Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology Meets Gettier s Counterexamples

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology Meets Gettier s Counterexamples"

Transcription

1 Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology Meets Gettier s Counterexamples John Ian K. Boongaling Abstract The overall goal of this paper is to apply Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology to Gettier s counterexamples to the tripartite definition of knowledge as justified true belief. In the process, I will make full use of Socratic Epistemology s methodology and commitments. This includes, among other things, looking at Gettier s counterexamples as games between an Inquirer and Nature (the source of information), as well as treating the items in them as pieces of information. The strategy that I employ in this paper also makes use of frames (or partitions). One of the important results of this paper is a scenario where Gettier cannot setup the dilemma for the tripartite definition of knowledge. Keywords: Hintikka s socratic epistemology, Gettier s counterexamples, knowledge as justified true belief, interrogative model of inquiry, deductive and interrogative moves, logic of questions and answers 1 Introduction One of the reasons why epistemic agents like you and me take serious interest in knowing that something is the case is because having knowledge is valuable, that such a state is preferable to ignorance. If we can grant this, then perhaps we can also grant something else: that as epistemic agents, we aim (or should aim) at knowledge. While these ideas are unproblematic for most (if not all) of us, some disagreements may soon appear once we get into the details. To begin with, there seems to be no hope of defining the concept of knowledge without dealing with the difficult problems that are associated with the concepts that traditionally comprise it: (1) truth, (2) belief, and (3) justification. As is well known, the idea that knowledge is justified true belief (henceforth JTB) may be traced back to the writings of Plato. For Kriterion Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): c 2017 The author

2 26 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): instance, in 201d of the Theaetetus, Theodorus pupil, Theaetetus, responds to Socrates in the following way: Oh, yes, Socrates, that s just what I once heard a man say; I had forgotten, but now it s coming back to me. He said that it is true judgment with an account that is knowledge; true judgment without an account falls outside of knowledge. And he said that the things of which there is no account are not knowable (yes, he actually called them that), while those which have an account are knowable. [7, p. 223, emphasis added] Subsequent scholars refer to the foregoing as the tripartite definition (or standard analysis) of knowledge. The tripartite definition of knowledge, however, had been the target of what contemporary epistemologists refer to as the Gettier counterexamples (or Gettier cases). In a landmark paper, Edmund Gettier sums up the knowledge as JTB thesis in the following way: a subject S knows that P (where P is a proposition) if and only if the following conditions hold: (1) P is true, (2) S believes that P, and (3) S is justified in believing that P [1, p. 121]. In a very general way, it can be said that the Gettier counterexamples (henceforth GCs) demonstrate that it is possible for all three conditions to be satisfied by an epistemic agent and still fail to have knowledge. For most of us, philosophy involves logical and conceptual analysis, and perhaps, this is the reason why a significant number of philosophers agree that the GCs count as successful refutations of the JTB thesis. In fact, Ernest Sosa, et al states: Edmund Gettier s landmark paper successfully refuted the traditional analysis of knowledge as justified true belief. Through a series of examples, Gettier shows that one can believe what is true and be justified in so believing and yet fail to know. Justified true belief is not sufficient for knowledge. [8, p. 189, (emphasis added)] To further strengthen the point that a significant number of philosophers agree that the GCs count as successful refutations of the JTB thesis, consider Michael Huemer s description of Gettier s overall strategy below: Edmund Gettier famously refuted the justified, true belief theory by means of a type of counter-example now referred to

3 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 27 as a Gettier case. There are two possible kinds of counterexample to a definition. The first kind is one that would show the definition to be too broad; in this case, this would mean an example of something that in fact is not knowledge, but that the definition would count as knowledge... The other kind is that which would show the definition to be too narrow; in this case, an example of something that in fact is knowledge but that the definition would fail to classify as knowledge. Gettier s counter-examples are of the first kind; in other words, they show that justified, true belief is not sufficient for knowledge. [4, p. 436 (emphasis in the original)] From the foregoing discussion, it is safe to say that at this point in time, no philosopher may easily maintain that the JTB thesis is correct in the absence of a successful argument that shows that the GCs are mistaken. In my estimation, this shows that the GCs exert tremendous impact not only on attempts to construe knowledge as JTB but also to other attempts that seek to identify conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for knowledge. Given these things, one may ask whether or not contemporary epistemology should be concerned with the task of identifying these conditions. In other words, we may ask ourselves whether or not contemporary epistemology should be concerned with the definition (or the analysis) of knowledge. In relation to the questions above, Jaakko Hintikka offers a different view through his Socratic Epistemology (henceforth SE) or what he refers to as the Interrogative Model of Inquiry in his earlier works. 1 In a way, Hintikka s SE, as a model of inquiry, is revolutionary in the sense that it envisions a way of doing epistemology without the concepts of knowledge and belief. Consider what Hintikka says in the following: If we review the questioning process through which we obtain our knowledge and justify it and inventory the concepts employed in the process, we find all the notions of a logic of questions and answers, the notions of ordinary deductive logic, and something like the notions of acceptance and rejection in the form of rules of bracketing and unbracketing. We also find a notion roughly tantamount to the concept of information. What we do not find are philosophers concepts of knowledge and belief. Hence, the problems of knowledge acquisition can be examined, and must be examined, without using the two concepts. This is perhaps not surprising, for if knowledge is going to be the end product of interrogative

