Free Will and Theism. Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Free Will and Theism. Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns. edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak"

Transcription

1 Free Will and Theism Connections, Contingencies, and Concerns edited by Kevin Timpe and Daniel Speak 1

2 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries the several contributors 2016 The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in 2016 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: ISBN Printed in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, St Ives plc Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced in this work.

3 2 Libertarianism and the Problem of Flip-flopping John Martin Fischer Introduction We should evaluate views on free will and moral responsibility in terms of a philosophical cost benefit analysis. The benefits of a view must be carefully weighed against its costs. My main topic here is one alleged cost of libertarianism: it appears to imply that our status as free agents who are morally responsible for our behavior hangs on a thread. Libertarianism depends on whether the (arguably) empirical thesis of causal determinism is true. The problem is not that our status as free agents would depend on an empirical thesis as such it is that our status would depend on that sort of empirical thesis. Specifically, our free agency would depend on whether the laws of nature have associated with them 100 percent probabilities, instead of 95 percent or 99 percent probabilities. It seems curious that this sort of difference should change our status as free and morally responsible agents. I am going to argue that it is a cost of libertarianism that it holds our status as agents hostage to theoretical physics, but that claim has met with disagreement. Some libertarians regard it as the cost of doing business, not a philosophical liability. By contrast, Peter van Inwagen has addressed the worry head on. He says that if he were to become convinced that causal determinism were true, he would not change his view that humans are free and morally responsible. Rather, he would give up at least one of the formerly-thought-to-be a priori truths that are elements in his argument for the incompatibility of causal determinism and the relevant sort of freedom. Thus, according to van Inwagen, our status as free and morally responsible agents would not be held hostage to the physicists or hang on a thread. I think that van Inwagen s strategy for securing our freedom and responsibility is unattractive. Somewhat tendentiously, I have called the rejection of an a priori ingredient in the incompatibilist s argument, contingent upon learning that causal determinism is true, metaphysical flip-flopping. 1 And it does seem that van Inwagen s approach 1 The term metaphysical flip-flopping was introduced in Fischer and Ravizza 1998,

4 The Problem of Flip-flopping 49 is implausible insofar as he is open to such metaphysical flip-flopping. That he is open to it that he would flip-flop if he became convinced of the truth of causal determinism is a problem for his actual philosophical position. Or so I will argue. In this essay, I will try to pinpoint and elaborate the problem with metaphysical flip-flopping. I ll thus defend the contention that libertarian views face the worry that they render our status as free and responsible agents unduly at the mercy of certain discoveries of the physicists. I will also argue that libertarian theists libertarians who also believe in God are subject to a structurally parallel worry. That is, given the rejection of the strategy involving the possibility of metaphysical flip-flopping, libertarian theists would appear to have to give up their belief in God, if they were convinced that causal determinism were true. But, again, this is a significant price to pay for one s view about the conditions for free will: one s religious views would be held hostage to a certain sort of empirical discovery. Given the nature of religious beliefs and the nature of this sort of empirical discovery that, say, the laws of nature have associated with them 100 percent probabilities rather than lower ones it seems implausible that the religious beliefs should be held hostage to the possibility of the empirical discovery. The upshot of the discussion is to highlight one cost of libertarianism, which must be placed on the scales when evaluating positions on free will. Of course, no view comes without its costs, and the cost I will be highlighting is only one among a wider set of considerations. Nevertheless, I contend that this cost of accepting libertarianism is not insignificant. The Consequence Argument As I use the term here, libertarianism is the doctrine that human beings are free in the sense required for moral responsibility and that such freedom is incompatible with causal determinism. I further stipulate, at least for this part of the discussion, that the freedom in question involves freedom to do otherwise. To draw the problem with flip-flopping into view, I ll consider an influential and highly plausible argument for the incompatibility of causal determinism and freedom to do otherwise. This is one version a modal version of a family of arguments called the Consequence Argument, so named by Peter van Inwagen to mark the fact that under causal determinism, all of our choices and actions are the (deterministic) consequences of the past and the laws of nature. 2 The version of the Consequence Argument I shall present is a modal version because it employs a certain modal principle: the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness. 3 In stating this principle, it will be helpful to have some definitions at hand. When a proposition p obtains and a person S does not have it in his power so to act that p would not 2 Van Inwagen In the presentation of the modal version of the Consequence Argument, I draw heavily on Fischer and Ravizza 1998,

5 50 John Martin Fischer obtain, I ll say that p is power necessary relative to S. 4 Power necessity is that kind of necessity which implies that a person does not have control over whether a proposition is true. When a proposition is power necessary relative to a person, the proposition in fact obtains and the person has no choice about whether the proposition obtains. The abbreviation, N S,T (p) will stand for: it is power necessary for S at time T that p that is, p obtains and S is not free at T to perform any action such that if S were to perform it, p would not obtain. Consider now the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness: 1. If N S,T (p) and 2. N S,T (If p, then q), then 3. N S,T (q). Roughly, the principle says that if a person is powerless over one thing, and powerless over that thing s leading to another, then the person is powerless over the other. Slightly more carefully, the principle says that if p obtains and a person S cannot so act that p would be false, and S cannot so act that it would be false that if p then q, then q obtains and S cannot so act that q would be false. A second ingredient in the modal version of the Consequence Argument captures the intuitive idea that the past is currently fixed and out of our control. Here is one way of putting the idea: no person can act in such a way that some fact about the past would not have been a fact. Put differently, the thought is that if a person s performing a certain action would require some actual fact about the past not to have been a fact, then the person cannot perform the act. This might be called the Principle of the Fixity of the Past. A further ingredient captures the similar idea that the laws of nature are fixed and out of our control. Intuitively, no human being can act in such a way that some natural law would not be a law. In other words, the Principle of the Fixity of the Laws says that if a person s performing a certain action would require that some actual natural law not be a law, then the person cannot perform the act. Let s define causal determinism as the thesis that implies (whatever else it implies) that, for any given time, a complete statement of the facts about that time, together with a complete statement of the laws of nature, entails every truth as to what happens afterwards. Now the modal version of the Consequence Argument can be stated informally as follows. Suppose that causal determinism obtains and that some ordinary agent, Wilson, does something at a certain time: he mows his lawn on Wednesday afternoon. It follows from causal determinism that conditions obtaining in the past (say, on Monday), together with the laws of nature, entail that Wilson mows his lawn on Wednesday afternoon. And since Wilson has no control over the past, and Wilson has no control over the laws of nature, it follows (given the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness) that Wilson is not free between Monday 4 The term power necessary was introduced by Carl Ginet. See Ginet 1980,

