Critical Thinking, Reasoning, and Argument

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Critical Thinking, Reasoning, and Argument"

Transcription

1 Critical Thinking, Reasoning, and Argument Critical thinking is used in many contexts and has different connotations. Often it is applied to contexts such as interpreting texts, evaluating artistic expression, and so on. For our purposes, however, we will characterize critical thinking as openly and explicitly deliberating whether to accept or reject claims or beliefs. Critical thinking often involves reasoning. Reasoning or rationality implies that we accept or reject beliefs objectively. In other words, the reasons that persuaded us to accept or reject some belief would be equally persuasive to other individuals. In this respect, rationality implies intersubjectivity. Reasoning, therefore, is a process that should transcend prejudices, narrow self- interest, and sheer emotional motivations. Often, our reasoning is directed at matters of fact these are beliefs about what obtains in the world. For example, whether unicorns exist or not is a factual matter. But, critical thinking and reasoning can also consider matters of value. These are typically questions of what is good, evil, right or wrong. For instance, whether deceiving someone is ever morally right or justified is a question that at least in part depends on values. In either case, though, decisions about these beliefs can be critically examined and reasoned about. Specimens or expressions of reasoning are called arguments. Arguments are comprised by evidence and claims. Both claims and evidence are represented by statements. A statement is a sentence that expresses what is either true or false. In grammar, statements are called declarative sentences. The claim or conclusion is the point of the argument; it expresses what we are asked to accept as true. The evidence is what is offered to persuade us to accept the truth of the claim. Rational arguments are those whose evidence supports the claim by means of some generally accepted form of reasoning. These are sometimes called logical arguments. Arguments are normally spoken or written. In normal discourse, arguments may be expressed in spoken or written passages that contain a variety of other sentences whose function is to advance the narrative. Interrogatory sentences ( Are you a real American?), exclamatory sentences ( You must believe me! ), and others do not actually express statements. Consequently, strictly speaking, they are not considered parts of an argument. In addition to what is stated, sometimes elements of an argument may be implied by what is said but not strictly expressed. Consequently, it is permitted and often useful to rephrase or reconstruct arguments in order to identify the evidence and claim more precisely. For example, someone might utter the following. When I woke up this morning, I thought that it must have rained last night because the streets were wet. Here we have a simple argument that might be analyzed in the following manner. (E) the streets are wet this morning (E) when it rains, the streets get wet (C) it rained last night The second piece of evidence, of course, is implicit but normally understood in a commonsense context. It is needed in order to express the connection between rain and wetness. Although we should, we don t always express every detail in our arguments. - 1-

2 Arguments or inferences that have missing or implied pieces are sometimes called enthymenes. Notice, though, that the evidence is not conclusive. It is possible that it did not rain; instead a street cleaner might have doused the streets early in the morning. Even so, it is a plausible claim. As we shall see, evaluating how well the evidence supports the claim depends more on the kind of reasoning employed than the subject matter of the argument. For convenience, we will reconstruct arguments by simply listing the evidence sometimes called premisses 1 and indicating the conclusion afterwards and below a line. The triple dot signifies the conclusion and is usually read as therefore. So, the previous example would be rewritten the streets are wet this morning when it rains, the streets get wet it rained last night Some specimens of argument are not rational arguments at all. These usually express what is called informal fallacies. (You can find out more about them in a special section.) Logical Reasoning We learn about things in the world either by direct experience or by inference. Direct experience is the immediate observation provided by the senses (seeing, hearing, touching, etc.). For example, if someone says that his/her automobile is red, we can inspect it to see what color it is. This is knowledge (or learning) by direct experience. On the other hand, inference involves deriving some statement from the evidence at hand. Inferences are so common that we are unaware of how often we depend upon them in normal circumstances. For instance, if we walk up to the front door of a friend s home and hear voices within, it would be normal to believe that someone is home. Of course, the sound of voices could be from the television left on when the occupants departed. Thus, we have inferred that the sound of voices implies that people are inside. Logical reasoning is a formalized way of making and analyzing inferences. Specifically, a logic is a system that explains how claims can be correctly derived from evidence or sets of premisses. In short, there are potentially many different logics that is, different systems that formalize inferential reasoning. Intuitively, we evaluate any logic using a principle called the Criterion of Adequacy (CoA). Basically, it states in any argument, as the evidence increases, the extent to which the collected (true) evidence supports or warrants the conclusion as measured by the logic should also increase. Moreover, it should better discriminate related false claims as false and true claims as true. 2 In other words, a logic that satisfies its CoA will provide us with a method by which we can determine whether an argument is good or bad, i.e., whether the evidence supports the claim. Furthermore, it should help us decide the truth- value of related claims. Imagine an argument of the form, p q - 2-

