sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object"

Transcription

1 JUSTIFICATION AND RELATIVE APRIORITY Heimir Geirsson Abstract There is obviously tension between any view which claims that the object denoted is all that names and simple referring terms contribute to propositions expressed by sentences in which they appear and the apparent a posteriority of identity statements containing different but codesignative names. Frege solved the tension by adopting a description theory of names. The direct designation theorist cannot do the same, for that would amount to abandoning the theory. Instead, she has to provide one of two solutions; (a) argue that although Hesperus is Hesperus and Hesperus is Phosphorus express the same proposition their epistemic status differs such that one s justification of the proposition expressed by the former but not the latter is a priori, or (b) argue that both Hesperus is Hesperus and Hesperus is Phosphorus express a priori truths. I will argue for a version of option (a), and that while coreferential names can be freely substituted in simple belief contexts, they cannot be freely substituted in contexts involving justification. The direct designation theory maintains that proper names and other simple referring terms are nondescriptive in content. On most accounts it furthermore includes the claim that these names and simple referring terms only contribute their referents to the propositions expressed by the sentences in which they occur, thus giving us singular propositions that contain the object denoted. One of the alleged consequences of the direct designation theory is that identity sentences such as 1. Hesperus is Phosphorus and

2 2 2. Cicero is Tully express necessary but a posteriori truths. 1 To claim that the class of necessary truths and the class of a priori truths are not extensionally equivalent is in itself remarkable and goes against a well established philosophical tradition reaching, at least, back to Kant. To claim that identity statements provide examples of necessary a posteriori truths is even more remarkable, since it is those kinds of statements Gottlob Frege used when he established his descriptive view of proper names as being infinitely superior to a view that embeds the object denoted by a name occurring in a declarative sentence in the proposition expressed by that sentence. 2 If proper names only contribute the object denoted to the propositions expressed by the sentences in which they appear, Frege asked, how can it be that the proposition expressed by (1) differs in epistemological status from 3. Hesperus is Hesperus which is certainly a priori? There is obviously tension between any view which claims that the object denoted is all that names and simple referring terms contribute to propositions expressed by sentences in which they appear and the apparent a posteriority of identity statements containing different but codesignative names. Frege solved the tension by adopting a description theory of names. The direct designation theorist cannot do the same, for that would amount to abandoning the theory. 3 Instead, she has to provide one of two solutions; (a) argue that although (1) and (3) express the same proposition their epistemic status differs such that one s justification of the proposition expressed by (3) but not (1) is a priori, or (b) argue that (1) as well as (3) expresses an a priori truth.

3 3 I have argued for a version of option (a). 4 Nathan Salmon has argued for option (b) 5 saying, for example, that Recognition of the fact that Cicero is Tully is a priori simpliciter is crucial to finding a philosophically satisfactory solution to Frege s Puzzle. 6 Since Salmon s focus is on the semantic content of singular propositions he allows for substitutions of coreferential names in all belief contexts and claims that identity statements are uninformative and trivial. Against that, I will argue that since the justification of one s belief of singular propositions depends on one s epistemic access to the proposition, substitutions of coreferential names in epistemic contexts involving justification (and thus knowledge) generally fail, even though we can freely substitute coreferential names in simple belief contexts. The bulk of the paper will focus on explaining what it is about singular propositions that forces one to abandon the orthodox account that propositions either are or are not a priori and why the relevant factor only affects contexts involving justification. The last part of the paper will show how Salmon s view is similar to the orthodox account, raise a serious problem for Salmon s view, and show how the problem can be avoided given the relative account of apriority that I advocated in the earlier part of the paper. I. There are those who claim that true identity statements are not necessarily true. Let us assume that proper names are both direct and rigid designators. Consider a world in which Hesperus does not exist, the objection goes, and we have a world in which neither (1) nor (3) is true. But this can easily be fixed. We can consider a conditional, namely 4. If Hesperus exists, then Hesperus is Phosphorus,

4 4 which gives us a necessary truth. If Hesperus does not exist the antecedent is false, and if Hesperus does exist, then both parts of the conditional are true. But, the objection might go, if Hesperus does not exist at a world, then it is not at all clear how to treat existential statements involving Hesperus at that world. So we have not solved a problem, we have just passed it on to an even more persistent problem of existential claims involving nondenoting terms. But this objection is based on the misunderstanding that when we evaluate the truth value of a proposition at a world we have to be at that world and there use the proposition. That is not what we do. Instead, we use the English language as we always do, having already established that Hesperus is a denoting name. Given that I will assume in the remainder of the paper that true identity statements are necessarily true. II. The orthodox account of a priori justification has found a strong supporter in Frege s description theory of names. The basic idea behind the orthodox account is stated as OA below. OA: A proposition is a priori iff it can be justified without empirical evidence. It is important to note that the focus is on justification, not how one acquires the belief. One might need experience to acquire the concepts bachelor and unmarried males, but once one has acquired the concepts one needs no further empirical evidence to justify the belief that all bachelors are unmarried males. This account fits nicely with the descriptive picture Frege gave us. For Frege, propositions are composed of conceptual entities, senses, that reside in the third realm and can be apprehended or grasped by thought. Such an apprehension is direct, so speakers of different languages and different cultures can grasp the same proposition. Furthermore, if two