4 28 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): inquiry, it cannot be one of the means of reaching this goal. [2, p. 9 (emphasis added)] At this point, I have only described (in a very general way) the significant items that I would like to investigate in this paper: (1) the tripartite definition of knowledge as JTB, (2) the GCs as refutations of (or at the very least, difficult challenges to) the JTB thesis, and (3) Hintikka s SE and its revolutionary character. In the proceeding parts of the paper, I will discuss these items in a more precise and detailed manner. As I have mentioned earlier, the overall goal of this paper is to apply Hintikka s SE to the GCs. Allow me to briefly explain why I think the aforementioned goal is both important and interesting especially for philosophers interested in contemporary epistemology (and this requires a little bit of context). As is well known, epistemology after Gettier s famous paper continues to grapple with the problems posed by the GCs to the tripartite definition of knowledge as JTB. As discussed earlier, one of the reasons for this is the fact that a significant number of philosophers consider the GCs as successful refutations of the JTB thesis. This has resulted to at least two things: (1) some form of skepticism about the entire project of providing a definition (or an analysis) of knowledge, and (2) the continuous attempts by philosophers to identify a fourth condition to the JTB so as to avoid the problems posed by the GCs. In any case, it would not be implausible to maintain that contemporary epistemology is still unable to free itself from the clutches of the GCs. For instance, regarding (2) above, David Moshman points out that while philosophers offer many proposals for the fourth condition, no consensus has emerged [6, p. 13]. At this point, one might ask if the tasks in (1) and (2) above are the only tasks left for philosophers to deal with after Gettier. This is where I find the overall goal of this paper to be both important and interesting. By applying Hintikka s SE to the GCs, we can reveal an important but neglected approach to epistemology an approach that considers questioning as a knowledge-seeking procedure (or activity). To illustrate the significance of this kind of approach, let us compare it with the kind of approach involved in Gettier s paper. In the GCs, we find ourselves confronted with the task of trying to determine whether or not a particular epistemic agent has knowledge given certain conditions. In other words, in the GCs, our focus has been on the evaluation (or assessment) of knowledge (i.e. whether or not an epistemic agent S, for instance, knows that P). However, what we fail to consider in the GCs is the process by which epistemic agents form their beliefs or the process

5 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 29 by which they arrive at knowledge. To be sure, knowledge is important (or valuable), but the same thing might be said about the process of acquiring it. In short, applying Hintikka s SE to the GCs will allow us to see knowledge acquisition in a different light. That is, the knowledge acquisition process should be seen as a questioning process where epistemic agents deal with various pieces of information, employ different moves, and make different choices (e.g. strategies) in determining for themselves what to believe in or what they can claim to have knowledge of. 2 Gettier s Counterexamples and the Refutation of Knowledge as Justified True Belief In this section, I will discuss the GCs in relation to their alleged refutation of the tripartite definition of knowledge as JTB: (JTB Thesis): A subject S knows that P (where P is a proposition) if and only if the following conditions hold: (1) P is true, (2) S believes that P, and (3) S is justified in believing that P. For a fuller understanding of the JTB thesis above, several points need to be emphazised. First, the conditions included in the formulation above are to be understood as conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for knowledge. This means that, if the above formulation is correct, then anything that qualifies as knowledge must fulfill the three conditions specified in it. Second, the abovementioned formulation of the JTB thesis is concerned with what it means for a subject S to know a proposition P. What this means is that the JTB thesis above is concerned not with knowledge in general but only with a specific kind of knowledge: propositional knowledge. Noah Lemos defines this kind of knowledge as the knowledge of facts or true propositions [5, p. 2]. Third, and if we can grant that the second point is correct, then the accomplishments of the GCs should be limited to a particular analysis of propositional knowledge. Fourth, in the formulation of the JTB thesis above, it is important to note that we are interested in some sort of relation between a subject S and a proposition P. Lemos succinctly describes such a relation in the following: We may think of belief as a relation between a subject and a proposition. If the proposition one believes is true, then

6 30 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): one s belief is true and if the proposition one believes is false, then one s belief is false. We may also think of propositional knowledge as a relation between a subject and a proposition. More precisely, propositional knowledge is a relation between a subject and a true proposition. [5, p. 2] At this juncture, I wish to add that Lemos is not alone in viewing knowledge as a relation between a subject and a proposition. Consider what Linda Zagzebski says in the following: Knowledge is a highly valued state in which a person is in cognitive contact with reality. It is, therefore, a relation. On one side of the relation is a conscious subject, and on the other side is a portion of reality to which the knower is directly or indirectly related... Propositions are either true or false, but only true propositions link the knower with reality in the desired manner. So the object of knowledge in the sense of most interest to philosophers is usually taken to be a true proposition... In a state of knowledge the knower is related to a true proposition. The most general way of characterizing the relation between the knower and the proposition known is that she takes it to be true, and this relation is standardly called the state of belief. [9, pp (emphasis added)] The four points mentioned above are important so that we may avoid, as early as possible, some of the possible misunderstandings/misconceptions that may arise from the JTB thesis and the GCs (most especially in relation to their alleged achievements). For the purposes of this paper, they also serve another important function. They serve as guides that may help make the task of elucidating and evaluating the GCs in a more efficient and fruitful manner. In arguing that the JTB thesis is false, in the sense that the three conditions stated therein are not sufficient for knowledge, it is instructive to take note of two important points provided by Gettier before presenting the GCs. He states: I shall begin by noting two points. First, in the sense of justified in which S s being justified in believing P is a necessary condition of S s knowing that P, it is possible for a person to be justified in believing a proposition that is in fact false. Secondly, for any proposition P, if S is justified in believing P, and P entails Q, and S deduces Q from P and accepts Q

7 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 31 as a result of this deduction, then S is justified in believing Q. [1, p. 121] In his paper, Gettier provides two GCs. In GC 1, Gettier presents the case of two individuals, Smith and Jones, applying for a certain job. Gettier then asks us to grant that Smith has strong evidence for the following conjunctive proposition: (SI 1 ): Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket. (SI 1 ) above stands for Smith s Inference No. 1 and it is a label that we will attach to the conjunctive proposition in GC 1 so that we can easily discuss and refer to the said proposition later on. Gettier provides us with some of the possible pieces of evidence that Smith has for (SI 1 ): (SE 1 ): The president of the company told Smith that Jones would be selected. (SE 2 ): Smith counted the coins in Jones pocket (ten minutes ago). Take note that (SI 1 ) above is an inference made by Smith based on (SE 1 ) and (SE 2 ). (SI 1 ) entails the following: (SI 2 ): The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. To complete the first part of GC 1, Gettier asks to grant additional assumptions: (1) that Smith sees the entailment from (SI 1 ) to (SI 2 ), and (2) that Smith accepts (SI 2 ) on the grounds of (SI 1 ) for which he has strong evidence. For the first part of GC 1, Gettier concludes that Smith is justified in believing that (SI 2 ) is true. In the second part of GC 1, Gettier introduces the characteristic move involved in the GCs: the introduction of evidence (or data) that is currently unavailable to epistemic agents like Smith. Gettier asks us to consider that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket [1, p. 122]. This move completes the GC and the resulting picture is as follows: (1) (SI 2 ) is true, (2) Smith believes that (SI 2 ) is true, and (3) Smith is justified in believing that (SI 2 ) is true. If the JTB thesis is correct, we should be willing to accept that in GC 1, we have a genuine case of knowledge since the three conditions in the JTB thesis have been satisfied. However, in GC 1, we are not willing to accept that Smith