6 The Problem of Flip-flopping 51 and Wednesday afternoon (say, on Wednesday morning) to refrain from mowing on Wednesday afternoon. A slightly more careful statement of the argument is in order. Given that causal determinism is true, there is some statement of the conditions of the world at T1, b, which, together with the laws of nature, entails that S does act A at T3. Since nobody has control over the past, 1. N S,T2 (b at T1). And since nobody has control over the laws of nature, 2. N S,T2 (If b at T1, then S does A at T3). Thus, by the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness, it follows that 3. N S,T2 (S does A at T3). The argument employs plausible ingredients to reach the result that causal determinism is incompatible with freedom to do otherwise the freedom that most libertarians presume is required for moral responsibility. There are other versions of the Consequence Argument, but for our purposes this modal version will do. Van Inwagen s Flip-flopping The Consequence Argument s conclusion that causal determinism is incompatible with free will, in the sense presumed to be required for moral responsibility is disturbing. After all, causal determinism is an empirical thesis that might turn out to be true. We do not know for certain that it is false, and so our status as free and morally responsible agents is called into question. As already noted, van Inwagen has a strategy that seeks to secure our fundamental status as free and morally responsible. He says that in the unlikely event that he were convinced of the truth of causal determinism, he would not conclude that, despite appearances to the contrary, we are not in fact free and morally responsible. Rather, he would give up one of the previously-thought-to-be a priori true elements of the Consequence Argument. Van Inwagen says that he would reject what I have called the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness (van Inwagen s Principle Beta ). He writes: I have defended [Beta, i.e. the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness] entirely on a priori grounds. But it would not surprise me too much to find that this proposition, which at present seems to me to be a truth of reason, had been refuted by the progress of science. Such refutations have happened many times. And it does not follow from the fact that they have happened that there is anything wrong with accepting on a priori grounds a principle that later turns out to be empirically refutable. One must simply realize that a priori convictions are as corrigible as any others. 5 5 Van Inwagen 1983, 221.

7 52 John Martin Fischer This strikes me as problematic. Van Inwagen s willingness to reject the modal transfer principle merely on the supposition that he would become convinced of the truth of causal determinism is unappealing it makes for bad epistemology. I hope to explain the source of my concern. Notice first that there appears to be a difference between the dialectical situation here and the sorts of situations van Inwagen envisions when he writes of principles that had appeared to be truths of reason but were then refuted by the progress of science. Let s say there is a principle P that we take to be an a priori truth. Science gradually progresses to the stage where P, joined with newly developed scientific principles, entails some further proposition that is clearly and indisputably empirically refutable. Then we would rightly abandon what we once took to be an a priori true principle. Importantly, our giving up principle P in the envisaged context is different than van Inwagen s giving up the modal principle in the Consequence Argument upon discovering that causal determinism is true. The Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness is initially regarded as a priori true, but then science marches onward and causal determinism is established as true. So now scientific principles, causal determinism included, as well as the modal principle, entail that we are not free and morally responsible. Although van Inwagen wishes to resist this entailment because he s so confident that we are free and morally responsible, it is not clearly and indisputably empirically refutable that we lack freedom and moral responsibility. That s a crucial difference between the two contexts. Whether we are free and morally responsible is controversial and can t be settled by empirical means alone. (One more thing: the entailed putatively empirical proposition is precisely the proposition at issue in the dialectical context; it then seems especially problematic to employ an antecedent view about this proposition as part of a project of reverse engineering the argument.) To be sure, we sometimes sensibly rethink our commitment to principles earlier deemed a priori truths, as we see in the example involving principle P. But that fact does not by itself make the disposition to metaphysical flip-flopping appropriate for van Inwagen. In An Essay on Free Will, van Inwagen discusses the problems associated with indeterministic conceptions of freedom and moral responsibility. He admits that it is puzzling how an agent can genuinely be in control of his behavior, given indeterminism (in the relevant places along the sequence). But he also admits that it is nevertheless inconceivable that causal determinism is compatible with freedom and moral responsibility. Van Inwagen is quite confident that we are indeed free and morally responsible even though he can t fully explain how we are. And so he confesses: I must choose between the puzzling and the inconceivable. I choose the puzzling. 6 But is this right? Is it really inconceivable for van Inwagen that causal determinism is compatible with freedom and moral responsibility? After all, as I ve already noted, he has written that, if he were to be convinced of the truth of causal determinism, he would give up the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness and embrace compatibilism. My 6 Van Inwagen 1983, 150.