5 5 persons grasp the same proposition, then they have the same thought or the same belief. A general proposition, unlike singular propositions, cannot be grasped in more than one way. 7 If the sense of Kasparov is the highest rated chess player ever, then the sentence 5. Kasparov is a grandmaster expresses a proposition more perspicuously expressed by 6. The highest rated chess player ever is a grandmaster. And anyone who sincerely assents to (5) (or a proper translation of (5)) would believe the proposition expressed by (6). Most direct designation theorists would balk at this result. According to them the object denoted by a referring term in a simple declarative sentence becomes a part of the proposition expressed by the sentence, giving us singular propositions. The proposition expressed by (5) is properly represented as an ordered pair consisting of the property being a grandmaster and Kasparov himself. (5) expresses the singular proposition 7. <being a grandmaster, Kasparov> and the proposition expressed by (1) is 8. <identity, <Hesperus, Phosphorus>>. How we think of the objects in the propositions plays a role in our thoughts. Contemporary Russellians, such as Nathan Salmon and Scott Soames acknowledge that much. Nathan Salmon talks about one grasping a proposition under an appearance or a guise. 8 Scott Soames claims that Propositions are contents of various intermediaries with which we are intimately related--sentences, belief states, and other modes of presentation. 9 For the purpose of this paper it is not important what exact form mental representation needs to take for a contemporary Russellian. 10 What is important is that one can grasp a proposition in different

6 6 ways depending on how one mentally represents the object in the proposition. We need to consider whether and how the possibility of grasping singular propositions in different ways affects belief contexts. Let us assume for a moment, going along with the Fregean that names have descriptive meanings, that the names Kasparov and Garry have the same descriptive sense and that the embedded sentences in (9) - (14) express the same general proposition. As long as we are dealing with a single general proposition we can assume that if it is true that 9. Sue believes that Kasparov is a grandmaster then it is also true that 10. Sue believes that Garry is a grandmaster and if it is true that 11. Sue is justified in believing that Kasparov is a grandmaster then it is also true that 12. Sue is justified in believing that Garry is a grandmaster, and, if it is true that 13. Sue knows that Kasparov is a grandmaster it is furthermore true that 14. Sue knows that Garry is a grandmaster. The explanation of this is that as long as the proposition remains the same one is grasping it. One cannot grasp the same general proposition in two or more different ways. Consequently, if Sue is justified in believing the proposition, then she cannot grasp the proposition in a new and different way such that she is not justified in believing it, or she doesn t know it, as she now grasps it. 11 Different belief content is explained, by the Fregean, with reference to a different

7 7 proposition being believed, so if two belief contents differ they result from beliefs of different propositions. 12 If one accepts the direct designation theory and singular propositions and tries to accept the same kind of reasoning, then the direct designation theorist is saddled with the view that because the ancients were justified in believing that Hesperus is Hesperus they were justified in believing that Hesperus is Phosphorus, and because they knew that Hesperus is Hesperus, they also knew that Hesperus is Phosphorus; highly improbable scenarios. So, what is a direct designation theorist to do? Suppose Sue sees Kasparov being introduced as being a grandmaster when crowned as the world chess champion. She has then acquired the belief that Kasparov is a grandmaster, her belief is justified, and she knows that Kasparov is a grandmaster. Later Sue sees Kasparov playing volley ball on the beach and hears his teammates call him Garry. She fails to realize that Garry is Kasparov. She has then apprehended 7. <being a grandmaster, Kasparov> in a different way and does not recognize that (7) and 15. <being a grandmaster, Garry> are the same proposition. The fact that Sue does not recognize that (7) and (15) are the same proposition does not prevent us from saying that she nevertheless believes (15) since, after all, (15) and (7) are the same proposition, and one plausible way to account for the belief relation is simply in terms of one standing in the appropriate relation to a proposition. 13 The situation is different with regard to justification. Here we need to take into account how the proposition is apprehended. Sue is obviously justified in believing (7) when she apprehends the proposition as involving Kasparov the chess player. It is equally obvious that

8 8 she is not justified in believing (7) (=(15)) when she apprehends the proposition as involving Kasparov (=Garry) the volley ball player. 14 The reason has to lie in one of two things; how the proposition is presented to Sue, that is, via what sentence she is acquainted with the proposition, or how Sue mentally represents the object in the proposition. It cannot lie in how the proposition is presented to Sue for the same problem can be presented with sentences using only one name of the object in the proposition. 15 So, the reason Sue is not justified in believing that Garry the volley ball player is a grandmaster has to lie in how she mentally represents Kasparov. So, justification, and hence knowledge of singular propositions is tied to mental representation of the object in the proposition. Consider identity statements again. Suppose someone points at Kasparov and informs Sue that this is Kasparov. Sue immediately forms the belief that Kasparov is Kasparov and, given that she only has one representation of Kasparov, her belief is justified without further empirical investigation. Her belief that Kasparov is Kasparov, given how she believes it, is justified a priori. Suppose now that someone points at Kasparov playing on the beach and tells Sue that this is Garry. She already knows who Kasparov is and she knows that Kasparov is Kasparov, but she wonders whether Kasparov is Garry. Given how she now believes the proposition it will take some empirical investigation to justify her belief that Kasparov is Garry. No amount of a priori pondering will justify her belief given how she now believes the proposition. We now see why the orthodox account of the a priori does not apply to singular proposition as it did to general (or conceptualized) propositions. The orthodox account assumes there is only one epistemic access to propositions and that everyone who believes a general

