ALSO included in the concept of God, and is therefore an essential property of God. In other words, it is impossible to conceive of a supremely perfect being that does not exist. If we tried, we would just be imagining something that is NOT GOD. For, if we are imagining God as merely existing in our minds and not in reality, we are just imagining some LESS THAN supremely perfect being; it would be possible to imagine an even MORE perfect being still namely, one that EXISTS IN REALITY (because existing in the mind alone is less perfect than existing in reality). Therefore, God exists. One more time: Since existence is a great-making characteristic (i.e., it is better to exist than not exist), then it must be included in the concept of God, which is by definition the GREATEST conceivable being or the being with ALL of the great-making characteristics. Therefore, existence is one of the essential properties of a supremely perfect God. But, an essential property is one that INSEPARABLE from a thing. This means that to imagine God as not existing in reality is a contradiction (or else, you re not really imagining God at all). In other words, the claim God does not exist is as self-contradictory as the claim, Triangles do not have 3 sides. For, existence is a part of the very CONCEPT of God. So, God must exist in reality. 2

We might state this in argument form, as the following: 1. God is, by definition, the greatest conceivable being. 2. We have a mental concept of the greatest conceivable being. 3. To exist in reality is greater than merely existing in the mind alone. 4. Therefore, if you are considering the concept of God, then you are considering a being that exists in reality. Note: If the thing you are considering exists merely in the mind, then either: (a) You are NOT imagining the greatest conceivable being. (b) You are imagining a contradiction (the greatest conceivable being both existing and not existing); but this is impossible. 5. So, the being you have a concept of is one that exists in reality; i.e., God exists. Objection: Just because 3-sidedness is an essential property of triangles, this does not prove that triangles EXIST. It seems coherent to think of a triangle that exists only in my mind, and not in reality. So, why is God different? Reply: Because, we re not attributing something like 3-sidedness to God as an essential property. We are attributing EXISTENCE to God as an essential property. This makes God a special case. As such, God is the only being that can be demonstrated to exist merely by thinking about its attributes. 3. Gaunilo s Criticism: Is God really the ONLY being that can be demonstrated to exist in this way? Gaunilo, a contemporary of Anselm s, criticizes the above line of reasoning for leading to absurd conclusions. He thinks that, if Anselm s reasoning can be used to prove that God exists, then it can also be used to prove that ALL SORTS of things exist. For instance, consider The Lost Island : It is the most perfect possible island. It has perfect sand, perfect waterfalls, and the perfect number of coconuts. These are all essential properties of the island. But, it furthermore has the essential property of existing in reality, since the island would be less perfect if it existed in the mind alone. Therefore, the perfect island exists in reality. This sort of criticism is known as a reductio ad absurdum. This method of attack attempts to show that some line of reasoning that is thought to be correct actually leads to absurdities and for this reason, we should actually reject the line of reasoning as mistaken. Since Anselm s line of reasoning leads to the absurd conclusion that the perfect island exists (as well as the perfect pizza, and the perfect toilet, and the perfect paper clip), his line of reasoning must be mistaken. 3

Anselm s Reply: Anselm responded by insisting that God was the only sort of being to which his reasoning applied. Why does Anselm think this? First, we might think that certain sorts of perfections are impossible. For instance, what IS the most perfect number of coconuts for an island to have? The question does not seem to make sense. Other properties, such as knowledge, do not seem to have this problem. For instance, the most perfect amount of knowledge just seems to be ALL the knowledge that it is possible to have. (In contrast, an island that had all the coconuts sounds like a very crowded island.) In short, it seems like the only sorts of properties that can BE possessed perfectly are those that have MAXIMUM LIMITS. Just as there is no highest number, for SOME properties (such as number of coconuts), there is no perfect limit to that property. Now, imagine a being that possessed knowledge perfectly. Can you imagine that being as NOT knowing what 2+2 equals? NO, you CANNOT. For, you would either be imagining a contradiction (a perfect-knowledge being with imperfect knowledge), or else you are simply not imagining a being that possesses knowledge perfectly. It seems as if imagining a being with the maximum amount of a great-making property THAT HAS A MAXIMUM LIMIT is coherent. So, now imagine a being that has ALL the great-making properties that have a maximum limit. It seems that this being would also have to possess the great-making property of existing in reality. And this, supposedly, only applies to the being that has ALL the maximal-great-making properties. 4. Kant s Criticism: Immanuel Kant offered another criticism about 700 years later. Rather than trying to demonstrate that Anselm s reasoning leads to absurdities, he actually pointed out what the flaw in the reasoning was: Existence is not a great-making property. In fact, it is not a property at all! 1. Subjects and Predicates: In his Ontological Argument, Anselm claims that a contradiction arises when you assert God does not exist because the predicate existence is one of the predicates contained within the concept God. In other words, since existence is an essential property of God, saying God does not exist is like saying, God, who exists, does not exist, or A triangle does not have three sides (since threesidedness is an essential property of triangles). But, Kant says, a contradiction only arises when you assert the EXISTENCE of a subject without one or more of its essential properties. For instance, it WOULD be a contradiction to say that, A triangle exists, but it lacks three sides or There is a bachelor who is not male. This is because three-sidedness is ESSENTIAL to triangles, and being male is ESSENTIAL to bachelors. 4