3 A logic that satisfies its CoA would tell us how well the evidence p supports the claim q. If that support is sufficient, then we should expect that q is true and that not- q (or it is not the case that q ) is false at least to the extent to which that CoA warrants. As we shall see, not all logical inferences carry the weight of absolute certitude, though some do. Perhaps surprisingly, not all forms of reasoning have been formalized logically. Logicians have identified at least major three types of reasoning: deductive, inductive, and abductive reasoning. Each of these classifications intends to specify a particular style of reasoning or inference. We will adapt an example conceived by American philosopher and logician, Charles Sanders Pierce (pronounced purse ) to illustrate. 3 Imagine that you enter a room where you find a table. On the table, there is a bag that contains solid- colored marbles. You examine all of the marbles in the bag. In this context, a deductive inference on the facts would be all the marbles in this bag are white this is a marble from this bag this marble is white Suppose instead of inspecting them in advance, you draw one marble at a time from the bag. An inductive inference might take this form, I have examined at least two- thirds of the marbles in this bag each of the observed marbles was white I expect that the next marble that I pick out of the bag will be white Finally, an abductive inference would be fashioned along these lines. Suppose that there were several other bags of marbles on the table. You examined each and found that they contained marbles that were not colored white. If we saw some white marbles on the table, we would then infer there is only one bag on the table containing only white marbles there are several white marbles on the table these white marbles must have come from that bag As you can see, these instances represent very different styles of inference. Deductive inferences are conclusive. We can decide up or down without any recourse to additional information. You don t have to step foot inside the room to know whether this inference is good or bad. On the other hand, inductive and abductive inferences are not conclusive in the same manner. We do have to consider other factors in assessing their merit. This is not to say that deductive inferences are better than the other two varieties: only that they are different. Let s examine these styles of reasoning more closely. Deductive Reasoning and Arguments Deductive arguments are those that are conclusively provable. Deductive reasoning has been thoroughly studied and formalized. Deductive arguments are classified as valid or invalid. Informally, a valid deductive argument exhibits the strongest logical connection between the evidence and conclusion. Specifically, a (deductively) valid argument is one for which it is logically impossible for the premisses (evidence) to be true and the conclusion false. Note that the reference here is logically impossible. This means that affirming the evidence and denying the truth of the conclusion leads to an inconsistency or logical contradiction. Very strong indeed. - 3-

4 Consider this syllogistic chestnut as an example of a deductively valid argument. All men are mortal Socrates is a man Socrates is mortal The point is that if the premisses are true, then the conclusion must also be true. For instance, if we denied that Socrates was mortal after all, then the general statement that All men are mortal would now be false. But, it can t be both true and false at the same time. This would be a logical contradiction. So, if the premisses are indeed true, then the conclusion must also be true. There is an important distinction to be made however. The argument s validity doesn t guarantee the truth of the conclusion per se. In other words, it is possible for the conclusion to be false but only when the evidence fails likewise. For example, if the historical figure Socrates never existed, then Socrates is a man would be false. As a result, the conclusion would likewise be false. In spite of this, the argument would still be valid. In short, deductive validity expresses a technical or formal property of the argument. In fact, we could standardize the structure of this argument in the following manner. All M are P (All) S are M (All) S are P S, M, and P are properties that designate class membership (for example, being human, being mortal, and being Socrates ). But, these variables may also signify other properties as well. Thus, there is an indefinite number of potential arguments that could be derived from this form. All of them would be deductively valid. Arguments that lack the formal property of deductive validity are, of course, deductively invalid: it is logically possible for the premisses to be true and the conclusion false. Our initial example works here. the streets are wet this morning. when it rains, the streets get wet. it rained last night. We can accept that both premisses are true, but still maintain that the conclusion is false. (Remember the street cleaner explanation.) The connection between the evidence and the conclusion is simply not strong enough to satisfy the deductive CoA. Invalid arguments oddly enough could have true conclusions after all. The bottom line, though, is that the evidence has little or nothing to do with warranting our belief in the conclusion. Deductively invalid arguments with true conclusions are no more than lucky guesses. We would hope that our deductively valid arguments have warranted (true) evidence. These are called sound arguments. On the other hand, arguments that have evidence containing false statements are unsound. Deductive reasoning plays a significant but only a small role in most of the inferences that we make in normal circumstances. In practical contexts, our inferences usually lack the certainty or completeness required for deductive validity. Even so, other forms of reasoning can be rationally compelling. Inferences of this sort are usually categorized as defeasible reasoning. 4-4-