9 9 proposition grasps it in the same way. Consequently the proposition either can or cannot be justified a priori. But this is only true of general propositions. Since there is more than one epistemic access to singular propositions they can be believed in more than one way. Consequently, depending on how the singular proposition is apprehended it can be justified either a priori or only a posteriori. Instead of (OA) we get a relative account of a priori justification of singular propositions RA: A singular proposition is a priori relative to a way of believing it iff when so believed its truth can be justified without empirical evidence. And the corresponding account for a posteriori justification is RAP: A singular proposition is a posteriori relative to a way of believing it iff when so believed its truth cannot be justified without empirical evidence. Finally, since identity statements of the type we have been working with can easily be transformed into necessary truths without its affecting their epistemic status, we have examples of relative necessary a posteriori truths. Keith Donnellan has suggested, but not developed, an account which relativizes a priority to sentences. III. Given that it is true that Cicero is Tully (and whatever we need about what the relevant sentences express) Cicero is Cicero and Cicero is Tully express the same proposition. And the proposition is necessarily true. But looking at the proposition through the lens of

10 10 the sentence Cicero is Cicero the proposition can be seen a priori to be true, but through Cicero is Tully one may need an a posteriori investigation. 16 In Relative and Absolute Apriority Nathan Salmon argues against Donnellan s suggestion that Cicero is Cicero and Cicero is Tully differ in epistemological status. Since Salmon is the only direct designation theorist as of late to argue against relative apriority I will discuss his arguments below. 17 As I have already noted, it is not with what sentence a proposition is presented that makes the crucial difference to whether the proposition is a priori or a posteriori. Rather, it is how the believer mentally represents the object in the proposition that makes the crucial difference. It is therefore a little surprising that both Salmon and Kai-Yee Wong take apriority to apply to sentences as well as to propositions. 18 Where S ranges over true sentences, Salmon provides the following definition of sentence S being a priori. SA: S is a priori (simpliciter) = df S is [could be] a priori with respect to some way of taking a proposition. As a result, Kasparov is Garry is a priori on Salmon s account because there is a way of taking 16. <identity, <Kasparov, Garry>> in such a way that it is a priori. Identity statements, according to Salmon, are analytic, uninformative and trivial, and a priori, for any identity statement N is M, where N and M stand for names, is nothing more than the logical truth that N is itself (e.g., Cicero is Tully is nothing more than the logical truth that Cicero is himself). 19

11 11 But Salmon s account runs into problems with the following example. Let S be the sentence Salmon is in Santa Barbara on March 13th, 1996, at 9:25am, then consider the (supposedly true) proposition I am entertaining expressed by 17. Salmon is in Santa Barbara on March 13th, 1996, at 9:25am. This proposition is the same as the proposition expressed when Salmon thinks to himself in Santa Barbara on March 13th, 1996, at 9:25am 18. I am here now. Anytime the subject in the proposition expressed by (18), the one denoted by I, entertains the proposition his belief cannot be wrong and he does not need any empirical investigation to justify his belief. Hence, (18), when entertained by the subject in the proposition, is a priori. 20 And from this and (SA) it follows that S is a priori; a highly implausible conclusion, for it is utterly impossible that I, I not being Salmon, can know without empirical investigation the whereabouts of Salmon. Notice the similarity between Salmon s position and the orthodox position on apriority. In the spirit of the orthodox account Salmon claims that if a sentence can be a priori, then it is a priori. This is a reasonable claim to make if one does not accept singular propositions. General propositions, remember, are made up of senses that one either grasps or doesn t grasp. There are no ways of grasping general propositions. Consequently, any two persons who grasp the same general proposition grasp it in the same way. If one of the two persons has access to an a priori justification of the proposition, so does the other. And, since one cannot grasp a general proposition in this-or-that way, one cannot believe a general a priori proposition in such a way that, given how one believes it, one can only justify it a posteriori. Because there is only one way in which the proposition can be grasped, it is either a priori or a posteriori. But given that

12 12 singular propositions can be believed in various ways one has to ask why Salmon supports the orthodox account of apriority. The reason Salmon sides with the orthodox view is that he focuses on the semantic content of singular propositions and the semantic contents of, e.g., the propositions expressed by Cicero is Tully or Kasparov is Garry are the same as those expressed by Cicero is Cicero and Kasparov is Kasparov, respectively. The reason Salmon opts for focusing on the semantic content is to be able to account for the analyticity of identity statements. Catsup is Ketchup, he says, is unquestionably analytic, and tomatoes are tomatoes (pronounced tomae-toes and to-mah-toes, respectively) however it is pronounced,...has the logical form of a valid sentence. 21 But this reasoning is not very convincing, for the very issue at hand is whether identity statements, which arguably have the logical form of valid sentences, are unquestionably analytic and thus a priori. Granted, in Relative and Absolute Apriority, but not in Frege s Puzzle, Salmon is a little sympathetic with the relative a priori, allowing propositions to be speaker-relative. But he argues that even the speaker-relative notions do not support the view that Cicero is Tully is a posteriori. More importantly, [the relative notions] do not support the claim that Cicero is Tully is a posteriori, any more than the proposed absolute notions of s-apriority and s- aposteriority do. As we saw above, although Cicero is Tully is a posteriori with respect to some ways of taking its content, a Millian philosopher who both understands the sentence and knows that it is true is liable to take its content in a way with respect to which the sentence is a priori rather than a posteriori. The fact that the sentence is a priori