Kant states that, when we give a list of some thing s essential properties, ALL we can infer from this is that, IF that thing exists, then it definitely has those properties. For instance, because triangles are essentially 3-sided, we may only infer that, IF a triangle exists, then it definitely has 3 sides. Similarly, even if existence is a part of the concept of God (since existence is one of the great-making properties ), all this entails is that, IF God exists, then He exists. And this is uninteresting, since it is trivially true. To deny the existence of the entity altogether, Kant says, is never a contradiction. For, in that case, all that you are asserting is that the concept itself, with all of its properties, is not instantiated anywhere (i.e., it is nowhere to be found). So, no contradiction arises. You re simply denying the existence of the object altogether. Admittedly, if Anselm s interpretation of the denial of God s existence were correct, it WOULD be a contradiction for, then, denying God s existence would be equivalent to stating: God exists, yet He lacks existence. But, Kant points out, the correct interpretation of the denial of God s existence is simply the claim that There is no existing thing that the concept of God identifies. Kant writes, when you say, God does not exist, neither omnipotence nor any other predicate is affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject, and in this judgment there cannot exist the least self-contradiction. To illustrate this point, consider: I am imagining Sunshine, the unicorn, in my mind right now. Consider a list of attributes that Sunshine has: Horse-shape Horned Pure white Super soft Fast Immortal Farts rainbows Exists Imagine that you tell me, Sunshine does not exist. Is this coherent? Now, according to Anselm, to deny the existence of Sunshine is to say something like Something HAS all of these attributes, and does not exist. If he were right, then the denial of Sunshine s existence would be equivalent to the claim that Sunshine exists, and does not exist. So, since the denial of Sunshine s existence is self-contradictory, it must be false. So, have we now proved that there ARE existing unicorns? Clearly not. 5

According to Kant, if I deny the existence of Sunshine, I am simply denying that there IS anything that exists which instantiates this whole list of properties. Denying the existence of sunshine is simply to CLEAR AWAY this WHOLE list of attributes and deny that they apply to anything. 2. Existence is not a predicate: Why doesn t the fact that we have a coherent concept of Sunshine, an existing unicorn, prove that there IS one? Where have we gone wrong? Kant states that the mistake is made when we treat existence as a predicate. A predicate is a thing you ascribe to a subject, and it is supposed to ADD something to the concept of that subject. For instance, I might say, Imagine a one hundred dollar bill. Now imagine that the bill is crumpled. Here, crumpled is a predicate (or, property) which ADDS something to your concept of the hundred dollar bill. But, imagine that I then say, Now imagine that the crumpled bill EXISTS. Have I added anything to your concept? Do you now picture the bill in some new way? Kant says no. Existence does not add anything to the concept. Existence, Kant says, does not function grammatically as a predicate, but rather as a copula. For instance, when we say, The bill is crumpled, we are uniting two concepts: the bill, and crumpled. Predicates ADD something to a subject; i.e., crumpled ADDS something to our concept of the bill. In contrast, the word is merely indicates the relation between the subject and the predicate. This is the function of a copula. So, existence is not a predicate. Any time we say that some subject IS some way e.g., the bill IS crumpled we re already attributing existence to the bill. So, strictly speaking, we should not say that God IS omniscient, omnipotent, etc. Rather, we should say simply that, IF God exists, THEN He is omniscient, omnipotent, etc. So, the denial of Sunshine s existence is not equivalent to Sunshine, who has the property of existing, does not exist. All we really mean is There is no existing thing that is horse-shaped, has a horn, is white, soft, farts rainbows, and so on. Likewise, with God. If existence is not a predicate, then it is not one of the perfections that the supremely perfect being needs to possess. If existence is not a predicate, not only is existence not a great-making property. IT IS NOT A PROPERTY AT ALL. So, the denial of God s existence is not the assertion of the contradictory statement, God, who has the property of existing, does not exist. Rather, we simply mean that There is no existing thing that has the properties of omniscience, omnipotence, omnibenevolence, and so on. And that is not a contradiction. 6

5. Peter van Inwagen s Explanation of the Confusion: van Inwagen puts it this way: The author Homer is generally thought to have these attributes: He was a blind, male Greek poet from the 8 th century BC, who wrote The Iliad and The Odyssey. Now imagine that (as is actually the case) two scholars disagree, one believing that Homer actually existed, and the other believing that Homer is a fictitious legend. It would be absurd to suggest that the first scholar believes that someone was a blind, male Greek poet from the 8 th century BC, and wrote The Iliad and The Odyssey, and existed, while the second scholar believes that someone was a blind, male Greek poet from the 8 th century BC, and wrote The Iliad and The Odyssey, and did not exist. Simply put, predicates (or, properties) are the ingredients of a concept, or items that pinpoint what it is to fall under a certain concept. But, existence is not a thing that CAN be such an ingredient. What these two scholars are disagreeing about is whether or not there was ever any individual who INSTANTIATED the properties of blind, male Greek poet from the 8 th century BC, who wrote The Iliad and The Odyssey. Confusion of Two Separate Arguments : van Inwagen then points out that the ontological argument is really muddling the following two separate arguments together: 1. Anything that is a perfect being has all perfections. 2. Existence is a perfection. 3. Therefore, anything that is a perfect being exists. 1. There is a perfect being that has all perfections. 2. Existence is a perfection. 3. Therefore, there is a perfect being that exists. The first argument is rather uninteresting. Its conclusion is trivial, and does not prove that God exists. The second argument begs the question that is, the conclusion is just a re-statement of the first premise (i.e., the premise assumes the very thing that is supposed to be proved). The reason the ontological argument may SEEM valid at first is because the reader takes the argument to be claiming the premise one on the LEFT (in red), and, along with premise 2 (which both arguments have in common), drawing the conclusion on the RIGHT (in red). Clearly, this would be a mistake. 7