Got Soul? Aristotle Democratizes and Demythologizes the Psuchê By Rich Halvorson January 2002

Similar documents
Aristotle and the Soul

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

The Divine Nature. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 3-11) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian J.

Roots of Psychology Aristotle and Descartes

INTRODUCTION. Historical perspectives of Naturalism

DR. LEONARD PEIKOFF. Lecture 3 THE METAPHYSICS OF TWO WORLDS: ITS RESULTS IN THIS WORLD

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

! Jumping ahead 2000 years:! Consider the theory of the self.! What am I? What certain knowledge do I have?! Key figure: René Descartes.

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

Descartes: A Guide for the Perplexed

Personal Identity and the Jehovah' s Witness View of the Resurrection

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

QUESTION 47. The Diversity among Things in General

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

Chapter Six. Putnam's Anti-Realism

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

W H A T I T M E A N S T O B E R E A L : T H E A N C I E N T S, T H E B I B L E, A N D U S

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

Thomas Aquinas on the World s Duration. Summa Theologiae Ia Q46: The Beginning of the Duration of Created Things

Conversation with Prof. David Bohm, Birkbeck College, London, 31 July 1990

Aristotle. Cause, Purpose and the Prime Mover

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2016

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

On Being and Essence (DE ENTE Et ESSENTIA)

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

The Debate Between Evolution and Intelligent Design Rick Garlikov

Sophia Perennis. by Frithjof Schuon

AQUINAS S FOURTH WAY: FROM GRADATIONS OF BEING

01. Pre-Socratic Cosmology and Plato I. Basic Issues

Aristotle and Aquinas

FAITH & reason. The Pope and Evolution Anthony Andres. Winter 2001 Vol. XXVI, No. 4

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Science. January 27, 2016

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Aquinas, Hylomorphism and the Human Soul

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

to representationalism, then we would seem to miss the point on account of which the distinction between direct realism and representationalism was

Today we re gonna start a number of lectures on two thinkers who reject the idea

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Aquinas, The Five Ways

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

A Priori Bootstrapping

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

Introduction to Philosophy PHL 221, York College Revised, Spring 2017

The Platonic tradition and concepts of Freewill

George Berkeley. The Principles of Human Knowledge. Review

Being and Substance Aristotle

QUESTION 3. God s Simplicity

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Comparative Philosophical Analysis on Man s Existential Purpose: Camus vs. Marcel

As far as physical extra-mental object, one might respond, but they see the cat. According to de Saussure, that is irrelevant. It makes little to no

What does Nature mean?

Lecture 7.1 Berkeley I


Philosophy is dead. Thus speaks Stephen Hawking, the bestknown

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

William Hasker s discussion of the Thomistic doctrine of the soul

Trinity & contradiction

science, knowledge, and understanding

Published in Analysis 61:1, January Rea on Universalism. Matthew McGrath

Dualism: What s at stake?

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 4b Free Will/Self

5 A Modal Version of the

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

The Solution to Skepticism by René Descartes (1641) from Meditations translated by John Cottingham (1984)

CALVARY 1 CORINTHIANS 15:35-49 APRIL 10, 2016 TEACHING PLAN

Overview Plato Socrates Phaedo Summary. Plato: Phaedo Jan. 31 Feb. 5, 2014

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Descartes is commonly regarded as the origin of mind body dualism and

Nature and Grace in the First Question of the Summa

Nagel, T. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press, 1986.

Cartesian Dualism. I am not my body

What am I? An immaterial thing: the case for dualism

From Physics, by Aristotle

QUESTION 58. The Mode of an Angel s Cognition

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven:

Duncan Lowe and Colin Hill Present:

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

The Theory of Reality: A Critical & Philosophical Elaboration

Class 18 - Against Abstract Ideas Berkeley s Principles, Introduction, (AW ); (handout) Three Dialogues, Second Dialogue (AW )

Evolution: The Darwinian Revolutions BIOEE 2070 / HIST 2870 / STS 2871

Human Nature & Human Diversity: Sex, Love & Parenting; Morality, Religion & Race. Course Description

Morally Adaptive or Morally Maladaptive: A Look at Compassion, Mercy, and Bravery

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

QUESTION 55. The Medium of Angelic Cognition

Transcription:

Got Soul? Aristotle Democratizes and Demythologizes the Psuchê By Rich Halvorson January 2002 Upon first glance, Aristotle s view of the soul may be a bit striking, if not absurd, in contrast to what a modern person is used to hearing. Perhaps a likely reaction would be, You re telling me that plants have souls? Whereas people today, as well as philosophers in classical Greece, were primarily concerned with the human soul, Aristotle believes that this is perhaps an elitist notion, if not entirely misdirected. Why does everyone spend so much time discussing the corporeality or incorporeality of the human soul, when we have not yet studied something simpler? Perhaps Plato should learn about the soul by discussing the soul of an apple tree rather than his own eternal fate. The problem with the human soul, it seems, is that in leaping to study the most complex thing first, we have lost the ability to give a thorough account of what the soul is and what it does in an otherwise lifeless body. The problem with Aristotle s approach, in the view of his contemporaries (and perhaps ours), is that it was ridiculous to think that plants and animals have souls! Besides the difficulty of Aristotle s concepts and terminology, we are asked to embrace a fundamentally new idea of what it means to have a soul, and who or what in fact has soul. As Aristotle begins to explain his view, he gives a general account for all living things that the soul is the first actuality of a natural body that is potentially alive (412a27). This definition is full of concepts, meaning and perhaps qualifications that will help demonstrate what Aristotle means once we explore them. In essence, Aristotle is saying that the soul is the primary reality and substance that allows non-living or even scattered materials to become one living being. The best way to think about soul in the Aristotelian sense involves neither a smoky New Orleans jazz club nor Judeo-Christian overtones of angelic harps and demonic hellfire. Instead, Aristotle views the soul as that which brings life itself into inanimate materials. The Aristotelian soul is what transforms dead matter into living being. Perhaps Louis Armstrong s fans believe that his jazz accomplishes this same purpose, and perhaps God s breath of life from Genesis is closer to this notion than we might normally conceive. However, non-aristotelian notions of soul tend to focus only on humans and pertain primarily to the spiritual or posthumous function. Are people only matter, or is there something more? Is there life after death? Is mental activity merely a byproduct of brain activity? Aristotle s view is exponentially broader than its rivals, including all living things as soulbearers plants, animals, humans and probably even prokaryotic bacteria. Moreover, it is much less heavenly and more earthly. The vast majority of souls (plants and non-human animals) and their capacities can only exist along with their matter; once the living thing dies, its soul perishes as well. The soul s purpose is not necessarily to attain to heaven, and in most cases is only to help the creature get nutrition, grow, and perceive the outside world. Because we do not normally think of soul as this type of life force in all living things, but restrict it only to humans life and imbue spiritualized connotations, it is probably most helpful to approach Aristotle with a tabula rasa. The reader should not ask where Aristotle s view fits within the spectrum of contemporary views of the soul or the question of eternal life. Instead, she should inquire of Aristotle, what are souls and what things have them? without a preconceived dialectic framework. Aristotle himself seems to adopt this approach and encourage it for his readers: Let us for now return and make a new start, trying to determine what the soul is and 1