13 13 with respect to at least one way of taking its content is sufficient for the sentence to be a priori (simpliciter)--otherwise even Tomatoes are tomatoes and Paderewski is Paderewski should be counted a posteriori. 22 I don t find Salmon s examples convincing. Keep in mind that when it comes to singular propositions the road to the semantic content lies through modes of presentation or mental representations. Salmon s Tomato example involves a Santa Barbaran whose limited experience of tomatoes consists of seeing them sliced in salads in the US and in the form of a sauce in England. The Catsup example (previously introduced) involves someone learning the names by ostension or by reading labels or tasting the condiment. And the Paderewski example is, of course, of the same type as my Kasparov example where I argued that Kasparov is Kasparov could, given the right epistemic access, only be justified a posteriori (and notice that my conclusion that Kasparov is Kasparov could, given the right epistemic access, only be justified a posteriori is a far cry from Salmon s attempt to show by reductio that, given his scenario, the sentence or proposition Paderewski is Paderewski should be counted a posteriori, for that claim carries with it a commitment to absolute (not relative) notions of apriority and aposteriority). All of the examples above involve a person having learned the names in the identity statements on different occasions and having different mental representations of what is named. It is precisely because we need to access singular propositions through modes of presentation that vary from person to person that no simpliciter account of apriority will do. Compare this, again, with the traditional account of apriority for general propositions. General propositions are made up of senses and the propositional content is fully disclosed in the senses. You grasp the

14 14 general proposition by grasping the senses. If you change the sense of a name in a sentence that expresses a general proposition, then you change the proposition as well. That is, if you change a mode of presentation, you change the proposition. Not so for singular propositions. When it comes to singular propositions you can change the appearance (the mode of presentation) of an object in a singular proposition without changing the proposition. In short, you cannot change the epistemic access to a general proposition in the way you can change the epistemic access to a singular proposition. Because we cannot change the epistemic access to general propositions, they either are or are not justifiable without empirical evidence. They are either a priori simpliciter or a posteriori simpliciter. And because the epistemic access to singular propositions, such as identity statements, can change, their justification can be either a priori or only a posteriori depending on how the proposition is believed. So, they are not a priori simpliciter and not a posteriori simpliciter. As long as we accept Salmon s assumption that we should only be concerned with the semantic content of propositions when we assess their information content and epistemic status it might seem difficult to avoid his conclusion. But, as I have argued, once we get beyond mere belief and start dealing with justification and knowledge, modes of presentation of the objects in singular propositions affect the epistemic status of the proposition. That allows us to reject Salmon s highly counterintuitive claim that sentences such as Kasparov is Garry are uninformative, trivial, and knowable without experience. Consider again the propositions expressed by (17) and (18) for they provide an excellent reason why we should prefer the relative account of apriority. According to Salmon s account (17) (the sentence) is a priori because what (18) expresses is justified a priori. But to say that (17) or what (17) expresses, when entertained by me, is an a priori truth is highly implausible.

15 15 There is absolutely no way that I, I not being Salmon, can have an a priori justification of what (17) expresses. My epistemic access to the proposition prevents that. Salmon s epistemic access to the same proposition, via (18), shows that there is a way of believing the proposition such that it can be justified a priori. My epistemic access to the same proposition shows that there is a way of believing the proposition such that, given how it is believed, it can only be justified a posteriori. Relativizing apriority accommodates this. Hanging on to the orthodox account, or variations thereof such as Salmon s simpliciter account, saddles us with the highly unintuitive view that my belief about Salmon s whereabouts is justified a priori. Salmon claims that finding a philosophically satisfactory solution to Frege s puzzle requires a recognition of, e.g., Cicero is Tully being a priori simpliciter, for that allows us to say that, in a relevant sense, Cicero is Cicero and Cicero is Tully do not differ in epistemic status. But, as I have argued, Salmon s account faces problems of its own, is counterintuitive, and does not mesh well with singular propositions. Once we accept singular propositions and the fact that they require an epistemic access, allowing us to believe them in more than one way, relativizing justification to how a proposition is believed certainly seems to be the alternative one should take. What stands in the way is only the philosophical tradition of embracing absolute apriority; a tradition that is out of step with recent developments in philosophy of language and metaphysics. IV. I have argued that while we can accept the view that if one believes that, e.g., Hesperus is Hesperus, then one believes that Hesperus is Phosphorus, we cannot assume that the same is true in epistemic contexts, i.e., contexts involving justification and knowledge. If one is justified in believing that Hesperus is Hesperus when thinking of Hespeus under one mode of

16 16 presentation, then it does not follow that one is justified in believing that Hesperus is Hesperus when thinking of Hesperus under different modes of presentation (as represented with, e.g., Hesperus is Phosphorus ). I have argued that singular propositions, unlike general propositions, require an epistemic access via modes of presentation that allows one to grasp the same proposition in more than one way, and that the epistemic access affects the justificatory status of singular propositions in such a way that they require a relative a priori/a posteriori status. The main strength of a view that requires that justification applies to singular propositions as they are believed is that such a view allows us explain why it is that sentences such as Cicero is Tully and Kasparov is Garry are informative and not trivial. It also helps us to explain why a sentence such as (17) does not express an a priori proposition. Two thorny problems for the direct designation theorist are thus taken care of. 23 Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies Iowa State University Ames, IA USA geirsson@iastate.edu

17 17 1 I argue for the necessary a posteriori in Necessity, Apriority, and True Identity Statements, Erkenntnis 1994: , and examples of contingent a priori truths in The Contingent A Priori: Kripke s Two Types of Examples, Australasian Journal of Philosophy 1991: On Sense and Meaning, Translations from the Philosophical Writings of Gottlob Frege, eds. P. Geach and M. Blank (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1952). 3 In Necessity, Apriority, and True Identity Statements I argue that the direct designation theorist cannot assign nondenoting descriptive senses to names. 4 Geirsson, Necessity, Apriority, and True Identity Statements. 5 Salmon, Frege s Puzzle (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1986, and Relative and Absolute Apriority, Philosophical Studies 1993: Salmon, Relative and Absolute Apriority, p Although one can of course express it through two or more different media, such as different languages. 8 See for example Frege s Puzzle, chapter 8. 9 Scott Soames, Substitutivity, On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright, ed. Judith Jarvis Thomson (Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1987) pp , p I give an account of the nature of mental representations of singular propositions in Necessity, Apriority, and True Identity Statements. 11 Note that I am not claiming that one cannot have an a posteriori justification for an a priori general proposition. For one can certainly learn an a priori truth by hearing it from an authority; one might, e.g., learn from an authority of the English language that all bachelors are unmarried males, and one might learn mathematical a priori truths from a mathematician. But