5 Technically, deductively valid inferences or arguments are classified as monotonic reasoning. Specifically, if the conclusion can be inferred from a given set of premisses, then adding additional evidence has no effect on its validity. For example, consider this new version of the previous syllogistic example. All men are mortal Socrates is a man Socrates is married to Xanthippe Socrates is mortal Even though the new premiss is true, it has no real impact on the validity of the argument. An argument doesn t become more valid or less valid; it is valid or invalid pure and simply. In short, deductively valid inferences satisfy logical entailment. To put it another way, the knowledge expressed by the conclusion is contained within the premisses. There is no need to consult any other information. But there are many other contexts in which adding new information can change our opinion about the truth of some claim. For example, it is usually reasonable to seek a second opinion on medical diagnoses especially when the consequences are significant. In these instances, corroborating evidence adds weight to the original diagnosis. On the other hand, contradictory evidence would likely diminish its warrant. Thus, defeasible reasoning signifies rational inferences that have warrant but fail the standards of deductive validity. Formal systems that seek to capture this style of reasoning are usually called non- monotonic logics. There are a variety of types of inferences that fit this general category. Inductive inference is a style of defeasible reasoning that has been studied almost as long as deductive forms. Inductive Reasoning and Arguments Inductive reasoning generally involves inferring from the observed to the unobserved. This might mean reasoning from past to the present or future or from the seen to the unseen. This form of reasoning is typically measured probabilistically. In other words, the claims or conclusions are considered likely or less likely true, because the evidence confers some amount of probability for the truth of the conclusion. The most common type of inductive inference is an enumeration of cases. Here are a couple of examples. Each day that I can remember, the sun rose in the morning. I expect that the sun will rise tomorrow morning. In a random sample of 500 voters from our county (composed of 140,000 voters), 60% said that they would vote for a Republican candidate over a Democratic candidate in the next presidential election. This supports the conclusion (with a probability of 0.9) that between 55 and 65% of the county s voters would vote Republican if the next presidential election were held today. The first example seems less formal, but both specify a set of evidential cases that are intended to support the claim or conclusion. In the first instance, we are reasoning from observed cases to the next (unobserved) case; the second argument generalizes from a sample to the population. The second specifies a probability and a margin of error, but we could rephrase the first to make it look similar. For example, the probability might be

6 and no margin of error. The point is that in inductive inferences, the truth of the claim is contingent on the truth of the evidence. It is (logically) possible for the conclusion to be false based on that evidence, but we would be surprised if it were. Inductive arguments are classified in a continuum from strong to weak. An inductively strong argument is one in which the truth of the evidence confers a high degree of probability that the conclusion is likewise true. Inductively weak arguments fail to confer an acceptable degree of probability. Consider the following. I bought two lottery tickets from that vendor and lost each time. The next ticket I buy from that vendor will be another losing ticket. This is a weak inference in spite of the fact based on other considerations the claim might very well be true. Reasoning from two cases is simply too few to warrant such a conclusion. But how many tickets would I have to buy to strengthen the argument: 10, 20, 100, or 1000? The last two seem stronger. However, it is difficult to draw a precise line. Keep in mind that in the last example, our goal is to evaluate the argument and not just the truth- value of the conclusion. The odds on winning a national lottery are very long, so it is very unlikely that a single ticket from any vendor will be the winner. But, this is knowledge not expressed in the argument per se. In this instance, all that we have to go on is two enumerated cases. Unfortunately, there is disagreement among experts who seek to formalize inductive inferences by devising a system of inductive logic. (In other words, the CoA for evaluating inductive inferences is not well defined.) The majority view is that these types of inferences can be explained by means of probability theory (specifically Bayesian conditional probability). The details are highly technical and not intuitive. But, this is an instance when our theories cannot fully explain our practice. We do, after all, use and depend upon inductive inferences everyday. For example, I make an inductive leap of faith every time I choose to eat or drink something. How do I know that it will not poison me? In general, if I ingest the kinds of things that I have eaten before, then I should be safe. Thus, every day we stake our lives on the warrant of inductive inferences even though we lack a complete understanding of how to evaluate them precisely. Abductive Reasoning and Arguments Abductive reasoning is the kind of inference typically used in law, forensics, and scientific theories. We often employ this style of reasoning in ordinary contexts as well. For example, suppose that you are driving and notice that the gas gauge reads Empty. Being a reasonable person, you would plan to stop and buy some gasoline for your automobile. But, this is an inference. What made you decide so? We might reconstruct the argument in this manner. (1) The gas gauge reads Empty. I have no reason to determine that it is malfunctioning. It has been several days since I last put gasoline in the tank. I have good reason to believe that the gas tank is (near) empty. In this instance, the conclusion is inferred because it makes sense out of a collection of facts. In other words, if the conclusion were true, then the evidence would be understandable as a matter of course. If the gas tank were empty then the gas gauge reading would be predictable. Likewise, the fact that I haven t put any gasoline in the tank - 6-