8 The Problem of Flip-flopping 53 question is simple: how then could it be inconceivable that compatibilism is true? Perhaps van Inwagen s point is that at the present moment in the absence of a compelling reason to accept causal determinism it is inconceivable to him that compatibilism is also true, but that if he were convinced of the truth of causal determinism, it would (under those rather different circumstances) be conceivable to him that compatibilism is true. But this seems strange and a little awkward. If it would be conceivable under the envisaged circumstances that compatibilism is true, why isn t it now so conceivable, even in the absence of a belief in causal determinism? If one believes that under the counterfactual circumstances in question, there would be no barrier to conceiving of the truth of compatibilism, why is there now a barrier to conceiving of the truth of compatibilism? The change in the circumstances appears to be irrelevant to the conceivability of compatibilism. So why not bring it home? That is, why not bring home the claim about conceivability to the present circumstance? 7 Recall that van Inwagen sums up his theoretical choice as follows: I must choose between the puzzling [libertarianism] and the inconceivable [compatibilism]. I choose the puzzling. 8 But that isn t quite right. Van Inwagen can and should bring home the conceivability of compatibilism, given what he says about his disposition to flip-flop, upon learning that causal determinism is true. But there is more to say here. I want to push even further and challenge van Inwagen s libertarianism itself. It s not clear why he shouldn t also bring home belief in compatibilism to his current situation, given his flip-flopping disposition. Let us turn to that now. The Flip-flopping Problem Here is a quick initial statement of my argument. The disposition to flip-flop commits van Inwagen to this: if he were to learn that causal determinism ( determinism for short) is true, he would reject the Principle of the Transfer of Powerlessness ( Principle for short). Would he reject the Principle for no reason, aside from his desire to avoid the conclusion it would lead to, or would he have some reason to reject the Principle? Rejecting the Principle merely to avoid an unwanted conclusion seems problematic. And it likewise seems problematic to evaluate evidence differently simply to dodge an unwanted conclusion. So, I will assume that van Inwagen thinks that there would be some reason to reject the Principle, were he convinced that determinism is true. But then why would that reason only exist in the counterfactual scenario? Switching from the actual situation (where van Inwagen doesn t believe that determinism obtains) to the counterfactual situation (where van Inwagen does believe that determinism obtains) doesn t appear to have any impact on the existence of the reason at issue. So, why not bring the reason home? And thus why not bring compatibilism home, too? 7 I am indebted to Michael Nelson for the suggestion that the bringing it home metaphor applies to this sort of dialectical context; see Nelson Van Inwagen 1983, 150.

9 54 John Martin Fischer That was impressionistic, but allow me to develop this argument in more detail. What is so perplexing to me about van Inwagen s position is: the truth of determinism doesn t clearly have anything to do with the Principle. Learning that determinism is true does not seem to call for a different view of the Principle. But, again, van Inwagen s view is that if he were to learn that determinism obtains, he would reject the Principle. How could this be a reasonable policy unless determinism is somehow evidentially related to the Principle? Let me try out an initial thought on what the evidential relation might be. If learning that determinism is true would rationally change van Inwagen s assessment of the Principle, then that s because his evidence for the Principle depends on premises or assumptions that entail the falsity (or low probability) of determinism itself. In slightly different words: if by learning that determinism obtains, he would come to realize that the Principle needs a different assessment, then that s just because the Principle had led him all along to assume that determinism is false (or improbable). Once he learns that determinism is true, so much the worse for the Principle. That seems to be one way that learning that determinism obtains could be evidentially related to the Principle. But this account of the evidential connection is problematic. What is it about the Principle (or van Inwagen s evidence for it) that presupposes that determinism is false? I haven t the foggiest idea. The two seem evidentially unrelated. So, the present account appears to propose an entirely ad hoc evidential connection. Van Inwagen may say that learning that determinism is true is relevant to the Principle in the following way. For starters, notice the obvious: learning that determinism obtains, together with van Inwagen s evidence for incompatibilism (the Principle included), implies that humans lack free will and moral responsibility. If determinism is correct, and if van Inwagen s argument for incompatibilism is correct, there is no free will and moral responsibility. So, given what van Inwagen has learned about determinism from the physicists, there must be some defect in some part of the argument for incompatibilism since he thinks, of course, that we must have free will and moral responsibility. The defect in his argument is one that has so far gone unappreciated by him, but it is a defect nonetheless, and learning that determinism is true has revealed it to him. The idea here is that learning that determinism obtains is evidentially relevant to van Inwagen s assessment of the Principle because learning that determinism is true indicates that the Principle sneaks a defect into the argument. Van Inwagen can now see that the Principle must be mistaken, even if he doesn t know what exactly the problem is. It isn t obvious to me why learning that determinism obtains must rationally change van Inwagen s view of the Principle. We can grant that the Principle may have a hidden defect. But why must the defect rest right there? After all, the up-until-now unrecognized trouble may rest instead with commitment to free will and moral responsibility, not with the Principle. That is at least enough to show it s doubtful that there must be a defect with the Principle: learning that determinism is true, together with the argument for incompatibilism, does not entail that the Principle has a hidden defect,

10 The Problem of Flip-flopping 55 because there may instead be a hidden defect with commitment to free will and moral responsibility. I suspect that it s in the spirit of van Inwagen s position to reason along the following lines. If he learns that determinism is true, he realizes that there must be a hitherto hidden defect with his position. Where is the defect? When surveying his evidence for his position, it seems clear to him that his evidence for the Principle is weaker than his evidence for any other ingredient in his position. So, given the varying degrees of strength of his evidence for the other ingredients, it seems clear to him that the hidden defect is more likely to be found in the Principle than in his commitment to our freedom and responsibility or anything else. Thus, when he learns that determinism is true, he can rationally revise his assessment of the Principle, given that the defect is most likely found there. All of this offers an account of an alleged evidential connection between learning that determinism is true and the Principle. Learning that determinism is true is evidentially related to the Principle because learning as much reveals a hidden defect with the argument for incompatibilism and one that probably resides with the Principle. Even so, none of this makes van Inwagen s metaphysical flip-flopping look attractive, I think. Recall, once more, that van Inwagen says that if he were to learn that determinism is true, he would reject the Principle. This account of the evidential connection assumes that learning that determinism is true only reveals an up-until-now hidden defect with the Principle. What van Inwagen learns doesn t create the defect it merely makes it known. But note well: the account thus implies that the Principle is problematic even before van Inwagen learns that determinism is true. So, by adopting this account of the evidential connection between learning that determinism is true and the Principle, van Inwagen must accept that the Principle is dubious. Therefore, in his actual situation, there is already reason to give up the Principle. And it would seem odd to suppose that, although there is already reason to give up the Principle, the reason only becomes decisive when van Inwagen discovers that causal determinism is true! That is, there is no evidential connection between discovering that causal determinism obtains and the Principle which is such that discovering that causal determinism obtains would put the evidence against the Principle over the top, as it were. Contrast this situation with one provided in correspondence with Dan Speak, who writes: Suppose I rebuild a classic car. In doing so, I had special trouble getting the transmission into form (it s an especially tricky part of the machine). So, before I turn the key to take it for an initial spin, I think to myself, If I can t get this thing to drive properly, the problem is likely with the transmission. Does admitting this commit me to thinking that there is an actual problem with the transmission? Does it require me to give up my belief that the car will in fact run? It doesn t seem so. I agree. But this is because there is some evidential connection (in the context) between the car s not running and the transmission s having a problem; the fact that it doesn t

