What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency

Similar documents
Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Ludwig Wittgenstein: Philosophical Investigations

Wittgenstein: Meaning and Representation

Skepticism, Naturalism, and Therapy

The Representation of Logical Form: A Dilemma

WITTGENSTEIN ON EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF LOGIC 1

Negative Facts. Negative Facts Kyle Spoor

Philosophy 427 Intuitions and Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Fall 2011

Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Language

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

The purpose of this paper is to introduce the problem of skepticism as the

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Wittgenstein on Scepticism

Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (abridged version) Ludwig Wittgenstein

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Epistemology. PH654 Bethel Seminary Winter To be able to better understand and evaluate the sources, methods, and limits of human knowing,

Bridging Faith and Knowledge. through Wittgenstein s On Certainty

Descartes and Foundationalism

Class 4 - The Myth of the Given

Norman Malcolm ( )

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Epistemology Naturalized

WHERE ARE WE KNOW NOW?

Review of Steven D. Hales Book: Relativism and the Foundations of Philosophy

University of International Business and Economics International Summer Sessions. PHI 110: Introduction to Philosophy

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

The Assumptions Account of Knowledge Attributions. Julianne Chung

Wittgenstein and the Skeptical Paradoxes

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

DEGREES OF CERTAINTY AND SENSITIVE KNOWLEDGE: A REPLY TO SOLES. Samuel C. Rickless. [Penultimate version of a paper published in Locke Studies (2015)]

Philosophy A465: Introduction to Analytic Philosophy Loyola University of New Orleans Ben Bayer Spring 2011

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Logic, Truth & Epistemology. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

2014 THE BIBLIOGRAPHIA ISSN: Online First: 21 October 2014

Supplementary Section 6S.7

Issues in Thinking about God. Michaelmas Term 2008 Johannes Zachhuber

Philosophy 335: Theory of Knowledge

Foundations of Analytic Philosophy

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

UC San Diego UC San Diego Previously Published Works

Carnap s Non-Cognitivism as an Alternative to Both Value- Absolutism and Value-Relativism

The Elimination Of Metaphysics

Wittgenstein s On Certainty Lecture 2

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

BLACKWELL PUBLISHING THE SCOTS PHILOSOPHICAL CLUB UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS

THE AIM OF THIS PAPER IS TO PROVIDE AN OVERVIEW OF ONE ASPECT OF

DOES SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING SOLVE THE BOOTSTRAPPING PROBLEM?

Philosophy and Logical Syntax (1935)

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

WITTGENSTEIN ON LANGUAGE, REALITY AND RELIGION

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

AN APPROACH TO WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

AUSTIN AND WITTGENSTEIN ON "DOUBT" AND "KNOWLEDGE" imarquette University

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

REASONING ABOUT REASONING* TYLER BURGE

General Philosophy. Dr Peter Millican,, Hertford College. Lecture 4: Two Cartesian Topics

Symbols in Wittgenstein s Tractatus. Colin Johnston

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

Descartes Method of Doubt

Meditation 1: On what can be doubted

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

ON NONSENSE IN THE TRACTATUS LOGICO-PHILOSOPHICUS: A DEFENSE OF THE AUSTERE CONCEPTION

Conditionals II: no truth conditions?

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

MOORE, THE SKEPTIC, AND THE PHILOSOPHICAL CONTEXT * Wai-hung Wong

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

Wittgenstein s Logical Atomism. Seminar 8 PHIL2120 Topics in Analytic Philosophy 16 November 2012

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:


Wittgenstein, Kierkegaard and the Unspeakable

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

John Locke. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding

PL 399: Knowledge, Truth, and Skepticism Spring, 2011, Juniata College

New Chapter: Epistemology: The Theory and Nature of Knowledge

Nozick and Scepticism (Weekly supervision essay; written February 16 th 2005)

Contemporary Epistemology

Wittgenstein on forms of life: a short introduction

Reason and Explanation: A Defense of Explanatory Coherentism. BY TED POSTON (Basingstoke,

Death and Immortality (by D Z Phillips) Introductory Remarks

Berkeley, Three dialogues between Hylas and Philonous focus on p. 86 (chapter 9) to the end (p. 93).