7 for several days would be consistent with this explanation as well. Furthermore, the claim is more plausible than alternative explanations such as someone secretly filled my gas tank and doctored my gas gauge to read empty. It is also more plausible than I have a faulty gas gauge but plenty of gasoline, because it is a new secret formula gasoline that yields greatly increased mileage. Clearly, these stretch credulity much more than our initial explanation. Thus, the claim seems more warranted as an inference. Abductive arguments contain conclusions that are offered as the best hypothesis or explanation for a set of related facts or details. Here are a couple of other examples. (2) The victim lives alone. The victim arrived at home around 10:00 P.M. There are no signs of forced entry through the doors or windows of the house. It was raining last night around 10:00 P.M., but the only signs of muddy footprints were those matching the victim s shoes. The murderer had ready access to and was already in the house before the victim came home. (3) Fossils that look very much like the remains of modern fishes have been found in this land area. This land area is far inland from any large bodies of water. This land must have been covered by water when the animals that produced these fossils lived. Arguments (2) and (3) differ from the first example in one important respect. Argument (1) has some superficial resemblance to an inductive inference. We could rephrase it to read something like this. (1a) The gas gauge reads Empty. In the past, each time the gas gauge read Empty, the gas tank was (near) empty. I have good reason to believe that the gas tank is (near) empty this time. Thus, we could be reasoning from a sequence of past experiences that correlate these events. Arguments (2) and (3) resist this kind of inductive translation. It is very unlikely that they imply a past experience with either similar murders or fossils. Once more, these demonstrate the explanatory character of abductive reasoning. For instance, in (3) we are presented with an anomaly: literally, fish out of water. The conclusion fills in our gaps of understanding precisely by challenging appearances. The inland area was likely not always inland. The argument (2) represents a common type of reasoning in forensic science as applied in criminal investigations and legal proceedings. (Apologies to Sherlock Holmes.) Both offer a theory to explain the facts at hand. In this respect, abductive reasoning is prevalent in the sciences. While scientific research may employ both deductive and inductive reasoning, theories are explanations that try to interpret a collection of facts or observations in the most plausible way. Theories, of course, are confirmed or disconfirmed. Most theories have predictive power. In other words, a reliable theory is one that can be used to predict additional facts or states- of- affairs are consistent with the theory. For example, in (3), if there was an inland sea on the spot where the fossils are found, then there should be other signs that are typically associated with larger bodies of water. Suppose that we also find sizable areas of - 7-

8 sandstone rock formations. This is consistent with the hypothesis and helps to confirm it. On the other hand, if we found no such evidence, and in fact geologic formations inconsistent with the presence of an ancient sea, then these observations would disconfirm the theory. As you can see, abductive inferences belong to the category of defeasible reasoning discussed earlier. The merit of an abductive inference can change with the inclusion of additional evidence for better or worse. While abductive reasoning has been studied by some logicians, currently there is no accepted formal system for analyzing types and measuring the reliability of its inferences. Defeasible Reasoning, Again In recent years, logicians (and researchers in Artificial Intelligence) have isolated a very specific form of inference under the label of defeasible reasoning. Defeasible reasoning (in this new, narrower use) supports claims or conclusions only contingently. The argument offers the best evidence available, but future considerations may reverse our acceptance of the conclusion. The standard example of a defeasible argument is Tweety is a bird. Birds fly. Tweety flies. It is defeasible in the sense that if we later find out that Tweety is a penguin, then we would no longer accept the truth of the conclusion based on the evidence. Cast in these terms, defeasible inferences are perhaps better thought as presumptive inferences. Presumptive reasoning amounts to accepting some claim until better evidence comes along that would either corroborate or disconfirm it. The Tweety argument fits squarely into this category. Presumptive reasoning is very different from abductive, for example. Inferring the claim Tweety flies does not somehow make better sense of the premisses. Instead, the argument appears to be more like a faulty (unsound) deductive argument: (All) birds fly. Tweety is a bird. Tweety flies. The problem, of course, is that the generalization about birds flying is faulty. Penguins, ostriches, etc. are technically birds but do not fly. Presumptive arguments amounts to concluding that Given what we know, it is more reasonable to accept claim C than deny it. In other words, the argument rests on the truth of the evidence offered, but it is possible that, in the future, these assumptions may not be adequate. The rational person accepts presumptive reasoning because to do otherwise seems irrational, i.e., believing and acting without any good evidence at all! The point, here, is that there are many different kinds of defeasible reasoning, and presumptive reasoning is one of them. Inductive and abductive reasoning are two other varieties. As arguments or inferences, they share the fact that adding evidence can affect their adequacy. But, they differ in how that adequacy is measured. Whether there are other legitimate forms of reasoning is still an open question. From a practical standpoint, however, it much more difficult proving that something is impossible - 8-