what account of it best applies to all souls in common (412a5, emphasis mine). If we approach the text with our preconceived ideas about the soul, we will find ourselves quite confused or even scandalized imagining the absurd picture of a Judeo-Christian soul infused into a plant or a boar. Before we incorporate Aristotle s difficult concepts and terminology we must fundamentally revise our understanding of the soul s function and purpose. Moreover, the challenging terminology, such as potentiality and actuality, will be more clearly understood in light of a relatively straightforward example. What is the soul? Apple Seed Psuchê The Aristotelian soul is a kind of life force that can cause a natural body to move; it is the formal substance; and it is its purposeful end. In his own words, the soul is the cause and principle of the living body. Now, causes are spoken of in many ways, and the soul is a cause in three of the ways distinguished as the source of motion, as what something is for, and as the substance of ensouled bodies. (415b8-12) Since plants are normally furthest from our list of living things with souls, an illustration of Aristotelian soul in a plant may be helpful. The large apple tree we see today was once a dormant apple seed. When the apple seed begins the movement of sprouting, it is less than a gram and has within it neither the energy nor materials to complete the full-grown apple tree. It does, however, have an internal principle which is the soul of the apple tree that foreshadows and makes possible the life, nutrition, and growth of the seed into a sprout, and then into a seedling, and finally into a tree. This tree draws into itself an array of materials and energy in the process of growing from the seed. The scattered materials and the future form of the tree are, in an unconscious and impersonal sense, the desire of the soul within the apple seed. Its purpose and its ability is to put the matter of the seed into motion to draw in the available and necessary resources to produce its goal, which is a fully grown apple tree. This example of the plant is the simplest to begin with because the faculties and capacities of plants are the least among living things simply that of nutrition and growth. These functions, as capacities of the soul, show just how much Aristotle s conception of the soul is radically different from other views. For this reason, it is easier to begin with the apple tree s soul so that we make no mistakes of thinking the soul to be some supernatural substance like the Cartesian notion. Most contemporary notions of the soul lead to doubt or debate regarding its existence, showing that we tend to view it as something unobservable and unnatural (or supernatural). Scientists and laypeople observe matter constantly and the material world such that the existence of matter is rarely, if ever, challenged. These material observations contrast with our view of the immaterial soul which is something we cannot weigh, observe or count as we can with physical matter. The fact that there is a debate over the soul s existence shows that under our definition it is not so obviously present as Aristotle believed it to be. But this stems not so much from our lack of perception or Aristotle s exceptional empirical ability, but from a fundamentally different meaning. The soul, for Aristotle, is basically what our scientists mean when they say life. Certainly no one questions the fact that life exists; similarly, Aristotle did not question the soul s existence. Whereas the narrow modern conception of the supernatural 2

soul is hardly observable and many believe entirely absent the broader Aristotelian conception of the soul as life force is indubitable. Although this broader notion of soul bestows the fact of soulfulness upon more natural bodies, it unfortunately continues to elude perspicuous definition. For Aristotle, the nature of the soul is that essence which separates natural bodies into two categories: living and non-living. Those with life also have soul, and those without life also lack soul. At the hinge between animate and inanimate is a radical shift in the nature of the body s form. Let us consider our apple tree once again. If a couple comes to sit under the apple tree together on Monday, and the tree is alive, feeding itself and growing, then it is actually a tree. If the couple comes back on Tuesday and the tree has been chopped down, and is therefore dead, we can no longer properly say of the materials that they are an apple tree, but merely that it is a chunk of matter in the shape or appearance of an apple tree. So a tree is only a tree insofar as it participates (or could potentially participate) in the proper functions of tree life (life, nutrition, growth). Without these capacities, it no longer has the proper form of a tree. The proper form of a tree is life, the dead form of what was once a tree is only shape. Matter s Potentiality and Form s Actuality Nous About Nomenclature The foregoing illustration should provide a clear background of the Aristotelian conception of soul and cure us of the view that souls are only for humans. Upon that foundation of understanding, we can enter into Aristotle s terminology and understand what he means when he says that the soul is the first actuality of a natural body that is potentially alive (412a27). Once we realize the soul as natural, as essential to all life, it descends from the confounding mythologies that usually surround our notions about it. We can now ask simply and with clarity: What is the soul that it makes inanimate things come to life? In six words, Aristotle expresses the answer succinctly: Matter is potentiality, and form is actuality (412a10). Perhaps this quote illuminates the one prior to it, in that we should associate body with matter and the soul with form. Obviously, however, each of these terms demands its own definition and explanation. Since the soul is that which brings life to the lifeless, any body of matter is only potentially alive before it has a soul. Within the classification of natural bodies, Aristotle says that only an organic one is potentially alive (412b1). On the other hand, the inanimate organic body is not strictly potential. It is only potential with respect to life; it is actual with respect to its status as an organic body. As an actual organic body, its form is in its shape. When a bumblebee picks up pollen on its appendages, the pollen is merely lifeless organic material. Its actuality is realized in its physical and chemical description. When the bee touches down on another flower that is fertilized with the pollen, the pollen is incorporated into and originates a new process of life in which its actuality cannot be expressed merely in physical and chemical description, but has a principle of life propelling it towards nutrition, growth and reproduction. Whether the form is physical (such as the shape and size of the pollen granules) or it is soulful (such as the movement and purpose of the life cycle), matter must take on some form which is its actuality, and by which we can describe a this. With respect to life, the form of an organic body of matter has potential to assume the form and actuality of a living body. Every thing in the natural world has both form and matter; only organic bodies can potentially assume a soul as their form and thereby have life. Somewhere between the stillness of dead matter and the hum of life s constant motion, there must be something that sets everything in motion correctly. Further, all life seems to have 3