11 56 John Martin Fischer run, when you turn the ignition key, is further evidence that there is a problem with the transmission. In contrast, the fact that causal determinism obtains would not be further evidence that the Principle is false or at least it is mysterious why this should be so. In the car case, you already suspect the transmission (for good reason). In the case of the argument for incompatibilism, van Inwagen does not already suspect the Principle; in fact, it is quite the contrary. Let us take stock of my discussion of van Inwagen s argumentative approach thus far. Suppose that van Inwagen learns that determinism is true. One possibility, which I have left aside, is that there would be no reason to reject the Principle. Another possibility is that he has some reason to reject the Principle. I have explored what might allow him reasonably to reject it. The trouble, I think, is that if there is a reason to reject the Principle in the counterfactual scenario where physicists report that determinism is true, that reason is already present in the actual scenario. Thus, flip-flopping leads from libertarianism to compatibilism because it requires that there would be, and is, reason to reject the Principle. Could there be another interpretation of van Inwagen s argumentative strategy that I have overlooked? Here is one possibility. 9 Plausibly, van Inwagen actually finds it highly improbable that determinism is true. Under the actual circumstances, and given his belief to which he attaches a high probability that we are free and morally responsible, he deems it more likely that all of the ingredients in the Consequence Argument are true than that compatibilism is. But if he were per improbabile to be convinced that determinism is true, then it would be a matter of giving up the proposition to which he would, under those circumstances, attach the lowest probability. And if he were to believe that causal determinism is true, he would attach a lower probability to at least one of the ingredients in the Consequence Argument (namely, the Principle) than that we are not free and morally responsible. On this strategy, the idea is that van Inwagen is forced to reject at least one principle to which he had previously been attracted, and he rejects the least probable. This strategy raises some similar issues to the ones I have already explored. What are the reasons for accepting certain principles and rejecting others? Going without reasons here seems problematic. But, given that van Inwagen has learned that determinism is true, why is it plausible that the belief in free will and moral responsibility would be assigned a higher probability than the Principle (or other ingredients in the Consequence Argument, such as the Principle of the Fixity of the Past or the Principle of the Fixity of the Laws)? This would seem to suggest excessive confidence in our freedom and responsibility and perhaps an unattractive complacency. To elaborate. Even for van Inwagen, our status as free and morally responsible is not immune to empirical discoveries. He doesn t regard his belief in free will as empirically 9 I am grateful to Derk Pereboom and Christopher Franklin for suggesting this possible interpretation of van Inwagen s approach.

12 The Problem of Flip-flopping 57 indefeasible in the sense that it is supported by reasons that cannot possibly be removed or defeated by empirical reasons. For instance, while arguing against the Paradigm Case Argument, van Inwagen writes that the following scenario is at least possible: (M) When any human being is born, the Martians implant in his brain a tiny device one that is undetectable by any observational technique we have at our disposal, though it is not in principle undetectable which contains a program for that person s entire life: whenever that person must make a decision, the device causes him to decide one way or the other according to the requirements of a table of instructions that were incorporated into the structure of the device before that person was conceived. 10 He goes on to say: If we should discover that some particular person Himmler, say acted as he did because a Martian device, implanted in his brain at the moment of his birth, had caused all his decisions, then we should hardly want to say that Himmler had free will, that he could have helped what he did, that he had any choice about the way he acted, or that he ever could have done otherwise. And I don t see why matters should be different if we discovered that everyone was directed by a Martian device: then we should have to make these judgments about everyone. 11 Of course, it is possible that van Inwagen would give up his association of moral responsibility with freedom to do otherwise, were he to become convinced of (M). But he doesn t endorse this move, and I will assume that, if he were to be convinced that (M) were true, he would give up his view that we are free and morally responsible. And a similar point seems to apply to the discovery that determinism is true. Thus, van Inwagen s belief that we are free and morally responsible agents cannot be an empirically indefeasible belief it can be challenged or defeated by empirical facts. Martians and brain implants to the side, it would seem that our status as free agents can be called into question by other empirical hypotheses. Consider for instance the theses emerging from the situationist and automaticity literatures in psychology. According to certain interpretations of the experimental results, human behavior is largely driven by our emotions and cues from our environment, not reasons. If these contentions are true and of course they are highly controversial then it would at least be plausible that our status as free and morally responsible agents would be called into question. More generally, and for many reasons, moral-responsibility skepticism is a contender in the debates about free will and moral responsibility. To rule out such skepticism from the start is dialectically infelicitous (within the relevant dialectical context). But van Inwagen might still insist that, in the event of his coming to be convinced that determinism were true, he would hold on to the belief in free will and moral 10 Van Inwagen 1983, Van Inwagen 1983, 110.