9 than otherwise. So, smart money would go with the hunch that there may be other legitimate forms. Using and Assessing Arguments When you engage in debates or read or write position papers, it is important to consider the types of arguments or inferences offered. A position paper, for example, should have a clearly expressed claim or conclusion. The paper, however, may offer several arguments in favor of the claim rather than just one. Each of the arguments should be assessed on its own merits. But the moral from the foregoing is a simple one: When evaluating arguments, first, you should identify what type of reasoning is being expressed. Assessing the merit of the argument depends not only on the evidence offered but also the style of reasoning employed. For instance, it may be correct that an argument in a position paper is deductively invalid. But this observation is irrelevant if it was intended as an inductive or perhaps abductive inference instead. In debates and position papers, sometimes evaluating the argument is made more difficult because the reasoning involves either enthymenes and/or argument chains. We saw earlier that enthymenes are arguments with missing but implied elements. An argument chain is an argument whose conclusion is based on a series of connected inferences. In other words, some of the evidence for the claim rests on inferences derived from other evidence. Here is an example. (4) If Candidate X wins the New Hampshire primary, then he/she will likely have an advantage in raising more campaign funds than the opponents. This means that Candidate X would likely win the nomination and be elected in November. Let s restate the argument as a series of conditionals. (4a) If Candidate X wins the New Hampshire primary, then he/she will likely have an advantage in raising additional campaign funds. (4b) If Candidate X raises more campaign funds than the opponents, then he/she will likely secure the party s nomination. (4c) If Candidate X secures the party s nomination, then he/she will likely be elected president. Each of these conditionals expresses an inference. In this instance, most are also enthymenes, that is, having implied premisses. Together, they constitute a series of related inferences that lead to a final conclusion. We could challenge any or all of these inferences. But the credibility of the claim rests on the merit of all of the inferences. If one fails, then the argument chain fails. In some instances, even in editorials written by professionals, there are lots of claims being offered. But when we look for evidence, we may find very little offered. Writings like these may be very formal, but they amount to nothing more than a succession of pronouncements. The fact that something is published carries no extra authority. If the claim is a reasonable one, then there should be some evidence to warrant it. Finally, keep in mind that assessing arguments often depends on some interpretation. Specifically, it is possible that we may disagree about how to express someone s line of reasoning in argument form. The evidence and even the claim might be interpreted - 9-

10 differently. In these instances, there can be little or no basis for a common evaluation. Like apples and oranges, we are talking about two different things. This provides another practical reason for reconstructing the arguments from their original expression. It is much easier to agree or disagree about the merit of an argument, if we can agree that we are talking about the same thing. Exercises I. Each of the passages below express reasoning. Reconstruct the argument in conventional form by supplying any missing but implied elements. Likewise, identify any argument chains where a premiss for some claim is based on other evidence expressed or implied. 1. Reconstruct the argument chain expressed in specimen (4) above. Specifically, decide on any missing or implied premisses. 2. There is no thunderstorm nearby because we haven t heard any thunder recently. 3. Since Audrey graduated from medical school, her personal income is most likely very high. 4. You should have come to the party. You did promise me that you would. 5. This week I am going all out for the lottery! The law of averages guarantees that I can t keep losing forever. II. Each of the passages below express an argument, that is, each offers evidence for some main claim. Reconstruct the argument in conventional form, identify the type of inference employed, and evaluate its merit. 1. If Mary hit a home run during yesterday s game, her sister would have congratulated her. But her sister did not congratulate Mary. So, Mary did not hit a home run during yesterday s game. 2. Frank is another one of the socialists and liberals who live in our town. All the socialists and liberals in town are at the meeting featuring a speaker who supports universal healthcare. Naturally, Frank is attending the meeting. 3. Your job as a juror is to determine whether the defendant who confessed to fatally stabbing the victim is guilty of first- degree murder or manslaughter. The issue before us is whether the knife blow was of moderate or strong force. The coroner has testified that the knife penetrated only 2 ½ inches and there were no knife marks on the bones of the victim. 4. There are those who say that we should not regulate pornography or any conduct of consenting adults. This is absurd. Like all civilized societies, we have long had rules that attempt to set moral standards and regulate sexual conduct. Regulating pornography is no different. It is no coincidence that societies have decayed and collapsed (viz. the Roman Empire) when moral standards have declined. (based on Alexander Bickel in Pornography, Censorship and Common Sense. ) 5. The materials of nature (the air, earth, water) that remain untouched by human effort belong to no one and not property. It follows that a thing can become someone s private property only if he or she works and labors on it thereby changing its natural state. From this I can conclude that whatever an individual improves by the labor of his hand belongs to him, and to him only

11 (based on John Locke, Of Property. ) 6. No man will take counsel; but every man will take money; therefore money is better than counsel. (Jonathan Swift) 1 Not to be confused with premises, which denotes a location, premiss is used in logic and law. The Oxford English Dictionary defines it as a statement or proposition from which another is inferred or follows as a conclusion. "premise, n.". OED Online. June Oxford University Press. (accessed July 12, 2011). 2 James Hawthorn, Inductive Logic, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, (2011). inductive/ (accessed July 18, 2011). 3 Charles Sanders Pierce Deduction, Induction, and Hypothesis, Popular Science Monthly Volume 13 (1878), pp Robert Koons, Defeasible Reasoning, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (2009). defeasible/ (accessed July 18, 2011)

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 1 A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 5 A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 1.1 Arguments Arguments crop up in conversations, political debates, lectures, editorials, comic strips, novels, television programs,