18 18 the proposition nevertheless remains a priori, for it can be justified a priori and (unlike singular propositions) one cannot believe the proposition in such a way that the way one believes it lends itself only to a posteriori justification. 12 We might find an exception in those Fregeans who admit of non-linguistic, or de re, beliefs of the kind Gareth Evans, Graeme Forbes, and John McDowell have advocated, for they might allow for more than one epistemic access to a proposition. If in fact they do, I expect that the argument can be extended to include their position. The key to the argument s success, after all, is not the direct designation theory, but rather that it allows us to have more than one epistemic access to a proposition. 13 Vision provides a good analogy. If you see object X at two different times and you do not recognize it as being the same object, you nevertheless see object X on both occasions. Like Salmon, I think that the belief relation is a binary relation between a person and a proposition. A belief report simply relates a person to a proposition without making any claims about how she believes the proposition. I discuss belief reports in Partial Propositions and Cognitive Content, Journal of Philosophical Research, 1996: It is important to note that even though I accept belief as being a binary relation, as simply standing in the appropriate relation to a proposition, I nevertheless recognize the importance of how a proposition is believed when it comes to its justification. 14 Consider me asking Sue Is this person a grandmaster, pointing at Kasparov (a) at the ceremonies and (b) at the beach. Sue would confidently answer with a yes at the ceremonies, but not at the beach. 15 Kripke s well-known Paderewski puzzle.

19 19 16 Donnellan, K. Kripke and Putnam on Natural Kind Terms, in C. Ginet and S. Shoemaker, eds., Knowledge and Mind (Oxford University Press, 1983), pp , at p. 88n. 17 Only two philosophers have, to my knowledge, argued for relative apriority. K-Y Wong, in A Priority and Ways of Grasping a Proposition, Philosophical Studies 62, 1991: , has argued that N. Salmon should welcome a relative notion of apriority within his theoretical framework in Frege s Puzzle. For Salmon s reply to Wong see How Not to Become a Millian Heir, Philosophical Studies 62, 1991: See also Singular Propositions and the A Priori in Journal of Philosophical Research, 21, 1996: I have argued more broadly for relative apriority, first in Names and Beliefs (1988), a dissertation written at the University of Nebraska, Lincoln. Subsequent versions of the arguments were presented at the 1990 meeting of the Central States Philosophical Association and the 1991 APA Pacific Division meeting, and in Necessity, Apriority, and True Identity Statements, Erkenntnis 1994: My arguments are not directed specifically against Salmon but are rather intended to apply to any view that accepts untainted singular propositions as objects of belief. 18 Wong, K-Y Sentence-Relativity and the Necessary A Posteriori, Philosophical Studies : Salmon, Relative and Absolute Apriority p Wong and Salmon discuss this example in their exchange, but there the focus is on whether the proposition expressed by I am here now is or is not a logical truth. Salmon doubts it is a logical truth, and hence that it is a priori. The example that seems to have changed Salmon s mind on the issue (for in Frege s Puzzle he allowed for the proposition to be a priori) is G. Vision s example of the standard answering-machine message I am not here now. But the

20 20 discussion, as well as Salmon s doubt, are misguided. The issue does not concern the supposed logical truth of I am here now, but whether it is a priori. And assertions in absentia, like in the answering-machine example, do not show that the proposition is not a priori, for the I in the proposition is presumably not entertaining the proposition at the time the machine plays its tape. 21 Salmon, p Salmon, p I thank Rod Bertolet and Richard Mendelsohn for comments on an earlier version of this paper.

Discovering Identity

Discovering Identity Discovering Identity Let a and b stand for different but codesignative proper names. It then seems clear that the propositions expressed by a=a and a=b differ in cognitive value. For example, if a stands

More information

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956)

Phil 435: Philosophy of Language. [Handout 7] W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956) Quine & Kripke 1 Phil 435: Philosophy of Language [Handout 7] Quine & Kripke Reporting Beliefs Professor JeeLoo Liu W. V. Quine, Quantifiers and Propositional Attitudes (1956) * The problem: The logical

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. Appeared in Philosophical Review 105 (1998), pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE

PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE PHILOSOPHICAL PROBLEMS & THE ANALYSIS OF LANGUAGE Now, it is a defect of [natural] languages that expressions are possible within them, which, in their grammatical form, seemingly determined to designate

More information

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle Millian responses to Frege s puzzle phil 93914 Jeff Speaks February 28, 2008 1 Two kinds of Millian................................. 1 2 Conciliatory Millianism............................... 2 2.1 Hidden

More information

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions

Puzzles of attitude ascriptions Puzzles of attitude ascriptions Jeff Speaks phil 43916 November 3, 2014 1 The puzzle of necessary consequence........................ 1 2 Structured intensions................................. 2 3 Frege

More information

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind phil 93515 Jeff Speaks February 7, 2007 1 Problems with the rigidification of names..................... 2 1.1 Names as actually -rigidified descriptions..................