8 32 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): knows that (SI 2 ) is true for the following reasons: (1) (SI 2 ) is true in virtue of the number of coins in Smith s pocket, (2) Smith does not know the number of coins in his pocket, and (3) Smith s belief that (SI 2 ) is true is based on counting the number of coins in Jones pocket whom he falsely believes to be the man who will get the job [1, p. 122]. In GC 2, Gettier presents the case of Smith, Jones, and Smith s other friend Brown. Just like in GC 1, Gettier asks us to grant that Smith has strong evidence for the following proposition: (SI 1): Jones owns a Ford. Here are the possible pieces of evidence that Smith has for (SI 1): (SE 1): Jones has always owned a car. (SE 2): Jones car has always been a Ford. (SE 3): Jones offered Smith a ride while driving a Ford. Gettier then asks us to imagine that Smith has another friend, Brown. Smith is ignorant of Brown s whereabouts. Smith selects three-place names at random and constructs the three propositions below: (SI 2): Either Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Boston. (SI 3): Either Jones own a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona. (SI 4): Either Jones own a Ford, or Brown is in Brest-Litovsk. Each of the propositions above is entailed by (SI 1). On the assumption that Smith recognizes such entailment and then proceeds to accept (SI 2), (SI 3), and (SI 4) on the basis of (SI 1), which, as we granted, is a proposition which he has strong evidence, then Smith is therefore completely justified in believing each of these three propositions. Smith, of course, has no idea where Brown is [1, p. 123]. To complete the argument, Gettier asks us to imagine that the following conditions hold: unknown to Smith (1) Jones does not own a Ford (e.g. He is merely driving a rental car.) and (2) Brown is in Barcelona. Just like in GC 1, we find ourselves confronted with the following problem in GC 2 : There is an important sense in which we can maintain that Smith does not know that (SI 3) is true, even though (SI 3) is true, (2) Smith believes that (SI 3) is true, and (3) Smith is justified in believing that (SI 3) is true. Earlier, we stated that some philosophers consider the GCs as successful refutations of the JTB thesis. Given the clarifications that I made at the beginning of this section, I hope that I was able to provide the appropriate context for interpreting such claims. There is something

9 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 33 however that we cannot really deny: the GCs have changed the landscape of contemporary epistemology. As is well known, in the years following the publication of Gettier s famous paper, we find ourselves dealing with different versions of the GCs. In my estimation, these different versions are themselves proofs for the kind of impact that Gettier s short paper made on contemporary philosophers, especially those in the analytic tradition. In addition, the GCs have become very influential in the sense that they are generally being regarded as decisive or near-decisive tests [3, p. 23] for theories of knowledge post-gettier. Before I end this section, I would like to mention something that might have significant pedagogical import. As I have stated earlier, the GCs have been very influential to the extent that many philosophers created their own versions of it. Thanks to Zagzebski, a recipe for constructing the GCs have been made readily available for all of us: [S]tart with a case of justified (or warranted) false belief. Make the element of justification (warrant) strong enough for knowledge, but make the belief false. The falsity of the belief will not be due to any systematically describable element in the situation, for if it were, such a feature could be used in the analysis of the components of knowledge other than the true belief, and then truth would be entailed by the other components of knowledge, contrary to the hypothesis. The falsity of the belief is therefore due to some element of luck. Now emend the case by adding another element of luck, only this time an element which makes the belief true after all. The second element must be independent of the element of warrant so that the degree of warrant is unchanged. The situation might be described as one element of luck counteracting another. We now have a case in which the belief is justified (warranted) in a sense strong enough for knowledge, the belief is true, but it is not knowledge. [10, p. 69] In the foregoing passage, it is important to note that Zagzebski did not only provide us with a recipe for constructing the GCs. At the same time, she also explicitly mentions an important element involved in the various versions of the GCs: the element of luck. For Zagzebski, this element is crucial in diagnosing what went wrong in the GCs: What generates the problem for JTB, then, is that an accident of bad luck is cancelled out by an accident of good luck. The right goal is reached, but only by chance [10, p. 66]. In the following section, I will now discuss Hintikka s SE with the overall aim of applying it to the GCs.

10 34 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology Explained In section 1, I described Hintikka s SE as revolutionary for the main reason that it envisions a way of doing epistemology without the concepts of belief and knowledge. Before I discuss the rudiments of Hintikka s SE, allow me to expound first on the revolutionary aspect of Hintikka s SE. Philosophers, epistemologists in particular, have always been interested in defining concepts like knowledge and belief. In the case of knowledge, the goal, we might say, is to be able to identify the conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient for such a state. This goal, however, is theoretically misguided according to Hintikka. In addition, he considers the attempt to define the concept of knowledge in a general epistemological theory as an exercise in futility [2, p. 30]. He further adds that such a goal is not useful in practice and useless for applications [2, p. 30]. Allow me to explain the reasons behind Hintikka s seemingly harsh remarks on the attempts to define the concept of knowledge in a general epistemological theory. First of all, Hintikka maintains that the concept of knowledge belongs to applied epistemology [2, p. 30] and not to general epistemology. In my estimation, the reason for this is as follows. In a general epistemological theory, we are concerned with (1) belief -formation and (2) knowledge acquisition. For example, in a general epistemological theory, we might be interested in questions as to how, in normal (or ordinary) circumstances, the data provided (or furnished) to us by our senses usually lead us to form beliefs that are properly warranted. In an important sense, what we are concerned with in any general epistemological theory is the process by which we arrive at beliefs and knowledge. The crucial point that I wish to accentuate here is that beliefs and knowledge are arrived at, that they are themselves results of certain processes. In Hintikka s case, they are results of the process of (interrogative) inquiry. As Hintikka maintains: if knowledge is going to be the end product of interrogative inquiry, it cannot be one of the means of reaching this goal [2, p. 9]. For Hintikka, the concept of belief suffers the same fate as the concept of knowledge [2, p. 30]. To further clarify the points raised above, consider the following example. Suppose John is given a number of propositions by his colleagues about what transpired in a certain conference, which he, unfortunately, missed. Suppose that these propositions constitute an inconsistent set (i.e. the propositions cannot all be true). Suppose that John is determining for himself what to believe in (given the apparently conflicting data in his possession). How will John benefit from a definition of knowledge in this case? In the same vein, how can the concept of belief be