More information

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference 1 2 3 4 5 6 Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference of opinion. Often heated. A statement of

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics Critical Thinking Lecture 1 Background Material for the Exercise on Validity Reasons, Arguments, and the Concept of Validity 1. The Concept of Validity Consider

More information

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Ștefan Ciobâcă November 30, 2017 1 Propositions A proposition is a statement that can be true or false. Propositions are sometimes called

More information

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens. INTRODUCTION TO LOGICAL THINKING Lecture 6: Two types of argument and their role in science: Deduction and induction 1. Deductive arguments Arguments that claim to provide logically conclusive grounds

More information

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument

CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument CHAPTER THREE Philosophical Argument General Overview: As our students often attest, we all live in a complex world filled with demanding issues and bewildering challenges. In order to determine those

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary pm Krabbe Dale Jacquette Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test

Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test Appendix: The Logic Behind the Inferential Test In the Introduction, I stated that the basic underlying problem with forensic doctors is so easy to understand that even a twelve-year-old could understand

More information

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Standardizing and Diagramming In Reason and the Balance we have taken the approach of using a simple outline to standardize short arguments,

More information

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion.

Academic argument does not mean conflict or competition; an argument is a set of reasons which support, or lead to, a conclusion. ACADEMIC SKILLS THINKING CRITICALLY In the everyday sense of the word, critical has negative connotations. But at University, Critical Thinking is a positive process of understanding different points of

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7

Portfolio Project. Phil 251A Logic Fall Due: Friday, December 7 Portfolio Project Phil 251A Logic Fall 2012 Due: Friday, December 7 1 Overview The portfolio is a semester-long project that should display your logical prowess applied to real-world arguments. The arguments

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Logical (formal) fallacies

Logical (formal) fallacies Fallacies in academic writing Chad Nilep There are many possible sources of fallacy an idea that is mistakenly thought to be true, even though it may be untrue in academic writing. The phrase logical fallacy

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS

A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS A BRIEF INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC FOR METAPHYSICIANS 0. Logic, Probability, and Formal Structure Logic is often divided into two distinct areas, inductive logic and deductive logic. Inductive logic is concerned

More information

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC FOR PRIVATE REGISTRATION TO BA PHILOSOPHY PROGRAMME 1. Logic is the science of-----------. A) Thought B) Beauty C) Mind D) Goodness 2. Aesthetics is the science of ------------.

More information

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments REMEMBER as explained in an earlier section formal language is used for expressing relations in abstract form, based on clear and unambiguous

More information

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism Unit 8 Categorical yllogism What is a syllogism? Inference or reasoning is the process of passing from one or more propositions to another with some justification. This inference when expressed in language

More information

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Introduction Symbolic Logic An Introduction to Symbolic Logic Copyright 2006 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved CONTENTS Chapter One Sentential Logic with 'if' and 'not' 1 SYMBOLIC NOTATION 2 MEANINGS OF THE SYMBOLIC NOTATION

More information

A Note on Straight-Thinking

A Note on Straight-Thinking A Note on Straight-Thinking A supplementary note for the 2nd Annual JTS/CGST Public Ethics Lecture March 5, 2002(b), adj. 2009:03:05 G.E.M. of TKI Arguments & Appeals In arguments, people try to persuade

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning

Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning Foundations of Non-Monotonic Reasoning Notation S A - from a set of premisses S we can derive a conclusion A. Example S: All men are mortal Socrates is a man. A: Socrates is mortal. x.man(x) mortal(x)

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims). TOPIC: You need to be able to: Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims). Organize arguments that we read into a proper argument

More information

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood GILBERT HARMAN PRINCETON UNIVERSITY When can we detach probability qualifications from our inductive conclusions? The following rule may seem plausible:

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy Scientific Method and Research Ethics 17.09 Questions, Answers, and Evidence Dr. C. D. McCoy Plan for Part 1: Deduction 1. Logic, Arguments, and Inference 1. Questions and Answers 2. Truth, Validity, and

More information

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments M01_COPI1396_13_SE_C01.QXD 10/10/07 9:48 PM Page 26 26 CHAPTER 1 Basic Logical Concepts 19. All ethnic movements are two-edged swords. Beginning benignly, and sometimes necessary to repair injured collective

More information

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT What does it mean to provide an argument for a statement? To provide an argument for a statement is an activity we carry out both in our everyday lives and within the sciences. We provide arguments for

More information

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE CHAPTER VI CONDITIONS OF IMMEDIATE INFERENCE Section 1. The word Inference is used in two different senses, which are often confused but should be carefully distinguished. In the first sense, it means

More information

1.2. What is said: propositions

1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2.0. Overview In 1.1.5, we saw the close relation between two properties of a deductive inference: (i) it is a transition from premises to conclusion that is free of any

More information

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1 DOUBTS ABOUT UNCERTAINTY WITHOUT ALL THE DOUBT NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH Norby s paper is divided into three main sections in which he introduces the storage hypothesis, gives reasons for rejecting it and then

More information

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. Reply to Southwood, Kearns and Star, and Cullity Author(s): by John Broome Source: Ethics, Vol. 119, No. 1 (October 2008), pp. 96-108 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/592584.