13 58 John Martin Fischer responsibility and abandon his belief in the Principle. It is mysterious what would allow him to reject the Principle. As discussed earlier, it is unclear how he could sensibly give it up for no reason, and if there would be a reason to give it up, then it seems that there already is such a reason. But set this point aside. I claim that it is just unclear how van Inwagen could explain his preference for freedom and responsibility over the Principle. Antecedently anyway, it wouldn t seem obvious that our status as free and morally responsible agents stands on firmer footing than the Principle. Here is a further point. I would contend that the Consequence Argument does not depend essentially on the Principle. That is, the Consequence Argument can be presented without explicit or implicit reliance on the Principle (or any related transfer of powerlessness principle). 12 If I am correct on this point, then the only way van Inwagen could maintain that we are indeed free and morally responsible, were he convinced that determinism were true, would be to reject the Principle of the Fixity of the Past or the Principle of the Fixity of the Laws. But again it is completely unclear that these Principles are (or would be) less plausible than our status as free and morally responsible agents, or on what basis van Inwagen could reject them in order to maintain his belief in our freedom and moral responsibility. The considerations I ve offered reveal that, on the latest interpretation, van Inwagen s thinking is incomplete in important respects. Why would it be independently plausible, under the assumption of determinism and apart from wishful thinking that one should be less confident in the Principle than our status as free and morally responsible agents? And if, as I believe, the Consequence Argument does not depend on the Principle, why would it be independently plausible that our status as free and morally responsible agents should trump the Principles of the Fixity of the Past and the Laws? Consider some of what van Inwagen says about the laws of nature: It is quite conceivable that human power will grow to the extent that we shall one day be able to alter the stars in their courses. But we shall never be able to do anything about the laws of nature.... [T]he laws of nature impose limits on our abilities: they are partly determinative of what it is possible for us to do. And indeed this conclusion is hardly more than a tautology. 13 In light of his strong defense of the Principle of the Fixity of the Laws, how could he reasonably reject that principle in favor of our freedom and responsibility highly contested notions indeed if he were to be convinced that determinism obtains? Similar considerations also apply to the Principle of the Fixity of the Past. 12 Fischer and Ravizza It should be noted that Van Inwagen disagrees, claiming that all versions of the Consequence Argument depend on the Transfer Principle (his Principle Beta): see, for instance, van Inwagen 1983, 57 where he claims that the three versions of the argument he presents stand or fall together. 13 Van Inwagen 1983, 61 and 62.

14 The Problem of Flip-flopping 59 To sum up. In light of my argument, it seems that van Inwagen cannot easily maintain his libertarianism. On one hand, if he keeps libertarianism, he s subject to the criticism that he is willing to hold to, or reject, putatively fundamental principles simply to get what he wants in the argument. This is dialectically uncomfortable. On the other hand, if van Inwagen can t flip-flop, then our fundamental status as free and morally responsible agents hangs on a thread. Freedom will be held hostage to the theoretical physicists. This is a significant cost of libertarianism. Libertarianism and Theism Just as it is uncomfortable to have one s most basic views about one s freedom and moral responsibility hang on a thread, it is likewise uncomfortable to have one s belief in God held hostage to the possible discovery that determinism is true. If one does believe in God, then presumably a belief in God is a central feature of one s intellectual and affective orientation. So, it is a strike against a position that it so conceptualizes freedom that someone would have to give up her belief in God, if determinism were true. Given that flip-flopping (or the disposition to do so) is not an option, then the libertarian must indeed give up her belief in God, under the circumstance in which she becomes convinced that determinism is true. Let us focus on a libertarian who is also a theist. And allow me to stipulate what is certainly not implausible that the theist holds that belief in human freedom is necessary in order to justify or defend belief in God. Perhaps the theist holds that only those individuals who freely accept God s forgiveness could legitimately be saved, or that only those individuals who freely reject it can be damned. Or perhaps the theist holds that free will is a key component of a defense against the problem of evil. In any case, I shall simply assume that the theist I m talking about must hold that human beings are free. I ll make use of the shorthand: theism requires freedom. Given that theism requires freedom, and that flip-flopping is not an acceptable option, it would seem that a libertarian theist would have to give up her belief in God, if she were to learn that determinism holds. But then one of the libertarian theist s most central and fundamental beliefs will be held hostage to whether the natural laws have associated with them 100 percent probabilities or something less. And this seems uncomfortable. Now it might be objected that a true belief in a certain sort of God would entail the falsity of determinism. If one believed in a God who has the power to intervene in the world and prevent events that otherwise would have occurred, then it would follow that determinism is necessarily false insofar as the required entailments from truths about the past to truths about the present won t be secured. After all, given that such-and-such occurred in the past, it is still open to God to intervene

15 60 John Martin Fischer and thus disrupt the expected connection between such-and-such in the past and so-and-so in the future. So, perhaps a libertarian theist can avoid the problem that her theism hangs on a thread by claiming that determinism is necessarily false. Leaving aside the implausibility of claiming that determinism is necessarily false (and that we can know this from our armchair, as it were), I don t think that this move will help the libertarian theist. Note that what is envisaged is that God has the power to intervene to prevent an agent from behaving as he otherwise would have; but clearly if God were to exercise this power, God would thereby obliterate the agent s libertarian freedom. And this fact helps to generate an argument for the lack of (libertarian) freedom in such a scenario. We can suppose, then, that causal conditions are such that the entailments would go through but for the existence of God (construed as above). Let s also suppose that a God who has the power to intervene in the world exists. Now we assume that Wilson mows his lawn on Wednesday afternoon. Given the assumptions above, we also know that if Wilson had done otherwise (i.e. if Wilson had held off mowing his lawn on Wednesday), then either the past would have been different, some actual law of nature would not have obtained, or God would have intervened. But if Wilson s doing otherwise would require the past to have been different, then it is at least plausible that he was not able to do otherwise (from the Principle of the Fixity of the Past). And if Wilson s doing otherwise would require the laws to have been different, then it was at least plausible that he was not able to do otherwise (from the Principle of the Fixity of the Laws). And if Wilson s doing otherwise would have been as a result of God s intervention, then Wilson surely lacked the power to do otherwise in the sense in question. That is to say, in this scenario he would not have libertarian freedom, in the sense required for moral responsibility. Thus, the libertarian theist is not helped by invoking the thought that, assuming theism, determinism would be necessarily false. And given the unavailability of a disposition toward metaphysical flip-flopping (of the sort discussed earlier), a libertarian theist would always be in an uncomfortable spot. She would have to give up her belief in God, if the scientists were to show that determinism were true. I contend that this is a significant, if not decisive, cost of libertarianism, when the view is joined with theism. Conclusion I have argued that metaphysical flip-flopping is untenable. Thus, some of the most fundamental beliefs held by libertarians about freedom, moral responsibility, and perhaps God are in jeopardy. These important beliefs hang on a thread, in the sense that we would have to abandon them, given an acceptance of libertarianism, if scientists were to convince us that causal determinism is true. One advantage of compatibilism,