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Contextual two-dimensionalism Contextual two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks November 30, 2009 1 Two two-dimensionalist system of The Conscious Mind.............. 1 1.1 Primary and secondary intensions...................... 2

More information

Two-Dimensionalism and Kripkean A Posteriori Necessity

Two-Dimensionalism and Kripkean A Posteriori Necessity Two-Dimensionalism and Kripkean A Posteriori Necessity Kai-Yee Wong [Penultimate Draft. Forthcoming in Two-Dimensional Semantics, Oxford University Press] Department of Philosophy, The Chinese University

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers

Grounding and Analyticity. David Chalmers Grounding and Analyticity David Chalmers Interlevel Metaphysics Interlevel metaphysics: how the macro relates to the micro how nonfundamental levels relate to fundamental levels Grounding Triumphalism

More information

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00.

Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379. ISBN $35.00. Appeared in Linguistics and Philosophy 26 (2003), pp. 367-379. Scott Soames. 2002. Beyond Rigidity: The Unfinished Semantic Agenda of Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pp. i-ix, 379.

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction

Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction Quine on the analytic/synthetic distinction Jeff Speaks March 14, 2005 1 Analyticity and synonymy.............................. 1 2 Synonymy and definition ( 2)............................ 2 3 Synonymy

More information

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Epistemic two-dimensionalism Epistemic two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks December 1, 2009 1 Four puzzles.......................................... 1 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism................................ 3 2.1 Two-dimensional

More information

Analyticity and reference determiners

Analyticity and reference determiners Analyticity and reference determiners Jeff Speaks November 9, 2011 1. The language myth... 1 2. The definition of analyticity... 3 3. Defining containment... 4 4. Some remaining questions... 6 4.1. Reference

More information

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports Stephen Schiffer New York University The direct-reference theory of belief reports to which I allude is the one held by such theorists as Nathan

More information

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem

Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem Two-dimensional semantics and the nesting problem David J. Chalmers and Brian Rabern July 2, 2013 1 Introduction Graeme Forbes (2011) raises some problems for two-dimensional semantic theories. The problems

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Australasian Journal of Philosophy

Australasian Journal of Philosophy Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 69, No. 2: June 1991 THE CONTINGENT A PRIORI: KRIPKE'S TWO TYPES OF EXAMPLES Heimir Geirsson The thesis that the necessary and the a prior/are extensionally equivalent

More information

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames Draft March 1, 2014 My theory of propositions starts from two premises: (i) agents represent things as being certain ways when they perceive, visualize, imagine,

More information

An argument against descriptive Millianism

An argument against descriptive Millianism An argument against descriptive Millianism phil 93914 Jeff Speaks March 10, 2008 The Unrepentant Millian explains apparent differences in informativeness, and apparent differences in the truth-values of

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 3: The Case for A Priori Scrutability David Chalmers Plan *1. Sentences vs Propositions 2. Apriority and A Priori Scrutability 3. Argument 1: Suspension of Judgment 4. Argument

More information

Against the Contingent A Priori

Against the Contingent A Priori Against the Contingent A Priori Isidora Stojanovic To cite this version: Isidora Stojanovic. Against the Contingent A Priori. This paper uses a revized version of some of the arguments from my paper The

More information

Philip D. Miller Denison University I

Philip D. Miller Denison University I Against the Necessity of Identity Statements Philip D. Miller Denison University I n Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke argues that names are rigid designators. For Kripke, a term "rigidly designates" an

More information

Comments on Carl Ginet s

Comments on Carl Ginet s 3 Comments on Carl Ginet s Self-Evidence Juan Comesaña* There is much in Ginet s paper to admire. In particular, it is the clearest exposition that I know of a view of the a priori based on the idea that

More information

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz

Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D Konstanz CHANGING CONCEPTS * Wolfgang Spohn Fachbereich Philosophie Universität Konstanz D 78457 Konstanz At the beginning of his paper (2004), Nenad Miscevic said that empirical concepts have not received the

More information

Knowledge of Manifest Natural Kinds

Knowledge of Manifest Natural Kinds Knowledge of Manifest Natural Kinds 159 Facta Philosophica 6, 2004: 159 181 Peter Lang, Switzerland Knowledge of Manifest Natural Kinds Scott Soames Manifest kinds are natural kinds designated by terms

More information

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Putnam: Meaning and Reference Putnam: Meaning and Reference The Traditional Conception of Meaning combines two assumptions: Meaning and psychology Knowing the meaning (of a word, sentence) is being in a psychological state. Even Frege,

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 1: A Scrutable World David Chalmers Plan *1. Laplace s demon 2. Primitive concepts and the Aufbau 3. Problems for the Aufbau 4. The scrutability base 5. Applications Laplace

More information

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS

APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS APRIORITY AND MEANING: A CASE OF THE EPISTEMIC TWO-DIMENSIONAL SEMANTICS By Mindaugas Gilaitis Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

NAMING WITHOUT NECESSITY

NAMING WITHOUT NECESSITY NAMING WITHOUT NECESSITY By NIGEL SABBARTON-LEARY A thesis submitted to The University of Birmingham for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Department of Philosophy School of Philosophy, Theology and Religious

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997)

This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) This is a longer version of the review that appeared in Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 47 (1997) Frege by Anthony Kenny (Penguin, 1995. Pp. xi + 223) Frege s Theory of Sense and Reference by Wolfgang Carl

More information

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1

On a priori knowledge of necessity 1 < Draft, April 14, 2018. > On a priori knowledge of necessity 1 MARGOT STROHMINGER AND JUHANI YLI-VAKKURI 1. A priori principles in the epistemology of modality It is widely thought that the epistemology

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio This is the pre-peer reviewed version of the following article: Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2006), Externalism