11 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 35 helpful here, when, in the first place, what John is trying to determine is precisely what to believe in? At this point, we might ask ourselves if the concepts of knowledge and belief are indeed unhelpful in this scenario, if these concepts are really indispensable in a general epistemological theory. As I have mentioned earlier, the crucial point to consider is that beliefs and knowledge are arrived at. In other words, they are themselves results of certain processes. In John s situation, we may say that the moment for believing (or knowing) does not yet arise (for him) since he is still in the process of inquiring. This shows that we should distinguish between the results of inquiry and the process of inquiry itself since the latter is the means by which we arrive at the former. This also shows that the role of the concept of belief and the concept of knowledge only come into the picture after the process of inquiry has been carried out. For example, if John is ready to act on a belief that he formed after the process of inquiry, then this is the point where it would matter a great deal whether or not his belief, for instance, is true (or if it is properly warranted). In my estimation, scenarios like this one, can help provide the needed context as to why Hintikka considers the concepts of belief and knowledge as not useful in practice and why they are dispensable in a general epistemological theory. Consider what he says in the following regarding the dispensability of the concept of belief in a general epistemological theory: If you are inspired by this line of thought to review the structure of the interrogative inquiry with a view to finding a role for the notion of belief there, you will not find such a role. Receiving an answer and incorporating it into one s interrogative inquiry is not the same as adopting a new belief. Acceptance is not the same thing as belief-formation... For one thing, at no stage of an interrogative inquiry are there any indications whether or not the inquirer is prepared to act on the truth of the propositions that the inquirer has at that stage accepted (and not bracketed). Hence the entire theory of knowledge acquisition can and must be developed without using the notion of belief. This notion does not play any role in an interrogative inquiry, only in the evaluation of its putative end-point. If one thinks about it, the notion of belief does not play much of a role in the methodology of science. What I am suggesting is that it should not play any more of a role in general epistemology either. [2, pp ]

12 36 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): Indeed, one might say that these are very strong words but as we shall see, Hintikka s tough stance against defining the concepts of knowledge and belief (in the traditional sense) and giving them roles in a general epistemological theory is properly motivated. First of all, for Hintikka, knowing is an achievement verb [2, p. 32]. Like knowing, he maintains that believing is also an achievement notion [2, p. 32]. These insights led him to believe that knowledge and beliefs are themselves products of inquiry [2, p. 33]. If this is correct, i.e. if knowledge and belief are themselves products of inquiry, one might therefore ask to why these concepts should play a role in the very method that helps us to secure them. I must admit that viewed in its proper context, and perhaps, with an open mind, Hintikka s insight is a powerful one. Indeed, and as the foregoing discussion shows, SE is revolutionary and philosophers should at least rethink their overall research strategies in epistemology [2, p. 35]. Another important motivation for Hintikka s SE is his critique of Platonic methodology. In the following passage, he summarizes the fundamental assumption of such a methodology and its similarity with SE: I suspect that it is only in Plato s dialogues that he was looking for a definition of knowledge. And Plato put this question (and other questions of definition) into Socrates mouth because Plato shared the widespread assumption that the definition of X gives us the blueprint that enables us to bring about X... Hence it is seen that Plato had in one important respect the same focus as we: the quest for knowledge rather than the justification of beliefs. The definition of knowledge was thought of by Plato as a means for this quest. If so, the pursuit of the definition of knowledge would indeed have been the alpha and omega of epistemology. [2, p. 35] As Hintikka states in the passage above, the similarity between his approach and Plato s is a very limited one, i.e. in terms of what they seek to achieve, both Plato and Hintikka s SE focus on the quest for knowledge rather than the justification of beliefs. It is also worth noting that in the passage above, it is plausible to maintain that Hintikka makes a distinction between Socrates and Plato s Socrates (in the dialogues). This is confirmed by the fact that Hintikka considers Socrates as a practitioner of SE [2, p. 35] whereas he rejects the fundamental assumptions of Plato s methodology. This is confirmed by what Hintikka says in the following:

13 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 37 But we do not think in that way... For us, the fact that knowledge can be considered the end product of inquiry shows on the contrary that it cannot play any role in the process of inquiry. Hence the wild goose chase of the definition of knowledge only shows that too many contemporary epistemologists are still bewitched by Plato s assumptions. This is one of the reasons why... I called contemporary academic epistemology antiquated. Maybe it is time for its practitioners to take up some more up-to-date problems. [2, p. 35 (emphasis added)] After showing the revolutionary aspect of Hintikka s SE, some of the motivations behind it, and its possible repercussions to contemporary epistemology, we will now turn to the task of identifying the elements of Hintikka s SE. In the process, we will also be able to lay bare SE s structure. It is important to note that Hintikka conceives of SE as a game [2, p. 7]. Games, of course, have players. This is the first important element of SE. In SE, Nature and Inquirer 2 are involved in a game (of inquiry). Essentially, we might say that the game consists in drawing inferences and asking questions. The second important element of SE (conceived as a game) is its aim: In SE, the inquirer seeks to determine the truth value of certain propositions in a given model. In ordinary contexts, this model represents the actual world. This means that in SE, we find the inquirer aiming to establish, for instance, a preset formula, say C, from an initial set of premise/s, T. From a methodological standpoint, this means eliminating all the other cases where C obtains (or if we prefer, eliminating all the other C-worlds (or C-scenarios)). The third important element of SE are the moves that the inquirer makes in the course of the game: deductive moves and interrogative moves [2, p. 222]. In the following, Hintikka provides an initial description of SE s elements similar to the current discussion: The basic features of a game of inquiry are clear. A play of the game begins with a number of initial premises. Whenever the presupposition of a question has been established, the inquirer may ask it. If an answer is forthcoming, it is added to the list of available premises. (This presupposes, of course, an analysis of the question-answer relation and a specification as to which answers are available in the particular game in question.) Such interrogative moves can be interspersed by logical inference moves. [2, p. 222]