16 The Problem of Flip-flopping 61 in all of its forms (classical and semicompatibilism), is that it does not put these 14, 15 fundamental beliefs at risk as libertarianism does. References Ginet, Carl The Conditional Analysis of Freedom. In Time and Cause: Essays Presented to Richard Taylor, edited by Peter van Inwagen. Dordrect: D. Reidel. Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza Free Will and the Modal Principle. Philosophical Studies 83: Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza Responsibility and Control: A Theory of Moral Responsibility. New York: Cambridge University Press. Nelson, Michael Default Compatibilism and Narrativity: Comments on John Martin Fischer s Ways and Stories. Social Theory and Practice 37: Van Inwagen, Peter An Essay on Free Will. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 14 I have contended that the benefits of a philosophical view should be carefully weighed against its costs. Are there any extra benefits of libertarianism that enjoys, or extra costs of compatibilism, in light of our discussion? For theists, the problem of evil may seem to be easier to manage on libertarianism than on compatibilism. As a matter of fact, theists have occasionally argued that the problem of evil is insoluble given the assumption of determinism, and, if that s so, the problem of evil offers reason to favor libertarianism over compatibilism. I do not agree, but a full discussion is beyond the scope of this paper. So let me be brief. As regards human freedom, the compatibilist (and even the semicompatibilist) can hold that human beings have it in a deterministic world; indeed, the theorist can presumably attribute it to agents in just the same places as the libertarian would (in an indeterministic world). But wouldn t it follow from determinism that God is the author of all evil, and thus morally blameworthy for all evil? Again, I think not. True, on this picture, God would arguably be the author (causal source) of all evil, and presumably God would also be morally accountable for it. But moral accountability need not imply blameworthiness (even for evil upshots). Whether God is morally responsible or accountable for an upshot is one thing, and whether God is blameworthy for it is quite another. And whether God is blameworthy is presumably a complicated question having to do with whether, despite the evil, this is the best of all possible worlds. Here I see no reason why the compatibilist can t appeal to the same considerations that a libertarian could about how evil fits into the overall scheme of things. How a given defense or theodicy will fare lies beyond the scope of this paper. The suggestion here is simply that, arguably, a compatibilist is no worse off than an incompatibilist here. 15 For comments on an earlier version, I am grateful to Andrew Bailey, Christopher Franklin, Derk Pereboom, Joshua Rasmussen, Kevin Timpe, Jada Strabbling, and Dan Speak. A previous version was presented at a conference ( Free Will and the Scientific Worldview: Optimistic and Pessimistic Perspectives ) sponsored by the Center for Science, Ethics, and Public Policy at the University of Delaware, Newark: thank you to the audience for helpful discussion. I am especially indebted to detailed and extremely insightful comments by Nathan Ballantyne.

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is The Flicker of Freedom: A Reply to Stump Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is scheduled to appear in an upcoming issue The Journal of Ethics. That

More information

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER . Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 36, No. 4, July 2005 0026-1068 DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University John Martin Fischer University of California, Riverside It is

More information

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM Thought 3:3 (2014): 225-229 ~Penultimate Draft~ The final publication is available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/tht3.139/abstract Abstract: Stephen Mumford

More information

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit Published online at Essays in Philosophy 7 (2005) Murphy, Page 1 of 9 REVIEW OF NEW ESSAYS ON SEMANTIC EXTERNALISM AND SELF-KNOWLEDGE, ED. SUSANA NUCCETELLI. CAMBRIDGE, MA: THE MIT PRESS. 2003. 317 PAGES.

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

The Zygote Argument remixed

The Zygote Argument remixed Analysis Advance Access published January 27, 2011 The Zygote Argument remixed JOHN MARTIN FISCHER John and Mary have fully consensual sex, but they do not want to have a child, so they use contraception

More information

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

Chapter Six Compatibilism: Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford. Chapter Six Compatibilism: Objections and Replies Mele, Alfred E. (2006). Free Will and Luck. Oxford University Press: Oxford. Overview Refuting Arguments Against Compatibilism Consequence Argument van

More information

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument ESJP #12 2017 Compatibilism and the Basic Argument Lennart Ackermans 1 Introduction In his book Freedom Evolves (2003) and article (Taylor & Dennett, 2001), Dennett constructs a compatibilist theory of

More information

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

A New Argument Against Compatibilism Norwegian University of Life Sciences School of Economics and Business A New Argument Against Compatibilism Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Working Papers No. 2/ 2014 ISSN: 2464-1561 A New Argument

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility If Frankfurt is right, he has shown that moral responsibility is compatible with the denial of PAP, but he hasn t yet given us a detailed account

More information

Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued

Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued Compatibilism vs. incompatibilism, continued Jeff Speaks March 24, 2009 1 Arguments for compatibilism............................ 1 1.1 Arguments from the analysis of free will.................. 1 1.2

More information

The Mind Argument and Libertarianism

The Mind Argument and Libertarianism The Mind Argument and Libertarianism ALICIA FINCH and TED A. WARFIELD Many critics of libertarian freedom have charged that freedom is incompatible with indeterminism. We show that the strongest argument

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Moral Responsibility and the Metaphysics of Free Will: Reply to van Inwagen Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 48, No. 191 (Apr., 1998), pp. 215-220 Published by:

More information

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response to this argument. Does this response succeed in saving compatibilism from the consequence argument? Why

More information

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments.