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

KIERKEGAARD, WITTGENSTEIN, AND PHILOSOPHICAL DOUBT. Eric Froom. Thesis. Submitted to the Faculty of the. Graduate School of Vanderbilt University

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Some remarks on verificationism, constructivism and the Principle of Excluded Middle in the context of Colour Exclusion Problem

Proofs of Non-existence

Anton Wilhelm Amo: The African Philosopher in 18th Europe

The Metaphysical Status of Tractarian Objects 1

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

CURRICULUM VITAE STEPHEN JACOBSON. (Title: What's Wrong With Reliability Theories of Justification?)

Hume on Ideas, Impressions, and Knowledge

WITTGENSTEIN S PRIVATE LANGUAGE ARGUMENT ACCORDING TO KRIPKE. Wittgenstein according to Kripke 1

WEEK 1: WHAT IS KNOWLEDGE?

Transcription:

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge? : An Analysis of the Context Dependency of Knowledge YAMADA Keiichi Abstract: This paper aims to characterize Wittgenstein s view of knowledge. For this purpose, I will contrast his view of knowledge with that of traditional philosophers. Especially he shows that our beliefs are justified not within our minds but within our language games. I show how Wittgenstein translated the problem of epistemology into the problem of language, such as the grammatical connection between the words know and doubt and the grammatical difference between the words knowledge and certainty. Introduction Wittgenstein is known as the philosopher engaged in the problem of language and logic. But he had struggled with the problem of knowledge and certainty especially for his last one and a half years. This paper aims to characterize Wittgenstein s view of knowledge in contrast to that of traditional philosophy. Initially, I will provide a summary of the contrast of both views in four theses. Knowledge according to traditional philosophy (1) Knowledge certainty (indubitable). (2) The exemplar of knowledge is the one about my own mental state. (3) My belief is justified within my mind. (4) The truth value of I know p is invariable. Knowledge according to Wittgenstein (1) Knowledge Certainty (2) My own mental state is not an object of knowledge (3) My belief is justified not within my mind but within our language games. (4) The truth value of I know p depends on the language game. I will explain each thesis below. In the next section, I will briefly show how traditional philosophers have dealt with knowledge. 1. Knowledge according to traditional philosophy (1) Knowledge = certainty (indubitable). According to Cartesian Skepticism (Cf. Descartes (1641)), we must doubt all of our ordinary beliefs in order to determine their accuracy. If we find something that cannot be doubted, we must know it with certainty, and it can thus become the basis of our ordinary beliefs. In this sense, knowledge must be certain (indubitable). Certain knowledge is the foundation of our belief system and justifies our ordinary beliefs (what is called foundationalism ). 19

33 (2) The exemplar of knowledge is that of my own mental state. I cannot make a mistake about my own mental state (e.g., I am in pain ). However, I can make a mistake about the outer world (e.g., That is a cat ). Therefore, my beliefs about my own mental state are more certain (indubitable) than those about the outer world. Because of this contrast, we must mirror the outer world in our minds as accurately as possible in order to know certainly a state of the world. (Rorty (1979) called such mind models The Mirror of Nature. ) (3) My belief is justified within my mind. Descartes employed the well-known criterion clara et distincta ( clear and distinct ) in order to judge what belief is true. According to this criterion, only those things that I can perceive clearly and distinctly are known to be true. Of course, this verification is done within my mind. (4) The truth value of I know p is invariable. Generally, the truth value of a sentence (e.g., Tokyo is the capital of Japan ) changes only when the way world is changes (e.g., when the capital of Japan is changed). If such a change does not take place, the truth value of the sentence is invariable. Therefore, as long as the facts about my cognitive state (this is the one of the way the world is) do not change, the truth value of I know p is invariable. (This idea is called the invariantism of knowledge by Unger (1984).) We will see below why and how Wittgenstein denied the four theses of knowledge above. Initially, I will simply clarify his (1) thesis ((1) Knowledge Certainty). Wittgenstein discriminates certainty from knowledge, as against traditional philosophers. The distinction is as follows: Knowledge is a result of the elimination of error possibilities. Certainty is equal to the absence of error possibilities. In the following discussion, I want to clarify the meaning of this discrimination. 2. Do I know that I am in pain? Wittgenstein holds that the proposition I know that I am in pain is not true but senseless (neither true nor false). He writes as follows in his later work, Philosophical Investigations (PI): In what sense are my sensations private? Well, only I can know whether I am really in pain; another person can only surmise it. In one way this is wrong, and in another nonsense. If we are using the word to know as it is normally used (and how else are we to use it?), then other people very often know when I am in pain. (PI 246) Philosophers committed to Cartesian Skepticism insist that I can know that I am in pain, but I cannot know that another person is in pain. However, Wittgenstein insists that I cannot know I am in pain, but I can know that he is in pain. That is, 20