14 38 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): One may of course, compare SE to the task of constructing proofs in various areas of mathematics and logic. The main difference however lies in the fact that unlike the task of constructing proofs in the aforementioned areas, in SE, it is legitimate to make interrogative moves aside from purely deductive ones. One may therefore say that in SE, we find not only an original method, but more importantly, a method that better captures what actual inquirers do when they engage in the process of inquiry. At this point, the elements of SE are not yet complete. In particular, we still need to provide an important distinction that Hintikka makes in relation to the rules of the game. This is the distinction between the definitory rules and the strategic rules of the game. For example, in the game of chess, some of the definitory rules of the game pertain to rules related to the following: (1) what counts as a legitimate move in the game (e.g. the King can only move one square in any direction, the King cannot move himself to a square where he can be checked (or captured)), and (2) what counts as winning or losing in the game (e.g. when a player s King is put into check and cannot get out of check, then that player loses the game). As the name itself suggests, definitory rules may be said to define the game. There is something distinct however with regard to how these rules define a game: they tell us which moves are permitted in the game. Definitory rules are thus, according to Hintikka, merely permissive [2, p. 45]. To highlight the difference between definitory rules and strategic rules, consider once more, the game of chess. The (definitory) rules of the game define the game of chess. The same rules, however, do not by themselves tell a player anything about what he or she (or it, if the player is a computer) should do in order to play well, to increase one s chances of reaching the goal. Such advice is what the strategic rules of a game provide to a player [2, p. 7]. Questioning, in the context of seeking knowledge, is not a simple process but at least we can agree that the kinds of questions that we ask greatly affect the kinds of answers that we get. For instance, in the process of questioning, it is not only important for us to be able to ask questions that we are permitted (or allowed) to ask. It is also important for us to be able to ask questions that can best help us achieve (or reach) our epistemic goals. Another important element of Hintikka s SE that sits well with what actual people do in actual problem solving scenarios has something to do with certain rules (or norms) regarding questions and answers: bracketing (and unbracketing). Consider what Hintikka says in the following:

15 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 39 In the typical application of interrogative inquiry for instance in the cross-examination of a witness in a court of law the inquirer cannot simply accept all answers at their face value. They can be false. Hence we must have rules allowing the rejection, or as I will call it, the bracketing of an answer, and rules governing such bracketing. [2, p. 223] In Hintikka s SE, if an answer seems dubious (to the inquirer), then it can be disregarded or bracketed. Of course, all the other answers that rely on the bracketed one must also be bracketed together with their logical consequences [2, p. 3]. The good thing about SE and the element of bracketing is that such a move (i.e. bracketing an answer) can be done temporarily. This means that the bracketed answer can be reinstated (or unbracketed) as a result of further inquiry. SE then can be thought of as a self-corrective process [2, p. 3]. At this point, one may observe that there is a wealth of substantial insights that can be drawn from the questioning procedure in Hintikka s SE with the proviso, of course, that we take the questioning procedure seriously. To complete the elements of Hintikka s SE, we have to delve deeper into what Hintikka refers to as the logic of questions and answers [2, p. 115]. Here, Hintikka introduces several other elements involved in SE: (1) presupposition, (2) desideratum of the question, and (3) the conclusiveness condition of the answer [2, pp ]. To highlight these elements, Hintikka provides an example [2, pp ]. Suppose person A asks the following question: (1) Who will win the gubernatorial race? What is the intended epistemic result of asking (1) above? If we follow Hintikka, the intended epistemic result of asking (1) above is a scenario where person A will be able to say the following truly: (2) I know who will win the gubernatorial elections. The specification of the intended epistemic result in (2) above is what Hintikka refers to as the desideratum of the question. It is what is being required from any answer that one may provide to questions like (1). Being able to identify the desideratum of a question is extremely important and it reveals to us something important as well to the logic of questions and answers: It determines the logical behavior of the question in question as well as the behavior of its answers [2, p. 115]. Suppose that in response to (1) above, person B says the following:

16 40 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): (3) The democratic candidate. According to Hintikka, given several other assumptions, (e.g. that B is honest, that B is knowledgeable about such things), then person A can say the following truly: (4) I know that the democratic candidate will win the gubernatorial race. Hintikka notes however that (4) above is not yet what person A wanted to accomplish in asking (1). It is also not the desideratum nor does it imply the desideratum. Hintikka correctly notes that the reason for this is because person A may fail to know who the democratic candidate is. For the answer to be conclusive, Hintikka maintains that the following should obtain: (5) I know who the democratic candidate is. Speaking of the content of (5) above, Hintikka says: This requirement is called the conclusiveness condition of the answer. It is the presupposition of an answer mentioned earlier [2, p. 116]. At this point, allow me to clarify something that might cause a possible misunderstanding. Why is it that we still see the word know in (2), (4), and (5) above if, according to our previous discussion, Hintikka sees no role in it in general epistemology? In other words, why is the knowledge operator still present in (2), (4), and (5)? Answering this question requires a little bit of context. As I have said in the earlier parts of this paper, SE is a method of inquiry that Hintikka developed through the years. In the previous years, Hintikka refers to it as the Interrogative Model (of inquiry). It is in his 2007 book, the main material used for this paper, that he officially calls it SE. In general, the aforementioned book is a compilation of Hintikka s works on the interrogative model (or method) of inquiry. Some of the chapters (or materials) included in that book have been published previously, and some of the chapters are new. Consistent with what we discussed in the earlier parts of this section, Hintikka maintains that the concept of knowledge does not belong to a general epistemological theory. For clarity, and so as not to miss important details, it is better to let Hintikka speak for himself: The epistemic operator needed in the logic of questions and answers is therefore not a knowledge operator in the usual sense of the term. My emphasis on this point is a penance, for I now realize that my statements in the past might have