a directed purpose, such as growth, reproduction, or even abstract thought, there must be something to imbue this purpose into matter. Finally, it seems that we cannot fully describe a living body with a strictly physical account, there must be some essence which accounts for this difference. These describe the soul s function as efficient, final, and formal causes, respectively. The precise moment before and after death, the atoms of a body may be numerically the same and in exactly the same position and shape. However, there is something that causes these to move peculiarly while alive, like the cooperative parts of a cell making RNA or the blood coursing through the veins. What is it that sets these incredibly complex systems in motion and keeps them going? Ultimately, it is the soul, and in this example it is seen in its characterization as the efficient cause. The soul expresses itself also as a final cause, or telos, of a living organism. We see this as we can tell that there is a proper end or proper goal of living things. The soul works in the creature towards this goal. It does not work perfectly, but it aims at some goal. We can see this in looking at a healthy dog and a three-legged dog side-by-side. As the two dogs walk around, it is obvious that the essence of doghood is most fully realized approaches its telos in its healthy, four-legged form. Similarly in humans, plants, and animals, each living thing seems to have a goal or telos towards which it tends and, in a sense, innately and unconsciously desires. In this way, the soul provides a final cause by which the internal workings of organisms strive toward realizing some proper form of a human, dog, or daisy. The soul is also the formal cause of a living thing. As we expressed before, the potentiality of organic matter for life is realized when the actuality of the soul joins closely with it in the act of living. This joining is not in a Platonic or dualistic sense for Aristotle, but is usually inseparable and for the good of the soul, not its detriment, as in Plato s Timaeus. Aristotle does not believe that the body is the tomb of the soul, but that the body allows the soul to fully realize itself. Thus the union of soul and body is a much closer and mutually beneficial association. For plants and animals, there is no part of the soul that persists after death both body and soul are entirely inseparable and mortal. Nonetheless, it is proper to speak of the actuality of joining body and soul, as Aristotle tells us the animal is soul plus body (413a3). Moreover, this actuality must be understood in two tiers. The primary actuality consists in a living thing s existence and potential for carrying out its proper soulful capacities. The secondary actuality consists in participating in those soulful capacities. Aristotle describes this concept using two examples. First he describes an ax qua ax with the potential to cut and contrasts this with the act of cutting. Second he describes an eye with the potential to see and contrasts that with the act of seeing. Using these examples to illustrate the tiers of actuality, he says: Being awake, then, is a second actuality, corresponding to cutting or seeing. The soul is a first actuality, corresponding to the faculty of sight and to the potentiality of the instrument to cut; and the body is potentially this. And as an eye is the pupil plus sight, so an animal is soul plus body. (413a1-3) Likening this to our example of the apple tree, the soul of an apple tree corresponds to the capacity for nutrition, growth, and apple production. Realizing these by actually absorbing water and nutrients, getting taller, and sprouting apples off the branches is a secondary actuality. Therefore the soul s actuality does not consist necessarily in doing these things, but is often seen secondarily out of the capacity to do these things. The soul s actuality is the potential for growth, reproduction, perception or thought. When the soul joins with an organic body, it 4