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge?: An Analysis of the Context Dependency of Knowledge YAMADA (2) My own mental state is not an object of knowledge Why is this? Perhaps one of the roots of this idea can be found in his early thought of meaningful condition of propositions in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. In this work, he holds that a proposition must be able to be not only true but also false in order to have sense. Thus, the tautology (e.g., A A) as well as the contradiction (e.g., A A) have no sense (sinnlos). The proposition shows what it says, the tautology and the contradiction that they say nothing. The tautology has no truth-conditions, for it is unconditionally true; and the contradiction is on no condition true. Tautology and contradiction are without sense (sinnlos). (TLP 4.461) Now let us consider whether I know that I am in pain can be false. This proposition cannot be false. Not because it is a clear and distinct fact for me that I am in pain but because I cannot understand the meaning of the words the pain that I don t know. If someone were to say, I don t know whether I am in pain, we could not understand him and would think that he is using the word pain or know in a different way from our normal use. This is because the words I know p are used in situations where there are possibilities of making a mistake in believing p and I can eliminate these error possibilities. In case of my pain, there is no possibility of making a mistake about my pain. So, Wittgenstein thinks I know that I am in pain to be senseless. 3. Is my belief justified within my mind? The previous section has shown the grammatical connection between the concept of knowledge and error possibilities. In this section, we consider how error possibilities become relevant to us. I will begin with the following ordinary fact: frequently, the words I know p are used in situations where someone doubts p. Let us say that someone said to me, I am not sure if that is a cat. In response to this, I must prove that is a cat. But how to prove this depends on the context. This is because the doubt that p has a different meaning according to context and its difference reflects the negative possibilities of p implied by the doubt. We can think of some cases where she doubts P1 (P1: that is a cat). In Case 1, she may think that it is (not a cat but) a dog (P2). In Case 2, she may think it is (not a cat but) a stuffed toy (P3). In both Case 1 and Case 2, the question is the same, whether P1 or not. But the negative possibilities of P1 are different (P2 P3). From this distinction, we see the way to show that I know P1 is different. In Case 1, I have to provide evidence that it is not a dog, e.g., its size, shape, call, etc. (R2). With such evidence, I can say, e.g., It has such a round face, so it can t be a dog. In Case 2, I have to provide evidence that it is not a stuffed toy, e.g., its motions, reactions, expression, etc. (R3). Using these, I can say When I poked it, it moved. So, it can t be a stuffed toy. 21