17 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 41 conveyed to my readers a different impression. What is involved in the semantics of questions and answers is the logic of information, not the logic of knowledge. This role of the notion of information in interrogative inquiry is indeed crucial, but it does not involve epistemologists usual concept of knowledge at all. [2, p. 26] After clearing up a possible source of misunderstanding regarding the presence of the knowledge operator in the examples above, let us move on to questions and their presuppositions. In SE, the questions that the inquirer may ask are the following: (1) propositional questions and (2) wh-questions (i.e. questions involving what, who, where). Let us begin with the presupposition of propositional questions. Suppose our inquirer is asking the following: 3 (6) Is it the case that S 1 or is it the case that S 2? According to Hintikka, the presupposition of (6) is the following: (7) (S 1 S 2 ). In SE, we have to take note that we can only appropriately ask (6) in the event that (7) has been established otherwise we run the risk of not being able to ask the question in a meaningful way (i.e. helpful in the process of inquiry). This is also true in the case of wh-questions. Consider the following: (8) Who murdered Smith? In (8), the presupposition is clear, i.e. that someone murdered Smith. As stated earlier, we can only appropriately ask (8) in the event that its presupposition has been established. If we will not uphold such a rule (or norm) in the process of inquiry, what then can we hope to achieve by asking who murdered Smith if he has not been murdered to begin with? (Here, of course, we can imagine possible scenarios where Smith ends up dead but was not murdered.) In general, wh-questions, according to Hintikka, have the following presupposition: (9) ( x)s[x]. Before ending this section, let us point out a possible application of Hintikka s views on the logic of questions and answers. We are all familiar with the following textbook example of a complex question (or the fallacy of many questions):

18 42 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): (10) When did you stop beating your wife? Here are the important points to consider. First, what is the desideratum of (10)? The desideratum of (10), following Hintikka, is a specification of the time by which the respondent in (10) stopped beating his wife. Having identified the desideratum of (10), this also provides us with a range of acceptable answers to (10), i.e. answers that satisfy the conclusiveness condition. Second, the presupposition of (10) is that at some point in time, the respondent began beating his wife. Clearly, the questioner here must first establish the presupposition of (10) before he can appropriately ask (10) since if at no point in time did the respondent beat his wife, then he cannot really answer the question without getting himself into trouble. Third, questions like (10) are not fallacious in themselves since there are contexts/scenarios where asking (10) is appropriate, e.g. when the respondent is someone who in fact beats his wife. Fourth, and this is related to the third point, questions like (10) should not be assessed on their own, or in isolation. They must be assessed as parts of an entire process of inquiry. As the foregoing discussion shows, SE may also have significant implications on how we view the traditional fallacies (in informal logic and argumentation). In the next section, I will now apply Hintikka s SE to the GCs and see if applying such a method can yield important results to the problems in contemporary epistemology after Gettier s famous counterexamples. 4 Applying Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology to Gettier s Counterexamples In the foregoing discussions, we have seen the motivations, elements, and possible applications, as well as implications of Hintikka s SE to contemporary epistemology. In this section, I will make full use of the tools and concepts in SE s arsenal so that we may see for ourselves how such a method of inquiry may impact the GCs. Since the GCs have the same structure, in this section, I will only discuss GC 1. Again, here are the important elements for our discussion of GC 1 : (SE 1 ): The president of the company told Smith that Jones would be selected. (SE 2 ): Smith counted the coins in Jones pocket (ten minutes ago). (SI 1 ): Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket.

19 John Ian K. Boongaling: Hintikka s Socratic Epistemology 43 (SI 2 ): The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Take note that (SI 1 ) above is an inference made by Smith based on the evidence in his possession: (SE 1 ) and (SE 2 ). Gettier asks us to grant that Smith has strong evidence for (SI 1 ). Now, if Smith is justified in believing (SI 1 ), and (SI 1 ) entails (SI 2 ), and Smith deduces (SI 2 ) from (SI 1 ) and accepts (SI 2 ) as a result of this deduction, then Smith is justified in believing (SI 2 ). Now that the important elements are in place, let us start applying Hintikka s SE to GC 1, but first, let me point out a minor problem at the outset. Ever since I read Gettier s paper many years ago, I have always wondered why he still needed to mention that Smith has strong evidence for (SI 1 ). If this is really that important in setting up the GCs to refute the JTB thesis, I think Gettier should not be surprised if, in the final analysis, it turns out that Smith does not really know that (SI 1 ) is true. After all, having strong evidence for (SI 1 ) does not guarantee that (SI 1 ) is true or that subject S knows that (SI 1 ) is true. This is because the strength of one s evidence for a particular proposition is a matter of degree, and the same thing might also be said about (SI 2 ). Let us now move on to the task at hand. Consistent with SE s methodology and commitments, I propose the following: (1) that we view GC 1 as a game, (2) that in such a game, we will simply view (SE 1 ), (SE 2 ), (SI 1 ), and (SI 2 ) above as pieces of information within the range of our inquirer s (i.e. Smith s) attention, and (3) that the inquirer s task can be partitioned (or compartmentalized). To do (3), I will make use of frames, (F 1 ), (F 2 ), and so on. Before I proceed, allow me to briefly explain the main idea behind the employment of partitions or frames for the current purposes of this paper. On the whole, it can be said that they serve a very practical purpose: Frames or partitions are used to refer to the various parts (or stages) of the process of inquiry. This is in keeping with the idea that I mentioned earlier, i.e. that questions should not be assessed on their own or in isolation, but rather, as parts of an entire process of inquiry. Let us start with (F 1 ). In (F 1 ), Smith has, at his disposal, the following initial set of information: (SE 1 ) and (SE 2 ). Smith can do a deductive move or an interrogative move. Which move will he choose? Can Smith immediately deduce (SI 1 ) (the conclusion) from (SE 1 ) and (SE 2 )? Strictly speaking, Smith cannot do this absent several additional information such as the following: 4 (1) Everything that the company president says is true 5, and (2) Jones and Smith cannot both be hired