gives it life by imbuing the capacities for all of life s activities. The body is fully alive, however, before it utilizes or participates in any of these capacities. Damaging Democritus and Polishing Plato Aristotle s elaboration of the soul and its functions pulls the speculations of his contemporaries down from the clouds and into the real world of life, attempting to understand what makes life out of otherwise nonliving matter. For Aristotle, neither the Platonists nor the followers of Leucippus and Democritus had engaged the right question. As the sparring groups haggle over their narrow theories that turn on the hinge of corporeality, Aristotle says they have completely missed the boat. He offers instead a robust theory grounded in observable reality and ranging into the speculative world of metaphysics only in the case of explaining nous. He fits this complex question into his framework of the four causes, explaining that for living beings, the soul provides all three immaterial causes and must only be added to a material cause. Aristotle is vulnerable to the charge of simply redefining terms to suit his liking. Since Aristotle attempted to dramatically shift the concept of soul to a much more earthly and biological notion, he could simply be explaining more easily understood phenomena and calling it psuchê despite the fact that it is entirely different from what his interlocutors mean by the same term. It seems that this charge does have an element of truth, and Aristotle is certainly much less concerned with the eternal implications of nous than with the temporal revelations his theory yields. Yet while the criticism is valid, it is also true that Aristotle s soul actually teaches us much more about life than the speculations of the dualists. Perhaps if they brought the debate over corporeality within the framework of the four causes, the dialogue would become much more fruitful. In some sense, Aristotle bows out of the heated debate of corporeality and incorporeality and takes up his work elsewhere. He sits on the fence between the materialist and the dualist, arguing for the eternality of the intellect like the dualist but accounting for most soulful functions (such as getting nutrition, growing, perception, emotion) in a much more earthly fashion like the materialist. He chooses not to spill too much ink over this point and to try to make progress on a different front. The critic might also be concerned with the multiplicity of souls within individuals and among species. If the soul has many parts grounded in its various capacities, does this destroy the unity of the soul? Moreover, some souls seem to be divisible in a way that is not so much troubling as simply in need of further elaboration. When one cuts a rose and puts it in water, are the souls of roses then multiplied, since both the bush and the flower continue to grow and bloom? Similarly, there are some animals, certain worms, that one can cut in half and they regenerate both halves into a full adult. What does this mean for the multiplication of souls? Psuchê seems to be itself an incorporeal and elusive essence which comes from nowhere, and disappears into nonexistence at death (except nous). While Aristotle provides much more solid ground regarding the soul than his contemporaries, this problem of soul also leaves much explanation. From whence does the soul come? How does it multiply readily in some living things? A more serious objection to Aristotle s definition of the soul lies in the problem that the soul is an essence, and yet only those things with essences are definable. According to Aristotle, souls are nothing apart from the potentialities they bring: 5

Clearly, then, soul will have one single account in the same way that figure has; for just as figure is nothing apart from the triangle and the figures that follow in order, so equally the soul is nothing apart from those potentialities we have mentioned. (414b20-22) If definition applies only to bodies that have essences, and yet souls are essences in themselves as a triangle is nothing more than a three-sided figure then we raise the question of whether souls can be defined. It is possible to give a single account, but this seems to be nothing more than naming the conglomeration of the potentialities a living thing entails. Perhaps this means that the soul is loosely known as the various potentialities life brings to matter. Conclusion Aristotle brought his system of philosophy, his ideas and his four causes to bear upon the problem of psuchê and ended up with an entirely different focus than philosophers in his day or ours. Of course, the human question of eternal life continually draws our minds back toward our own souls: what will happen to me when I die? Aristotle s approach, by describing the soul as a shared substance of all living things, brings a much more practical and less egocentric view of life, body and soul. While his writings are often in the cryptic form of lecture notes and he was constrained by the limited language, Aristotle s writings on the soul remain insightful and original. Indeed, despite his attempt to recast the debate in different terms we see that the debate has made little progress in the two millennia since he wrote. Platonic dualists and Epicurean materialists abound under different names and in a variety of flavors, yet the debate hinges essentially on the same metaphysical question now as it did in 300 B.C. This question of corporeality should not be ignored, but perhaps answers could be better pursued within the Aristotelian four causes framework. Even though I began as quite a skeptic of Aristotle s view, the more I consider it, it seems quite appealing. Can we describe matter without form? Can we fully explain the world in efficient causes? Does life necessarily entail a final cause? Even as I try to draw myself away from assenting to Aristotle s conclusions, his argument and even the intuitive appeal of his framework are difficult to avoid. Perhaps we should conclude with Aristotle as a heuristic if not in concrete that all life has soul as its primary substance. Despite the common attempts to explain life in the world solely in terms of efficient cause (perhaps with formal and material implied), Aristotle seems correct that life has a purposive teleological end. It seems both practical and plausible to redefine psuchê as the essence which is all three formal, efficient and final causes leaving only the material cause, an organic body, to which it is enjoined.in forming life. 6