I will briefly summarize each of the 11 chapters and then offer a few critical comments. Hugh J. McCann (ed.), Free Will and Classical Theism: The Significance of Freedom in Perfect Being Theology, Oxford University Press, 2017, 230pp., $74.00, ISBN 9780190611200. Reviewed by Garrett Pendergraft,

More information

MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, DETERMINISM, AND THE ABILITY TO DO OTHERWISE

MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, DETERMINISM, AND THE ABILITY TO DO OTHERWISE PETER VAN INWAGEN MORAL RESPONSIBILITY, DETERMINISM, AND THE ABILITY TO DO OTHERWISE (Received 7 December 1998; accepted 28 April 1999) ABSTRACT. In his classic paper, The Principle of Alternate Possibilities,

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. According to Luis de Molina, God knows what each and every possible human would

More information

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 7 Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Winner of the Outstanding Graduate Paper Award at the 55 th Annual Meeting of the Florida Philosophical

More information

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance It is common in everyday situations and interactions to hold people responsible for things they didn t know but which they ought to have known. For example, if a friend were to jump off the roof of a house

More information

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics

Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics Journal of Cognition and Neuroethics How Not To Think about Free Will Kadri Vihvelin University of Southern California Biography Kadri Vihvelin is Professor of Philosophy at the University of Southern

More information

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism

A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism A Coherent and Comprehensible Interpretation of Saul Smilansky s Dualism Abstract Saul Smilansky s theory of free will and moral responsibility consists of two parts; dualism and illusionism. Dualism is

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Metaphysics and God. Edited by Kevin Timpe. Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump. T&F Proofs: Not For Distribution. New York London

Metaphysics and God. Edited by Kevin Timpe. Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump. T&F Proofs: Not For Distribution. New York London Metaphysics and God Essays in Honor of Eleonore Stump Edited by Kevin Timpe New York London First published 2009 by Routledge 270 Madison Ave, New York, NY 10016 Simultaneously published in the UK by Routledge

More information

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention

Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention Kane is Not Able: A Reply to Vicens Self-Forming Actions and Conflicts of Intention Gregg D Caruso SUNY Corning Robert Kane s event-causal libertarianism proposes a naturalized account of libertarian free

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases Bruce Macdonald University College London MPhilStud Masters in Philosophical Studies 1 Declaration I, Bruce Macdonald, confirm that the work presented

More information

CRITICAL STUDY FISCHER ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY

CRITICAL STUDY FISCHER ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 47, No. 188 July 1997 ISSN 0031 8094 CRITICAL STUDY FISCHER ON MORAL RESPONSIBILITY BY PETER VAN INWAGEN The Metaphysics of Free Will: an Essay on Control. BY JOHN MARTIN

More information

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2015 Mar 28th, 2:00 PM - 2:30 PM Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism Katerina

More information

Free Will [The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy]

Free Will [The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy] 8/18/09 9:53 PM The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy A B C D E F G H I J K L M N O P Q R S T U V W X Y Z Free Will Most of us are certain that we have free will, though what exactly this amounts to

More information

The Consequence Argument

The Consequence Argument 2015.11.16 The Consequence Argument The topic What is free will? Some paradigm cases. (linked to concepts like coercion, action, and esp. praise and blame) The claim that we don t have free will.... Free

More information

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES? MICHAEL S. MCKENNA DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES? (Received in revised form 11 October 1996) Desperate for money, Eleanor and her father Roscoe plan to rob a bank. Roscoe

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3b Free Will

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 3b Free Will Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 3b Free Will Review of definitions Incompatibilists believe that that free will and determinism are not compatible. This means that you can not be both free and determined

More information

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 10, No. 1, March 2007 HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Michael Quante In a first step, I disentangle the issues of scientism and of compatiblism

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society

Bad Luck Once Again. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXVII No. 3, November 2008 Ó 2008 International Phenomenological Society Bad Luck Once Again neil levy Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics, University

More information

Time travel and the open future

Time travel and the open future Time travel and the open future University of Queensland Abstract I argue that the thesis that time travel is logically possible, is inconsistent with the necessary truth of any of the usual open future-objective

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will Stance Volume 3 April 2010 The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will ABSTRACT: I examine Leibniz s version of the Principle of Sufficient Reason with respect to free will, paying particular attention

More information

Free Will Agnosticism i

Free Will Agnosticism i Free Will Agnosticism i Stephen Kearns, Florida State University 1. Introduction In recent years, many interesting theses about free will have been proposed that go beyond the compatibilism/incompatibilism

More information

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will Alex Cavender Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division 1 An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio University of Arizona Some classical studies in social psychology suggest that we are more sensitive to situational factors, and less responsive

More information

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN DISCUSSION NOTE ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN BY STEFAN FISCHER JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE APRIL 2017 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT STEFAN

More information

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism

Williamson, Knowledge and its Limits Seminar Fall 2006 Sherri Roush Chapter 8 Skepticism Chapter 8 Skepticism Williamson is diagnosing skepticism as a consequence of assuming too much knowledge of our mental states. The way this assumption is supposed to make trouble on this topic is that

More information

Free Will. Course packet

Free Will. Course packet Free Will PHGA 7457 Course packet Instructor: John Davenport Spring 2008 Fridays 2-4 PM Readings on Eres: 1. John Davenport, "Review of Fischer and Ravizza, Responsibility and Control," Faith and Philosophy,

More information

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE

ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE Rel. Stud. 33, pp. 267 286. Printed in the United Kingdom 1997 Cambridge University Press ANDREW ESHLEMAN ALTERNATIVE POSSIBILITIES AND THE FREE WILL DEFENCE I The free will defence attempts to show that

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Fischer-Style Compatibilism

Fischer-Style Compatibilism Fischer-Style Compatibilism John Martin Fischer s new collection of essays, Deep Control: Essays on freewill and value (Oxford University Press, 2012), constitutes a trenchant defence of his well-known

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

IS GOD SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' Wesley Morriston In an impressive series of books and articles, Alvin Plantinga has developed challenging new versions of two much discussed pieces of philosophical theology:

More information

Philosophical Review.