33 The evidence in Case 1 does not justify my belief of P1 in Case 2, and vice versa. It has such a round face. So it can t be a stuffed toy. When I poked it, it moved. So it can t be a dog. Therefore, justification rules vary with contexts. I will call this view contextualism of justification (cf. Cohen (1988), Lewis (1996), DeRose (2002); they are called epistemological contextualism or conversational contextualism ). Wittgenstein would call these contexts not conversational contexts but language games. He would say that different language games are played in Case 1 and Case 2 and that different justification rules (R2 and R3) are adopted to prove the same P1. We can rephrase the above consideration as thesis (3), which contradicts thesis (3) of traditional philosophers. (3) My belief is justified not within my mind but within our language games This thesis implies I know that p does not signify my mental state but my epistemic status given in language games, which determine what is required to justify that p. But what does it mean that language games are different? And what determines which games we are engaged in? In the next section, I want to answer these questions using the idea of hinge propositions. 4. Is the truth value of I know that p invariable? Wittgenstein intensively considered problems of knowledge and certainty in his last work (On Certainty). He states: If I make an experiment, I do not doubt the existence of the apparatus before my eyes. I have plenty of doubts, but not that. (OC 337) In a chemical experiment, we can raise questions about various facts such as the existence of CO2 in a gas. The rule of its justification is, e.g., observing that the calcic water turns white when the gas enters it (hereinafter called Rule E ). We can play this Experiment Game (hereinafter called Game E ) as long as there are apparatuses such as a beaker with calcic water, a plastic bag with gas, and so on. Certainly, I can doubt there are apparatuses (PA) in an anomalistic situation such as one wherein I am seeing a hologram made by a shining laser. In such a situation, I can doubt the existence of these apparatuses; this doubt implies the negative possibility that they are (not apparatuses but) holograms (not PA). Thus, there are error possibilities, and the sentence I know that there are apparatuses (PA) is meaningful in this context. However, in an ordinary situation, I do not in fact doubt that there are apparatuses. Furthermore, I cannot continue to play Game E if I doubt that there are apparatuses. Wittgenstein expresses a role of this proposition by the metaphor of a hinge. That is to say, the questions that we raise and our doubts depend on the fact that some proposi- 22

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge?: An Analysis of the Context Dependency of Knowledge YAMADA tions are exempt from doubt, are as it were like hinges on which those turn. (OC 341) Among students of Wittgenstein s philosophy, such propositions (as PA) are commonly called hinge propositions. We can restate this point as the necessary condition of the rules of language games below. If the hinge propositions of the game are not true, the justification rules of the game cease to be in effect. In the above case, if Game E s hinge proposition, there are apparatuses, is not true, we observe that the calcic water turns white when the gas is entered in it also cannot be true; therefore, Game E s justification rule (Rule E) cannot be in effect. Of course, it is possible to doubt the hinge proposition, as in the previous context, but then that game (hereinafter called Game H ) is designed to confirm whether there are apparatuses or not (not hologram), a different game from Game E (Fig. 1). (Fig. 1 ) So, when I have a good evidence for whether there is CO 2 in the gas in Game E, in Game H, I do not know that, even though I have the same evidence as that in Game E. That is to say, the truth value of I know that there is CO 2 in the gas varies depending on which language game I am playing. That is, (4) The truth value of I know p depends on the language game A similar relation holds in the case of the previous section. In Case 1 s justification rule, observing the shape of the object can justify that is a cat, only if that object is not a stuffed toy but a living being (I will refer to the game that adopts Case 1 s rule as Game 1 ). Epistemic activities in Game 1 are possible, as long as it is not doubted whether the object is a living being and the object is a living being is a hinge proposition in Game 1 ( as it were like hinges on which those turn ). If some concrete reason to doubt this proposition arises, Case 1 s justification rule cannot be used, and Game 2, which adopts justification rule 2 (confirming whether the object moves when it is poked), begins (Fig. 2). In this aspect, hinge propositions define the limit of the game. In other words, which propositions are hinge propositions (what propositions are exempt from doubt) deter- 23

33 (Fig. 2 ) mines the direction of research in the language game (what should be doubted in that research game) and the direction of research determines what justification rule we should adopt ( justification contextualism in the previous section). Wittgenstein expresses his attitude toward hinge propositions ( ) by the words sureness (Sicherheit) or certainty (Gewissheit) (not knowledge (Wissenshaft)). Here remember Thesis (1), which discriminates certainty from knowledge, as follows: Knowledge is a result of the elimination of error possibilities. Certainty is equal to the absence of error possibilities. In our examples, I am sure that there are apparatuses or that that is a living being, without being justified in believing so. This state is different from knowledge, which means I can eliminate error possibilities using justification rules ( ). Rather, it makes the game such that there are no error possibilities about each hinge proposition within the game. 5. Do I know that there is a hand here? On the basis of the previous discrimination, Wittgenstein attempts to deal with the problem of skepticism. He writes as follows, in response to Moore, who raised his hand and said, I know that there is a hand here, as an argument against skepticism. It s not a matter of Moore s knowing that there s a hand there, but rather that we should not understand him if he were to say Of course I may have erred about this. We should ask What is it like to make such an error as that? e.g., what s it like to discover that it was an error? (OC 32) Some of the reasons why the sentence I know that there is a hand here is senseless are the same as those for I know that I am in pain in section 2. In short, there are no error possibilities to be eliminated, for I cannot understand making a mistake in determining that there is a hand. But there is the different point between the pain case and the hand case. In the pain case, I cannot make a mistake about the existence of my pain, because of the grammar of the word pain, but in the case of the hand, I can make a mistake about the existence of my 24