20 44 KRITERION Journal of Philosophy, 2017, 31(3): by the company. 6 Two things might be said about Smith s case in (F 1 ): (1) if we are going to be strict about what Smith may infer based on his set of evidence, then Smith cannot correctly infer (SI 1 ) given that several of the assumptions that we mentioned above are absent, and (2) the problems that we encounter in this case are all related to (SE 1 ) rather than (SE 2 ). But since Gettier asks us to grant that Smith has strong evidence (whatever that means) that (SI 1 ) is true, would Smith now be in a position to know that (SI 2 ) is true? This appears to be the case since: (1) (SI 1 ) entails (SI 2 ), (2) Smith deduces (SI 2 ) from (SI 1 ), and (3) Smith accepts (SI 2 ) as a result of the said deduction. Consider (F 2 ). In this frame, let us grant Gettier s request. In other words, that Smith has already established (SI 1 ). A purely deductive move on Smith s part then would entail (SI 2 ). It is, after all, a simple application of the existential generalization rule. In general, we can say that from the fact that Fa, it follows that ( x)f x. But a purely deductive move on Smith s part is precisely the kind of move that will generate the dilemma for the JTB thesis. This is made possible by the introduction of evidence (or data) that is currently unavailable to Smith: (UD 1 ): Smith himself, not Jones, will get the job. 7 (UD 2 ): Smith himself has ten coins in his pocket. Clearly, and as Gettier hoped, (SI 1 ), (SI 2 ), (UD 1 ), and (UD 2 ) will generate the dilemma for the JTB thesis. Here is where the proposal of partitioning Smith s tasks will prove to be helpful in getting things in perspective. It is important to note that (F 1 ) is a distinct task (or game) from (F 2 ). If we will choose to consider (F 1 ) and (F 2 ) as a single game, then is it not only reasonable that we should add (UD 1 ) and (UD 2 ) to the original set of information in Smith s possession? Doing so however will produce (at least) two complications for Gettier s aim: (1) (UD 1 ) conflicts with (SE 1 ) and if (UD 1 ) conflicts with (SE 1 ), it will affect (SI 1 ), which in turn, will affect (SI 2 ), and (2) as a corollary of (1), we will not be able to bring together the needed ingredients for the dilemma that Gettier directs at the JTB thesis. At this point, another important result needs to be mentioned. Earlier, I said that in order to generate the dilemma for the JTB thesis, Gettier needs (SI 1 ), (SI 2 ), (UD 1 ), and (UD 2 ). Interestingly, he has no need for (SE 1 ) and (SE 2 )! Consider (F 3 ). In this frame, we will simply adopt the important elements and assumptions in (F 1 ) and (F 2 ). The difference is that in this partition, Smith makes interrogative moves aside from purely deductive

AS PHILOSOPHY 7171 EXAMPLE RESPONSES. See a range of responses and how different levels are achieved and understand how to interpret the mark scheme.

AS PHILOSOPHY 7171 EXAMPLE RESPONSES. See a range of responses and how different levels are achieved and understand how to interpret the mark scheme. AS PHILOSOPHY 7171 EXAMPLE RESPONSES See a range of responses and how different levels are achieved and understand how to interpret the mark scheme. Version 1.0 January 2018 Please note that these responses

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Gettier: Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?

Gettier: Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Review Preliminaries Case 1 Case 2 General remarks Replies Gettier: Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Gettier: Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? March 7, 2014 Overview I Review Preliminaries Case 1

More information

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011.

Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011. Book Reviews Epistemology: A Contemporary Introduction to The Theory of Knowledge, by Robert Audi. New York: Routledge, 2011. BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 540-545] Audi s (third) introduction to the

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the

A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields. the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed extensively in the A Solution to the Gettier Problem Keota Fields Problem cases by Edmund Gettier 1 and others 2, intended to undermine the sufficiency of the three traditional conditions for knowledge, have been discussed

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo "Education is nothing more nor less than learning to think." Peter Facione In this article I review the historical evolution of principles and

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit Published online at Essays in Philosophy 7 (2005) Murphy, Page 1 of 9 REVIEW OF NEW ESSAYS ON SEMANTIC EXTERNALISM AND SELF-KNOWLEDGE, ED. SUSANA NUCCETELLI. CAMBRIDGE, MA: THE MIT PRESS. 2003. 317 PAGES.

More information

3. Knowledge and Justification

3. Knowledge and Justification THE PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE 11 3. Knowledge and Justification We have been discussing the role of skeptical arguments in epistemology and have already made some progress in thinking about reasoning and belief.

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the

Philosophical reflection about what we call knowledge has a natural starting point in the INTRODUCTION Originally published in: Peter Baumann, Epistemic Contextualism. A Defense, Oxford: Oxford University Press 2016, 1-5. https://global.oup.com/academic/product/epistemic-contextualism-9780198754312?cc=us&lang=en&#

More information

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response to this argument. Does this response succeed in saving compatibilism from the consequence argument? Why

More information

What is Game Theoretical Negation?

What is Game Theoretical Negation? Can BAŞKENT Institut d Histoire et de Philosophie des Sciences et des Techniques can@canbaskent.net www.canbaskent.net/logic Adam Mickiewicz University, Poznań April 17-19, 2013 Outlook of the Talk Classical

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism

Philosophy Epistemology. Topic 3 - Skepticism Michael Huemer on Skepticism Philosophy 3340 - Epistemology Topic 3 - Skepticism Chapter II. The Lure of Radical Skepticism 1. Mike Huemer defines radical skepticism as follows: Philosophical skeptics

More information

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 561-567 Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence Luca Tambolo Department of Philosophy, University of Trieste e-mail: l_tambolo@hotmail.com

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011

Verificationism. PHIL September 27, 2011 Verificationism PHIL 83104 September 27, 2011 1. The critique of metaphysics... 1 2. Observation statements... 2 3. In principle verifiability... 3 4. Strong verifiability... 3 4.1. Conclusive verifiability

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis James R. Beebe (University at Buffalo) International Journal for the Study of Skepticism (forthcoming) In Beebe (2011), I argued against the widespread reluctance

More information

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS SCHAFFER S DEMON by NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS Abstract: Jonathan Schaffer (2010) has summoned a new sort of demon which he calls the debasing demon that apparently threatens all of our purported

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi

Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xi 1 Knowledge and its Limits, by Timothy Williamson. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000. Pp. xi + 332. Review by Richard Foley Knowledge and Its Limits is a magnificent book that is certain to be influential

More information

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION:

A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION: Praxis, Vol. 1, No. 1, Spring 2008 ISSN 1756-1019 A PROBLEM WITH DEFINING TESTIMONY: INTENTION AND MANIFESTATION: MARK NICHOLAS WALES UNIVERSITY OF ST ANDREWS Abstract Within current epistemological work

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 10, No. 1, March 2007 HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Michael Quante In a first step, I disentangle the issues of scientism and of compatiblism

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem

Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the. Gettier Problem Quine s Naturalized Epistemology, Epistemic Normativity and the Gettier Problem Dr. Qilin Li (liqilin@gmail.com; liqilin@pku.edu.cn) The Department of Philosophy, Peking University Beiijing, P. R. China

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION

JUSTIFICATION INTRODUCTION RODERICK M. CHISHOLM THE INDISPENSABILITY JUSTIFICATION OF INTERNAL All knowledge is knowledge of someone; and ultimately no one can have any ground for his beliefs which does hot lie within his own experience.