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS

CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS Fall 2001 ENGLISH 20 Professor Tanaka CRITICAL THINKING (CT) MODEL PART 1 GENERAL CONCEPTS In this first handout, I would like to simply give you the basic outlines of our critical thinking model

More information

Criticizing Arguments

Criticizing Arguments Kareem Khalifa Criticizing Arguments 1 Criticizing Arguments Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College Written August, 2012 Table of Contents Introduction... 1 Step 1: Initial Evaluation

More information

Three Kinds of Arguments

Three Kinds of Arguments Chapter 27 Three Kinds of Arguments Arguments in general We ve been focusing on Moleculan-analyzable arguments for several chapters, but now we want to take a step back and look at the big picture, at

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning

Module 9- Inductive and Deductive Reasoning Inductive and Deductive Reasoning Inquire: Types of Argumentative Reasoning Overview Sometimes, when we write an essay, we re setting out to write a really compelling and convincing argument. As we begin

More information

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Session 3 September 9 th, 2015 All About Arguments (Part II) 1 A common theme linking many fallacies is that they make unwarranted assumptions. An assumption is a claim

More information

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction... The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction... 2 2.0 Defining induction... 2 3.0 Induction versus deduction... 2 4.0 Hume's descriptive

More information

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE

THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE THE LARGER LOGICAL PICTURE 1. ILLOCUTIONARY ACTS In this paper, I am concerned to articulate a conceptual framework which accommodates speech acts, or language acts, as well as logical theories. I will

More information

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N

A R G U M E N T S I N A C T I O N ARGUMENTS IN ACTION Descriptions: creates a textual/verbal account of what something is, was, or could be (shape, size, colour, etc.) Used to give you or your audience a mental picture of the world around

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 Lesson Seventeen The Conditional Syllogism Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by means of the aforesaid figures; these considerations

More information

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS

VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS Michael Lacewing The project of logical positivism VERIFICATION AND METAPHYSICS In the 1930s, a school of philosophy arose called logical positivism. Like much philosophy, it was concerned with the foundations

More information

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 07 07 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 07 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010

Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements. Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010 Elements of Science (cont.); Conditional Statements Phil 12: Logic and Decision Making Fall 2010 UC San Diego 9/29/2010 1 Why cover statements and arguments Decision making (whether in science or elsewhere)

More information

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism

Chapter 1. Introduction. 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning Strong Syllogism Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Deductive and Plausible Reasoning................... 3 1.1.1 Strong Syllogism......................... 3 1.1.2 Weak Syllogism.......................... 4 1.1.3 Transitivity

More information

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1 BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1. What is Logic?... 2 2. Inferences and Arguments... 2 3. Deductive Logic versus Inductive Logic... 5 4. Statements versus Propositions... 6 5. Form versus Content... 7 6. Preliminary

More information

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of Logic: Inductive Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises and a conclusion. The quality of an argument depends on at least two factors: the truth of the

More information

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals

Argument and Persuasion. Stating Opinions and Proposals Argument and Persuasion Stating Opinions and Proposals The Method It all starts with an opinion - something that people can agree or disagree with. The Method Move to action Speak your mind Convince someone

More information

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic

On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic On Priest on nonmonotonic and inductive logic Greg Restall School of Historical and Philosophical Studies The University of Melbourne Parkville, 3010, Australia restall@unimelb.edu.au http://consequently.org/

More information

Logical behaviourism

Logical behaviourism Michael Lacewing Logical behaviourism THE THEORY Logical behaviourism is a form of physicalism, but it does not attempt to reduce mental properties states, events and so on to physical properties directly.

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All?

IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All? IDHEF Chapter 2 Why Should Anyone Believe Anything At All? -You might have heard someone say, It doesn t really matter what you believe, as long as you believe something. While many people think this is

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000)

Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) Helpful Hints for doing Philosophy Papers (Spring 2000) (1) The standard sort of philosophy paper is what is called an explicative/critical paper. It consists of four parts: (i) an introduction (usually

More information

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1. What is Logic?...2 2. Inferences and Arguments...2 3. Deductive Logic versus Inductive Logic...5 4. Statements versus Propositions...6 5. Form versus Content...7 6. Preliminary

More information

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1 The Appeal to Reason Introductory Logic pt. 1 Argument vs. Argumentation The difference is important as demonstrated by these famous philosophers. The Origins of Logic: (highlights) Aristotle (385-322

More information

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic

The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic The Problem of Major Premise in Buddhist Logic TANG Mingjun The Institute of Philosophy Shanghai Academy of Social Sciences Shanghai, P.R. China Abstract: This paper is a preliminary inquiry into the main

