Ibn Sīnā s modal logic

Similar documents
Handout for: Ibn Sīnā: analysis with modal syllogisms

Ibn Sīnā: analysis with modal syllogisms. Dedicated to my grandson Austin Jacob Hodges (6lb) born Wednesday 16 November 2011

What would count as Ibn Sīnā (11th century Persia) having first order logic?

Reconciling Greek mathematics and Greek logic - Galen s question and Ibn Sina s answer

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

A-LEVEL Religious Studies

A note: Ibn Sīnā on the subject of logic

1/12. The A Paralogisms

Predicate logic. Miguel Palomino Dpto. Sistemas Informáticos y Computación (UCM) Madrid Spain

Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Remarks on a Foundationalist Theory of Truth. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Coordination Problems

Ibn Sīnā on Logical Analysis. Wilfrid Hodges and Amirouche Moktefi

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

17. Tying it up: thoughts and intentionality

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

THE CAMBRIDGE SOLUTION TO THE TIME OF A KILLING LAWRENCE B. LOMBARD

Reply to Bronstein, Leunissen, and Beere

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Must we have self-evident knowledge if we know anything?

1 Clarion Logic Notes Chapter 4

1 Concerning distinction 39 I ask first whether God immutably foreknows future

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

Informalizing Formal Logic

John Buridan on Essence and Existence

Ibn Sīnā on reductio ad absurdum

Durham Research Online

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

On The Logical Status of Dialectic (*) -Historical Development of the Argument in Japan- Shigeo Nagai Naoki Takato

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

(Some More) Vagueness

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Future Contingents, Non-Contradiction and the Law of Excluded Middle Muddle

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

Varieties of Apriority

Intuitive evidence and formal evidence in proof-formation

VERITAS EVANGELICAL SEMINARY

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

The Subjectivity of Values By J.L. Mackie (1977)

HANDBOOK. IV. Argument Construction Determine the Ultimate Conclusion Construct the Chain of Reasoning Communicate the Argument 13

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Department of Philosophy. Module descriptions 2017/18. Level C (i.e. normally 1 st Yr.) Modules

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 2. Background Material for the Exercise on Inference Indicators

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Am I free? Freedom vs. Fate

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

Facts and Free Logic. R. M. Sainsbury

Facts and Free Logic R. M. Sainsbury

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

UC Berkeley, Philosophy 142, Spring 2016

Symbolic Logic Prof. Chhanda Chakraborti Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Kharagpur

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

The distinction between truth-functional and non-truth-functional logical and linguistic

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

Russell: On Denoting

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Theories of propositions

prohibition, moral commitment and other normative matters. Although often described as a branch

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

SYLLOGISTIC LOGIC CATEGORICAL PROPOSITIONS

Syllogisms in Aristotle and Boethius

What we want to know is: why might one adopt this fatalistic attitude in response to reflection on the existence of truths about the future?

First Principles. Principles of Reality. Undeniability.

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

1. Lukasiewicz s Logic

Affirmation-Negation: New Perspective

THE FORM OF REDUCTIO AD ABSURDUM J. M. LEE. A recent discussion of this topic by Donald Scherer in [6], pp , begins thus:

Transcription:

1 3 Ibn Sīnā s modal logic Wilfrid Hodges Herons Brook, Sticklepath, Okehampton November 2012 http://wilfridhodges.co.uk/arabic20a.pdf For Ibn Sīnā, logic is a tool for checking the correctness of arguments. More precisely it checks inference steps, starting from their premises (even if what mainly interests us is the conclusion). Paradigm case: two premises, both of them simple sentences (i.e. no subclauses). 2 4 We have four main sources for Ibn Sīnā s modal logic: (1) The Middle Epitome, c. 1013, available only in ms. (2) The logic of Najā ( Rescue ), also written c. 1013 but slightly revised for a later work. Translation Avicenna s Deliverance Logic, Asad Q. Ahmed 2011. (3) Books ii iv of Qiyās in the Šifā, mid 1020s. By far the fullest at about 140 pages. About a third in draft translation on my website. (4) The logic of Išārāt wa-tanbīhāt, late 1020s. Trans. Ibn Sīnā Remarks and Admonitions: Logic, S. Inati 1984. Sample simple sentence, analysed à la Ibn Sīnā: boy I good copula (±) 6 maybe I deserves I fudge