What is Wittgenstein s View of Knowledge?: An Analysis of the Context Dependency of Knowledge YAMADA hand in some anomalistic situation. Suppose that I was injured in a severe accident, and I awake after surgery under anesthetic. In this situation, I can doubt whether my hand is there, and there is a possibility of mistaking the existence of my hand. Thus, I can say, I know that there is a hand here by observing my hand or by hearing someone s testimony. In this context, I know that there is a hand here is meaningful. But the important point is that this case is not the normal case but an abnormal case. One may be wrong even about there being a hand here. Only in particular circumstances is it impossible. Even in a calculation one can be wrong only in certain circumstances one can t. OC 25 If, however, one wanted to give something like a rule here, then it would contain the expression in normal circumstances. And we recognize normal circumstances but cannot precisely describe them. At most, we can describe a range of abnormal ones. (OC 27) Thus, I can summarize the difference between the case of pain and the case of the hand as follows. In the case of pain, I know that I am in pain is senseless in all situations. In the case of one s hand, I know that there is a hand here is senseless in normal situations, but it has sense in abnormal situations. But what is it like to be normal? It is very difficult to define it in words. However, we can say that our ordinary life is formed by not doubting the existence of our hands. It is our normal form of life (Lebensform). This point shows the difference between the case of the hand and the case of the cat (or the experiment case). We can doubt the hinge proposition in the case of the cat, that is a living being, in normal situations because we have our ordinary practices of confirming whether such a thing is a living being or not. Thus, we can give expressions of doubt and knowledge an ordinary meaning. But confirming whether our hands exist is not our ordinary practice. We can provide neither doubting nor the knowing of their existence with an ordinary meaning. Moreover, Game 2, where the hinge propositions of Game 1 ( that is a living being ) is doubted, and Game H, where the hinge propositions of Game E ( there are apparatuses ) are doubted, are possible without the doubt of the existence of our own hands. If this were not a hand, I could not poke the object or touch the beaker. In this sense, the proposition there is a hand here plays a role as a hinge in almost all of (Fig. 3 ) 25

33 our ordinary language games in which we judge what belief is true (Fig. 3). Conclusion Most of the above discussion depends on the ordinary meaning of our language. This argument does not refute skepticism; in short, it does not show that we cannot give skeptical doubt some philosophical meaning which is different from ordinary meaning (see chapter 2 of Yamada (2009)). However, it reminds us of where the word know comes originally from. We may say Wittgenstein translated the problem of epistemology into the problem of language, such as the grammatical connection between the words know and doubt and the grammatical difference between the words knowledge and certainty. If we express this difference using early Wittgenstein s distinction between can be said and can be shown, we could say that knowledge can be said within language games, and certainty can be shown without words by our research practices. References Cohen, S. (1988), How to be a Fallibilist, Philosophical Perspective, vol. 2, pp. 91-123. DeRose, K. (2002), Assertion, Knowledge, and Context, The Philosophical Review, Vol. 111, No. 2, pp. 167-203. Descartes, R. (1641), Meditations on First Philosophy, Cottingham. J. (ed./trans.), Cambridge University Press, 1985. Lewis, D. (1996), Elusive Knowledge, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74, 4, pp. 549-67. Rorty, R. (1979), Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton University Press. Unger, P. (1984), Philosophical Relativity, University of Minnesota Press. Wittgenstein, L. (1922), Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (TLP), Routledge and Kegan Paul. (1953), Philosophical Investigations (PI), Blackwell. (1969), On Certainty (OC), Blackwell. Yamada, K. (2009), Wittgesntein Saigo no Sikou (The Last Thinking of Wittgenstein), Keiso Shobo. 26