More information

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference

Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Philosophia (2014) 42:1099 1109 DOI 10.1007/s11406-014-9519-9 Definite Descriptions and the Argument from Inference Wojciech Rostworowski Received: 20 November 2013 / Revised: 29 January 2014 / Accepted:

More information

Response. Paul Johnson University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign

Response. Paul Johnson University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign Response Paul Johnson University of Illinois, Urbana-Champaign Miller has offered us a solution to what we may agree, on the authority of Kripke himself, is a deep and genuine conceptual conundrum arising

More information

Propositions as Cambridge properties

Propositions as Cambridge properties Propositions as Cambridge properties Jeff Speaks July 25, 2018 1 Propositions as Cambridge properties................... 1 2 How well do properties fit the theoretical role of propositions?..... 4 2.1

More information

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem

Lecture 4. Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem 1 Lecture 4 Before beginning the present lecture, I should give the solution to the homework problem posed in the last lecture: how, within the framework of coordinated content, might we define the notion

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism by Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC To Appear in On Sense and Direct Reference: A Reader in Philosophy of Language Matthew Davidson, editor McGraw-Hill Ambitious Two-Dimensionalism

More information

On A Priori Knowledge of Necessity 1

On A Priori Knowledge of Necessity 1 < Draft, November 11, 2017. > On A Priori Knowledge of Necessity 1 MARGOT STROHMINGER AND JUHANI YLI-VAKKURI Abstract The idea that the epistemology of (metaphysical) modality is in some sense a priori

More information

Informative Identities in the Begriffsschrift and On Sense and Reference

Informative Identities in the Begriffsschrift and On Sense and Reference Informative Identities in the Begriffsschrift and On Sense and Reference This paper is about the relationship between Frege s discussions of informative identity statements in the Begriffsschrift and On

More information

A Posteriori Necessities

A Posteriori Necessities A Posteriori Necessities 1. Introduction: Recall that we distinguished between a priori knowledge and a posteriori knowledge: A Priori Knowledge: Knowledge acquirable prior to experience; for instance,

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE 15-Jackson-Chap-15.qxd 17/5/05 5:59 PM Page 395 part iv PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE 15-Jackson-Chap-15.qxd 17/5/05 5:59 PM Page 396 15-Jackson-Chap-15.qxd 17/5/05 5:59 PM Page 397 chapter 15 REFERENCE AND DESCRIPTION

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi

Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi Names Introduced with the Help of Unsatisfied Sortal Predicates: Reply to Aranyosi Hansson Wahlberg, Tobias Published in: Axiomathes DOI: 10.1007/s10516-009-9072-5 Published: 2010-01-01 Link to publication

More information

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper

Strawson On Referring. By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper Strawson On Referring By: Jake McDougall and Siri Cosper Russell s Theory of Descriptions S: The King of France is wise. Russell believed that our languages grammar, or every day use, was underpinned by

More information

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference

Kripke s Naming and Necessity. The Causal Picture of Reference Kripke s Naming and Necessity Lecture Four The Causal Picture of Reference Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Introduction The Causal Picture of Reference Introduction The Links in a

More information

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen

Philosophical Logic. LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen Philosophical Logic LECTURE TWO MICHAELMAS 2017 Dr Maarten Steenhagen ms2416@cam.ac.uk Last Week Lecture 1: Necessity, Analyticity, and the A Priori Lecture 2: Reference, Description, and Rigid Designation

More information

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports

A set of puzzles about names in belief reports A set of puzzles about names in belief reports Line Mikkelsen Spring 2003 1 Introduction In this paper I discuss a set of puzzles arising from belief reports containing proper names. In section 2 I present

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts

Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts 114 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 39, Number 1, Winter 1998 Singular Propositions and Singular Thoughts ARTHUR SULLIVAN Abstract The core of the debate between Fregeans and Russellians in the

More information

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body

Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Kripke on the distinctness of the mind from the body Jeff Speaks April 13, 2005 At pp. 144 ff., Kripke turns his attention to the mind-body problem. The discussion here brings to bear many of the results

More information

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which

Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames. sentence, or the content of a representational mental state, involves knowing which Propositions as Cognitive Acts Scott Soames My topic is the concept of information needed in the study of language and mind. It is widely acknowledged that knowing the meaning of an ordinary declarative

More information

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers

Primitive Concepts. David J. Chalmers Primitive Concepts David J. Chalmers Conceptual Analysis: A Traditional View A traditional view: Most ordinary concepts (or expressions) can be defined in terms of other more basic concepts (or expressions)

More information

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006

Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke. M.A. Thesis Proposal. Department of Philosophy, CSULB. 25 May 2006 1 Conceivability and Possibility Studies in Frege and Kripke M.A. Thesis Proposal Department of Philosophy, CSULB 25 May 2006 Thesis Committee: Max Rosenkrantz (chair) Bill Johnson Wayne Wright 2 In my

More information

Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics Percipi 1 (2007): 18 31 Conceivability, Possibility and Two-Dimensional Semantics Paul Winstanley Unversity of Durham paul.winstanley@durham.ac.uk Abstract Kripke (1980) famously separates the metaphysical

More information

Thinking About Consciousness

Thinking About Consciousness 774 Book Reviews rates most efficiently from each other the complexity of what there is in Jean- Jacques Rousseau s text, and the process by which the reader has encountered it. In a most original and

More information

Horwich and the Liar

Horwich and the Liar Horwich and the Liar Sergi Oms Sardans Logos, University of Barcelona 1 Horwich defends an epistemic account of vagueness according to which vague predicates have sharp boundaries which we are not capable

More information

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii) PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 8: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Introduction, Chapters 1-2) Introduction * We are introduced to the ideas

More information

Mental Files and their Identity Conditions

Mental Files and their Identity Conditions Mental Files and their Identity Conditions University of Oxford BIBLID [0873-626X (2013) 36; pp. 177-190] It is increasingly common for a thinker s capacity for singular thought to be described in terms

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit Published online at Essays in Philosophy 7 (2005) Murphy, Page 1 of 9 REVIEW OF NEW ESSAYS ON SEMANTIC EXTERNALISM AND SELF-KNOWLEDGE, ED. SUSANA NUCCETELLI. CAMBRIDGE, MA: THE MIT PRESS. 2003. 317 PAGES.