5 7 The next step is to cut down to the core (subject word, predicate word, quantifier, affirmative/negative): boy copula (+) I deserves If yes so far, then we restore the adjunctions (lawāḥīq, ziyādāt, šurūṭ) that were stripped off the core earlier. We test whether the earlier conclusion still survives, and with what adjunctions. This is murā c ātu l-šurūṭ, taking care of the conditions. This last stage is where we restore the mode. There are a rule of productivity for the mode, and a rule identifying the c ibra, i.e. the premise whose mode the conclusion follows. 6 8 Comparing the two premise cores tells us what figure (if any) the syllogism will be in, by checking where the same word appears in both premises. Then a condition of productivity (šarṭu l-intāj) tells us whether there is a conclusion. If yes, then rules of following tell us the quality and quantity of the conclusion, normally in terms of which premise the conclusion follows. So far, no great disagreement with Aristotle. Probably Ibn Sīnā thought he was taking all this from Aristotle. But now comes the major difference, which Ibn Sīnā repeatedly stresses:

9 11 Essential sentences: The range of adjunctions appearing in normal scientific discourse is very much more varied than Aristotle ever admits. It includes masses more than just modes. Examples: human is I animal I all the time he exists 10 12 Descriptional sentences: person-writing I at time t copula (+) I moves hand I at time t horse copula (+) I sleeps I sometime while it exists

13 15 Truth on the quantifier : this copula (+) 6 I medicine usually works I on people not too fat colour is I black in situation s 14 16 human copula (+) I laughs I because he s rational So when the stripped off adjunctions are restored, taking care of the conditions can be an open-ended task. This is both because of the variety of sentence-forms, and also because each speaker s intention (not formal rules of language, Ibn Sīnā stresses) determines the meaning of the speaker s utterance. Ibn Sīnā has no comprehensive procedure for it. Instead:

17 19 1. Ibn Sīnā classifies the possible adjunctions into three groups, according as they are (a) necessity-like; (b) contingency-like; (c) absolute, i.e. neither of the above. Default: all items in one group behave similarly. Ibn Sīnā notes that already Aristotle groups possibly and usually with contingency, and permanently with necessity. Some of the rules of inference that he adopts are not valid for his own semantics. Example: the device of putting in place of possibly as premise of an argument by reductio ad absurdum. But he never claims that they are valid. Instead his criteria for adopting inference rules tend to be that they are natural or close to our understanding or that they give certainty. In short, his criteria are cognitive rather than logical. 18 20 2. Unlike Aristotle, Ibn Sīnā prepares for logical study of an expression by explaining its meaning. But he never calculates the soundness of an inference by referring to the semantics. This is deliberate: for him M = and M = ) M = involves the adjunction M = (i.e. truth on quantifier) and hence alters the perceived meaning. The guarantee of ultimate correctness is not a calculation but experience: by applying the rule many times, we get to learn where it is safe and where not. Be aware that most of what the First Teaching contains about mixtures of modalities consists of tests rather than authoritative rulings. The true facts about them will become clear to you when things that have been said about mixtures of modalities are mentioned or used in later topics, so that you can make a ruling on them in the light of what the facts compel. (Qiyās 204.10 12)

21 23 Permanent 6) Necessary Permanent and necessary in Ibn Sīnā Ibn Sīnā, Išārāt Indication iv.4 11 : The permanent is not the necessary. In fact being a writer can be said not to hold of an individual at any time when he exists, let alone at times when he doesn t exist; but this denial is not a necessity proposition. (Here and below, a necessity proposition is a proposition stating that something is necessary, as opposed to a proposition that is necessarily true.) 22 24 Permanent = Necessary Ibn Sīnā, Najā 29.8 9 : The mode necessary signifies holding permanently. (Superscripts refer to the Handout.) Permanent 6( Necessary Ibn Sīnā, Qiyās 32.11 13 7.(14) : And we say Every thing that moves changes, with necessity, not that it permanently never did or will cease [to change],... but while it continues to move.

25 27 With some writers (maybe Al-Fārābī, Russell) we have to learn to accept only local consistency. But Ibn Sīnā insists on having a coherent general picture, so his (many) inconsistencies demand explanations. We will see that Ibn Sīnā himself identifies the problem above, and discusses it in some detail. But first we should review what was available to Ibn Sīnā in the Aristotelian background. From (a) (c) we can infer that Theophrastus mentioned three readings of Every B is an A as a necessary statement: (1) (Permanent reading) Every B is at all times an A. (2) (Subject reading) Every B is an A while the subject hupárkhei. (3) (Predicate reading) Every B is an A while the predicate hupárkhei, i.e. while the B is an A. Ibn Sīnā Qiyās 41.5 6 refers to this as the three-way division (tat līt fil-qisma). We discuss some of Ibn Sīnā s reactions to it. 26 28 Theophrastus (student and successor of Aristotle) wrote a Prior Analytics. In it he proposed three ways of understanding Every B is an A as a necessary/necessity proposition. We know about this from (a) Alexander s commentary on Aristotle Prior Analytics 1,2, (b) a 14th c Hebrew translation by Todros Todrosi of excerpts from an Arabic translation of a commentary by Themistius (4th c) 3, and (c) Ibn Sīnā Qiyās 41.5 13 6. Passages mentioned by Sharples in Liverpool Classical Monthly 3 (1978) 89 91 may also be relevant. A. The predicate reading Ibn Sīnā treats this reading with contempt, for two reasons. First (as he comments in several places) it is not really a reading of Every B is an A at all, since we would never suppress the condition while it is an A. Second, Every B is an A while it is an A is tautologous and not known to play a role in any serious argument.