Philosophical Review. Philosophical Review Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: The Philosophical Review, Vol. 98, No. 2 (Apr., 1989), pp. 254-257 Published by: Duke University Press on behalf of Philosophical

More information

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) Introduction We often say things like 'I couldn't resist buying those trainers'. In saying this, we presumably mean that the desire to

More information

THE ASSIMILATION ARGUMENT AND THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT

THE ASSIMILATION ARGUMENT AND THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT THE ASSIMILATION ARGUMENT AND THE ROLLBACK ARGUMENT Christopher Evan Franklin ~Penultimate Draft~ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 93:3, (2012): 395-416. For final version go to http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1111/j.1468-0114.2012.01432.x/abstract

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1

MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1 MANIPULATION AND INDEPENDENCE 1 D. JUSTIN COATES UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO DRAFT AUGUST 3, 2012 1. Recently, many incompatibilists have argued that moral responsibility is incompatible with causal determinism

More information

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction Albert Casullo University of Nebraska-Lincoln The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge has come under fire by a

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem

Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem Mark Balaguer A Bradford Book The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England 2010 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this

More information

The Mystery of Free Will

The Mystery of Free Will The Mystery of Free Will What s the mystery exactly? We all think that we have this power called free will... that we have the ability to make our own choices and create our own destiny We think that we

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires. Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires Abstract: There s an intuitive distinction between two types of desires: conditional

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Freedom and Miracles Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: Noûs, Vol. 22, No. 2 (Jun., 1988), pp. 235-252 Published by: Blackwell Publishing Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2215861. Accessed:

More information

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument Richard Johns Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia August 2006 Revised March 2009 The Luck Argument seems to show

More information

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas

Philosophy of Religion 21: (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas Philosophy of Religion 21:161-169 (1987).,, 9 Nijhoff Publishers, Dordrecht - Printed in the Nethenanas A defense of middle knowledge RICHARD OTTE Cowell College, University of Calfiornia, Santa Cruz,

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil.

David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. David E. Alexander and Daniel Johnson, eds. Calvinism and the Problem of Evil. Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock Publishers, 2016. 318 pp. $62.00 (hbk); $37.00 (paper). Walters State Community College As David

More information

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will

Predictability, Causation, and Free Will Predictability, Causation, and Free Will Luke Misenheimer (University of California Berkeley) August 18, 2008 The philosophical debate between compatibilists and incompatibilists about free will and determinism

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 3 February 11th, 2016 Harman, Ethics and Observation 1 (finishing up our All About Arguments discussion) A common theme linking many of the fallacies we covered is that

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Canadian Journal of Philosophy

Canadian Journal of Philosophy Canadian Journal of Philosophy Review: [untitled] Author(s): John Martin Fischer Source: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 31, No. 3 (Sep., 2001), pp. 427-444 Published by: Canadian Journal of Philosophy

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming. Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming. I. Three Bad Arguments Consider a pair of gloves. Name the

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION BY D. JUSTIN COATES JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JANUARY 2014 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT D. JUSTIN COATES 2014 An Actual-Sequence Theory of Promotion ACCORDING TO HUMEAN THEORIES,

More information

Free will and the necessity of the past

Free will and the necessity of the past free will and the necessity of the past 105 Free will and the necessity of the past Joseph Keim Campbell 1. Introduction In An Essay on Free Will (1983), Peter van Inwagen offers three arguments for incompatibilism,

More information

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth SECOND EXCURSUS The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth I n his 1960 book Word and Object, W. V. Quine put forward the thesis of the Inscrutability of Reference. This thesis says

More information

Causation and Free Will

Causation and Free Will Causation and Free Will T L Hurst Revised: 17th August 2011 Abstract This paper looks at the main philosophic positions on free will. It suggests that the arguments for causal determinism being compatible

More information

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will?

What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will? Nathan Nobis nobs@mail.rochester.edu http://mail.rochester.edu/~nobs/papers/det.pdf ABSTRACT: What would be so bad about not having libertarian free will? Peter van Inwagen argues that unattractive consequences

More information

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions GRAHAM OPPY School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University, Clayton Campus, Wellington Road, Clayton VIC 3800 AUSTRALIA Graham.Oppy@monash.edu

More information

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks

Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room. Trenton Merricks Comments on Van Inwagen s Inside and Outside the Ontology Room Trenton Merricks These comments were presented as part of an exchange with Peter van Inwagen in January of 2014 during the California Metaphysics

More information

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora

Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora Could have done otherwise, action sentences and anaphora HELEN STEWARD What does it mean to say of a certain agent, S, that he or she could have done otherwise? Clearly, it means nothing at all, unless

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism

Am I free? Free will vs. determinism Am I free? Free will vs. determinism Our topic today is, for the second day in a row, freedom of the will. More precisely, our topic is the relationship between freedom of the will and determinism, and

More information

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming.

Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks. Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming. Do Ordinary Objects Exist? No. * Trenton Merricks Current Controversies in Metaphysics edited by Elizabeth Barnes. Routledge Press. Forthcoming. I. Three Bad Arguments Consider a pair of gloves. Name the

More information

Leeway vs. Sourcehood Conceptions of Free Will (for the Routledge Companion to Free Will)

Leeway vs. Sourcehood Conceptions of Free Will (for the Routledge Companion to Free Will) Leeway vs. Sourcehood Conceptions of Free Will (for the Routledge Companion to Free Will) Kevin Timpe 1 Introduction One reason that many of the philosophical debates about free will might seem intractable

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information