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

Review Essay: Scott Soames, Philosophy of Language

Review Essay: Scott Soames, Philosophy of Language Review Essay: Scott Soames, Philosophy of Language Kirk Ludwig Philosophical Quarterly of Israel ISSN 0048-3893 DOI 10.1007/s11406-013-9447-0 1 23 Your article is protected by copyright and all rights

More information

Sense, Communication, and Rational Engagement Imogen Dickie and Gurpreet Rattan, University of Toronto

Sense, Communication, and Rational Engagement Imogen Dickie and Gurpreet Rattan, University of Toronto Sense, Communication, and Rational Engagement Imogen Dickie and Gurpreet Rattan, University of Toronto This paper is about the relation between a singular term s cognitive significance and the requirements

More information

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on

Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, True at. Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC. To Appear In a Symposium on Draft January 19, 2010 Draft January 19, 2010 True at By Scott Soames School of Philosophy USC To Appear In a Symposium on Herman Cappelen and John Hawthorne Relativism and Monadic Truth In Analysis Reviews

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 6: Whither the Aufbau? David Chalmers Plan *1. Introduction 2. Definitional, Analytic, Primitive Scrutability 3. Narrow Scrutability 4. Acquaintance Scrutability 5. Fundamental

More information

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle

The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Graduate Student Publications and Research CUNY Academic Works 2015 The Two Indexical Uses Theory of Proper Names and Frege's Puzzle Daniel S. Shabasson

More information

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori Lingnan University Digital Commons @ Lingnan University Theses & Dissertations Department of Philosophy 2014 Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori Hiu Man CHAN Follow this and additional

More information

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June 2 Reply to Comesaña* Réplica a Comesaña Carl Ginet** 1. In the Sentence-Relativity section of his comments, Comesaña discusses my attempt (in the Relativity to Sentences section of my paper) to convince

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Reply to Robert Koons

Reply to Robert Koons 632 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 35, Number 4, Fall 1994 Reply to Robert Koons ANIL GUPTA and NUEL BELNAP We are grateful to Professor Robert Koons for his excellent, and generous, review

More information

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03

Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03 Glossary of Terms Jim Pryor Princeton University 2/11/03 Beliefs, Thoughts When I talk about a belief or a thought, I am talking about a mental event, or sometimes about a type of mental event. There are

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics

Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics Wittgenstein s The First Person and Two-Dimensional Semantics ABSTRACT This essay takes as its central problem Wittgenstein s comments in his Blue and Brown Books on the first person pronoun, I, in particular

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone?

Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone? Is anything knowable on the basis of understanding alone? PHIL 83104 November 7, 2011 1. Some linking principles... 1 2. Problems with these linking principles... 2 2.1. False analytic sentences? 2.2.

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03

Minds and Machines spring The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited spring 03 Minds and Machines spring 2003 The explanatory gap and Kripke s argument revisited 1 preliminaries handouts on the knowledge argument and qualia on the website 2 Materialism and qualia: the explanatory

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning

Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Epistemic Contextualism as a Theory of Primary Speaker Meaning Gilbert Harman, Princeton University June 30, 2006 Jason Stanley s Knowledge and Practical Interests is a brilliant book, combining insights

More information

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language

Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language Philosophy 1760 Philosophy of Language Instructor: Richard Heck Office: 205 Gerard House Office hours: M1-2, W12-1 Email: rgheck@brown.edu Web site: http://frege.brown.edu/heck/ Office phone:(401)863-3217

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Relative Thoughts. Dr. Sanna Hirvonen Junior visiting fellow, Universita Degli Studi di Milano

Relative Thoughts. Dr. Sanna Hirvonen Junior visiting fellow, Universita Degli Studi di Milano Relative Thoughts Dr. Sanna Hirvonen Junior visiting fellow, Universita Degli Studi di Milano hirvonen.philosophy@gmail.com 1 Course schedule Lecture 1, Mon 16 th Oct, 10-12am: Propositions as contents

More information

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers

Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers Constructing the World, Lecture 4 Revisability and Conceptual Change: Carnap vs. Quine David Chalmers Text: http://consc.net/oxford/. E-mail: chalmers@anu.edu.au. Discussion meeting: Thursdays 10:45-12:45,

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester

Russellianism and Explanation. David Braun. University of Rochester Forthcoming in Philosophical Perspectives 15 (2001) Russellianism and Explanation David Braun University of Rochester Russellianism is a semantic theory that entails that sentences (1) and (2) express

More information

Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism

Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism Against Sainsbury and Tye s Originalism A Critical Investigation of an Originalist Theory of Concepts and Thoughts Sara Kasin Vikesdal Thesis presented for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY Supervised

More information

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at

by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at Fregean Sense and Anti-Individualism Daniel Whiting The definitive version of this article is published in Philosophical Books 48.3 July 2007 pp. 233-240 by Blackwell Publishing, and is available at www.blackwell-synergy.com.

More information