29 31 B. The subject reading Thanks to several ambiguities, three ways of taking Theophrastus subject reading appear in the literature: (2a) (Essential reading) Every B is an A so long as it ( the B ) exists. (2b) (Descriptional reading) Every B is an A so long as it is a B. (2c) (Nonempty reading) Every B is an A so long as there is a B. Modern readers of Alexander usually translate as (2c). Ibn Rušd, Mas ala i.3 12 : I reckon that... [Ibn Sīnā] thought that what had been said in order to distinguish different forms of absolute reality had been said in order to distinguish different universally quantified necessity propositions.... So I reckon this is how this man fell into error. But Allah knows the truth of it. Apart from Ibn Rušd s usual view that originality equals error, I think he has it exactly right. Ibn Sīnā converted what had been semantics proposed for Every B is an A into a range of new sentence forms. 30 32 C. Ibn Sīnā versus Theophrastus Ibn Sīnā in his discussion of the tat līt opts for the descriptional reading (2b), but elsewhere he frequently discusses the essential reading (2a). The many places where Ibn Sīnā explains the difference between (2a) and (2b) could be evidence that Ibn Sīnā was the first person to distinguish clearly between them. Sharples: It is perhaps questionable whether the early Peripatetics should be supposed to have been entirely clear about the distinctions between these different types of temporal qualification. Several recent writers refer to Ibn Sīnā s waṣfī sentences. In fact Ibn Sīnā had no name for these sentences, apart from a brief attempt in Mašriqiyyūn to call them adherent (lāzim). The name descriptional (waṣfī) was used by later writers, e.g. Tūsī. Ibn Sīnā calls attention to an argument form involving descriptional sentences. We can refer to it as the descriptional syllogism. It s a form of modal Barbara.

33 35 The descriptional syllogism 7 : I Every C is a B so long as it exists. I Every B is an A so long as it is a B. I Therefore C is an A so long as it exists. Given Theophrastus known interest in modal Barbara, and the fact that Ibn Sīnā claims no originality for this argument, my guess is that some confused form of this argument goes back to Theophrastus, though the form above is Ibn Sīnā s. D. Theophrastus or Aristotle? Ibn Sīnā attributes the tat līt not to Theophrastus but to the First Teaching, i.e. Aristotle. Easily explained. First, Alexander in his commentary 2 claims (perhaps correctly) that Theophrastus took at least his predicate reading from Aristotle s De Interpretatione. Second, the Arabs tended to believe (perhaps correctly) that Theophrastus and Eudemus would have discussed their views with Aristotle, so that their writings are indirect evidence for Aristotle s own later views 4. 34 36 Against this, Theophrastus is known to have proposed the peiorem rule: In a valid syllogism the properties of the conclusion match those of the weaker premise. But the descriptional argument violates peiorem. Its conclusion is essential and its major premise is descriptional, although the descriptional reading is clearly weaker than the essential. This point vanishes in face of the evidence that Theophrastus probably didn t distinguish between the essential and the descriptional readings. E. Necessary or absolute? Ibn Sīnā describes the tat līt not as a classification of modal necessity propositions, but as a classification of absolute, i.e. non-modal, propositions. Elsewhere he gives exactly the same propositions as examples of necessity propositions, apparently thinking that the ambiguity goes back to Aristotle. This is not an aberration in Ibn Sīnā. Themistius 3 had also presented the three readings first as readings of necessary/necessity propositions, and then as readings of non-modal propositions.