More information

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1, Logic: inductive Penultimate version: please cite the entry to appear in: J. Lachs & R. Talisse (eds.), Encyclopedia of American Philosophy. New York: Routledge. Draft: April 29, 2006 Logic is the study

More information

Logic. A Primer with Addendum

Logic. A Primer with Addendum Logic A Primer with Addendum The Currency of Philosophy Philosophy trades in arguments. An argument is a set of propositions some one of which is intended to be warranted or entailed by the others. The

More information

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments

ARGUMENTS. Arguments. arguments ARGUMENTS Arguments arguments 1 Argument Worksheet 1. An argument is a collection of propositions with one proposition, the conclusion, following from the other propositions, the premises. Inference is

More information

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary In her Testimony and Epistemic Risk: The Dependence Account, Karyn Freedman defends an interest-relative account of justified belief

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 06 06 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 06 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

National Quali cations

National Quali cations H SPECIMEN S85/76/ National Qualications ONLY Philosophy Paper Date Not applicable Duration hour 5 minutes Total marks 50 SECTION ARGUMENTS IN ACTION 30 marks Attempt ALL questions. SECTION KNOWLEDGE AND

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE Section 1. A Mediate Inference is a proposition that depends for proof upon two or more other propositions, so connected together by one or

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe. Overview Philosophy & logic 1.2 What is philosophy? 1.3 nature of philosophy Why philosophy Rules of engagement Punctuality and regularity is of the essence You should be active in class It is good to

More information

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. On Interpretation By Aristotle Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 'denial' and 'affirmation',

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

WHAT IS HUME S FORK? Certainty does not exist in science.

WHAT IS HUME S FORK?  Certainty does not exist in science. WHAT IS HUME S FORK? www.prshockley.org Certainty does not exist in science. I. Introduction: A. Hume divides all objects of human reason into two different kinds: Relation of Ideas & Matters of Fact.

More information

1 EVALUATING CORROBORATIVE EVIDENCE

1 EVALUATING CORROBORATIVE EVIDENCE 1 EVALUATING CORROBORATIVE EVIDENCE In this paper, we study something called corroborative evidence. A typical example would be a case where a witness saw the accused leaving a crime scene, and physical

More information

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1 On Interpretation Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill Section 1 Part 1 First we must define the terms noun and verb, then the terms denial and affirmation, then proposition and sentence. Spoken words

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments

Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments Introduction to Analyzing and Evaluating Arguments 1. HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT Example 1. Socrates must be mortal. After all, all humans are mortal, and Socrates is a human. What does the author of this

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION 11.1 Constitutive Rules Chapter 11 is not a general scrutiny of all of the norms governing assertion. Assertions may be subject to many different norms. Some norms

More information

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice. M05_COPI1396_13_SE_C05.QXD 10/12/07 9:00 PM Page 193 5.5 The Traditional Square of Opposition 193 EXERCISES Name the quality and quantity of each of the following propositions, and state whether their

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 8 Jun 3rd, 9:00 AM - Jun 6th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Goddu James B. Freeman Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center

Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center Covington, Other Logics 1 Other Logics: What Nonclassical Reasoning Is All About Dr. Michael A. Covington Associate Director Artificial Intelligence Center Covington, Other Logics 2 Contents Classical

More information

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2015 Mar 28th, 2:00 PM - 2:30 PM Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism Katerina

More information

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to: Sentential Logic Semantics Contents: Truth-Value Assignments and Truth-Functions Truth-Value Assignments Truth-Functions Introduction to the TruthLab Truth-Definition Logical Notions Truth-Trees Studying

More information

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form. LOGIC GUIDE 2 To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form. LOGICAL FORM The logical form of a statement or argument is the skeleton, or structure. If you retain only the words

More information

Instructor s Manual 1

Instructor s Manual 1 Instructor s Manual 1 PREFACE This instructor s manual will help instructors prepare to teach logic using the 14th edition of Irving M. Copi, Carl Cohen, and Kenneth McMahon s Introduction to Logic. The

More information

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen.

PHI 244. Environmental Ethics. Introduction. Argument Worksheet. Argument Worksheet. Welcome to PHI 244, Environmental Ethics. About Stephen. Introduction PHI 244 Welcome to PHI 244, About Stephen Texts Course Requirements Syllabus Points of Interest Website http://seschmid.org, http://seschmid.org/teaching Email Policy 1 2 Argument Worksheet

More information

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS

Revista Economică 66:3 (2014) THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS THE USE OF INDUCTIVE, DEDUCTIVE OR ABDUCTIVE RESONING IN ECONOMICS MOROŞAN Adrian 1 Lucian Blaga University, Sibiu, Romania Abstract Although we think that, regardless of the type of reasoning used in

More information

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Module by: The Cain Project in Engineering and Professional Communication. E-mail the author Summary: This module presents techniques

More information