37 39 Here we come close to our original problem. In fact Ibn Sīnā brings matters to a head by observing that 8.(24) I in Qiyās (his commentary on the Prior Analytics) permanent sentences count as necessity propositions but essential and descriptional sentences count as absolute, I whereas in Burhān (his commentary on the Posterior Analytics), essential and descriptional sentences count as necessity propositions. To introduce his explanation of this discrepancy, we note some distinctions that he makes. Nevertheless he regularly gives sentences with their intended meaning partly suppressed. A frequent example is Everything that moves changes. where a temporal condition is added in the meaning. This is an awful nuisance but clearly deliberate. He believes logicians should follow normal usage. 38 40 G. Modal in act F. Explicit versus intended Ibn Sīnā constantly distinguishes between what we say and what we mean. Normally we mean more than we say. In practice language users are well aware of this. He consistently takes the view that logical inference is between intended meanings in the mind, not between syntactic sentence forms. For Ibn Sīnā a proposition is modal in act (bil-fi c l) 8 if its meaning contains a modal meaning necessarily or possibly. Note that permanent, essential and descriptional propositions are in general not modal in act. But here is a proposition that is modal in act 8.(23) : Some trees grow leaves in the spring. On Ibn Sīnā s reckoning the intended meaning is that these trees have to grow leaves in the spring. (I m not convinced, but it s arguable.)

41 43 Note: This modality is not conveyed by the temporal clause. Proof (my example based on Ibn Sīnā): Compare with Some people sit down when they eat. So in the tree case the intended meaning has to include a mention of modality, and hence the proposition is modal in act. (i) The objection is addressed to you, i.e. Ibn Sīnā. In fact although Ibn Sīnā can trace the original ambiguity to Aristotle, he defends his own treatment of it without any reference to Aristotle. (ii) The problem is hard to describe (as opposed to hard to solve ). This seems to rule out some obvious explanations. It rules out that the propositions described as absolute are not the same as those described as necessity propositions. It rules out that the problem rests on an ambiguity in the word necessary or the word absolute. 42 44 Now consider Ibn Sīnā Burhān 123.14 16 8.(26) : Someone might say: In the book Qiyās, when you considered those propositions which are necessary in the sense that [the predicate holds] so long as the subject [individual] continues to fit the [subject] description, you took them to be absolute propositions. In that book there were universally quantified propositions that are [called] absolute although their universality is not qualified by any gap in the time at which they apply. A page later (Burhān 124.16): This leaves Ibn Sīnā with very little wriggle room. Ibn Sīnā s solution is difficult to decipher, and not one that can be straightforwardly read off. We have to conjecture what he might have been aiming at, and then check whether his text fits our conjecture. Under these circumstances any explanation of his solution has to be provisional. But here is one. So this hard-to-describe ( c awīs) problem has been solved.

45 47 H. Modal in possibility ( imkān) A proposition is modal in possibility if it could (though in general need not) have a modal condition added without changing the meaning 8. From a modern point of view, this is as if the proposition was factual, and the added modal condition represented an evaluation that doesn t change the facts. If this is correct, then the distinction between absolute and necessary in Ibn Sīnā is, at least sometimes, not a distinction between different kinds of proposition. It is closer to a distinction between ground-level and more subtle aspects of the same propositions. When we add necessarily to a non-modal statement, we need not in general be changing the factual content or truth conditions. Rather, we may be labelling the statement as suitable for giving scientific knowledge and certainty. This accounts for the change of terminology in Burhān, which is about epistemology and scientific method. 46 48 Note for example Ibn Sīnā s closing comment at Burhān 124.13 15 8 : Such premises do occur in Burhān with the modality of necessity suppressed [in the expression] but present in the mind. They really are absolute when the modality of necessity is suppressed [in the expression] and not present in the mind either, and the proposition is regarded as purely factual (nuẓira ilā l-wujūd faqaṭ). Such views don t appear in Najā (written a dozen years before Qiyās, published later). Instead Najā treats necessity and permanence as parallel concepts. The main difference between them is that propositions about individual objects can be permanent without being necessary. This can t happen with truly universal propositions 10. This view is repeated by Ibn Rušd 12 and by Tūsī (commentary on Išārāt).

49 51 The Najā view, though interesting, doesn t come near explaining the complex relations between permanence and necessity in the Šifā. For example the propositions that express necessity but not permanence. Maybe it represents an earlier layer of Ibn Sīnā s thinking. If so, what effect would the development of the Šifā view have had on his modal logic? Instead he presents the categorical syllogisms, and as he describes each figure he examines the effect of adding conditions of various kinds, modal or other. (murā c ātu l-šurūṭ, already a leading theme in Šifā.) Like much of Išārāt, the treatment is sketchy. It would be extremely interesting to know how Ibn Sīnā himself would have expanded it if he had had the time and the inclination. 50 It s plausible that the logical relations between propositions depend mainly on their truth conditions, and less on their evaluative content. If Ibn Sīnā took that view, we would expect it to lead him in later work to downplay the role of modalities in logical rules. But this is exactly what we find in the late Išārāt, where Ibn Sīnā abandons Aristotle s scheme of treating modal rules separately.