More information

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins

Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: Nicholas Silins Transmission Failure Failure Final Version in Philosophical Studies (2005), 126: 71-102 Nicholas Silins Abstract: I set out the standard view about alleged examples of failure of transmission of warrant,

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn Philosophy Study, November 2017, Vol. 7, No. 11, 595-600 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2017.11.002 D DAVID PUBLISHING Defending Davidson s Anti-skepticism Argument: A Reply to Otavio Bueno Mohammad Reza Vaez

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

Florida State University Libraries

Florida State University Libraries Florida State University Libraries Electronic Theses, Treatises and Dissertations The Graduate School 2011 A Framework for Understanding Naturalized Epistemology Amirah Albahri Follow this and additional

More information

McDowell and the New Evil Genius

McDowell and the New Evil Genius 1 McDowell and the New Evil Genius Ram Neta and Duncan Pritchard 0. Many epistemologists both internalists and externalists regard the New Evil Genius Problem (Lehrer & Cohen 1983) as constituting an important

More information

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology

The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Oxford Scholarship Online You are looking at 1-10 of 21 items for: booktitle : handbook phimet The Oxford Handbook of Epistemology Paul K. Moser (ed.) Item type: book DOI: 10.1093/0195130057.001.0001 This

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Lasersohn Comments on Lasersohn John MacFarlane September 29, 2006 I ll begin by saying a bit about Lasersohn s framework for relativist semantics and how it compares to the one I ve been recommending. I ll focus

More information

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments

ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments ISSA Proceedings 1998 Wilson On Circular Arguments 1. Introduction In his paper Circular Arguments Kent Wilson (1988) argues that any account of the fallacy of begging the question based on epistemic conditions

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY by ANTHONY BRUECKNER AND CHRISTOPHER T. BUFORD Abstract: We consider one of Eric Olson s chief arguments for animalism about personal identity: the view that we are each

More information

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology

Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology 1. Introduction Ryan C. Smith Philosophy 125W- Final Paper April 24, 2010 Foundationalism Vs. Skepticism: The Greater Philosophical Ideology Throughout this paper, the goal will be to accomplish three

More information

Three Modified Versions of Nozick s Theory of Knowledge

Three Modified Versions of Nozick s Theory of Knowledge 金沢星稜大学論集第 51 巻第 1 号平成 29 年 9 月 89 Research Note Three Modified Versions of Nozick s Theory of Knowledge Shohei Edamura 1. Introduction Since Edmund Gettier wrote his influential paper Is Justified True

More information

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to Lucky to Know? The Problem Epistemology is the field of philosophy interested in principled answers to questions regarding the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take

More information

An Interview with Jaakko Hintikka

An Interview with Jaakko Hintikka 1) The new biogenetic researches, for example cloning, present once again the ticklish question of the relationship between science and ethics. What is your opinion about this? And what part, do you think,

More information

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe. Overview Philosophy & logic 1.2 What is philosophy? 1.3 nature of philosophy Why philosophy Rules of engagement Punctuality and regularity is of the essence You should be active in class It is good to

More information

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions. Replies to Michael Kremer Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions. First, is existence really not essential by

More information

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise Michael Blome-Tillmann University College, Oxford Abstract. Epistemic contextualism (EC) is primarily a semantic view, viz. the view that knowledge -ascriptions

More information

What is a counterexample?

What is a counterexample? Lorentz Center 4 March 2013 What is a counterexample? Jan-Willem Romeijn, University of Groningen Joint work with Eric Pacuit, University of Maryland Paul Pedersen, Max Plank Institute Berlin Co-authors

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy

From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy From the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Epistemology Peter D. Klein Philosophical Concept Epistemology is one of the core areas of philosophy. It is concerned with the nature, sources and limits

More information

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Copyright 2004 Abraham Meidan All rights reserved. Universal Publishers Boca Raton, Florida USA 2004 ISBN: 1-58112-504-6 www.universal-publishers.com

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION FILOZOFIA Roč. 66, 2011, č. 4 STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION AHMAD REZA HEMMATI MOGHADDAM, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (IPM), School of Analytic Philosophy,

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism

Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism Klein on the Unity of Cartesian and Contemporary Skepticism Olsson, Erik J Published in: Philosophy and Phenomenological Research DOI: 10.1111/j.1933-1592.2008.00155.x 2008 Link to publication Citation

More information

Class 13 - Epistemic Relativism Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich, Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions

Class 13 - Epistemic Relativism Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich, Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions 2 3 Philosophy 2 3 : Intuitions and Philosophy Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class 13 - Epistemic Relativism Weinberg, Nichols, and Stich, Normativity and Epistemic Intuitions I. Divergent

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett

MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX. Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett MULTI-PEER DISAGREEMENT AND THE PREFACE PARADOX Kenneth Boyce and Allan Hazlett Abstract The problem of multi-peer disagreement concerns the reasonable response to a situation in which you believe P1 Pn

More information

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR CRÍTICA, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. XXXI, No. 91 (abril 1999): 91 103 SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR MAX KÖLBEL Doctoral Programme in Cognitive Science Universität Hamburg In his paper

More information

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents UNIT 1 SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY Contents 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Research in Philosophy 1.3 Philosophical Method 1.4 Tools of Research 1.5 Choosing a Topic 1.1 INTRODUCTION Everyone who seeks knowledge

More information

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE By RICHARD FELDMAN Closure principles for epistemic justification hold that one is justified in believing the logical consequences, perhaps of a specified sort,

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 1: A Scrutable World David Chalmers Plan *1. Laplace s demon 2. Primitive concepts and the Aufbau 3. Problems for the Aufbau 4. The scrutability base 5. Applications Laplace

More information

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows:

Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore. I. Moorean Methodology. In A Proof of the External World, Moore argues as follows: Does the Skeptic Win? A Defense of Moore I argue that Moore s famous response to the skeptic should be accepted even by the skeptic. My paper has three main stages. First, I will briefly outline G. E.

More information

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005):

Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism. Tim Black and Peter Murphy. In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005): Avoiding the Dogmatic Commitments of Contextualism Tim Black and Peter Murphy In Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005): 165-182 According to the thesis of epistemological contextualism, the truth conditions

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) Thomas W. Polger, University of Cincinnati 1. Introduction David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work

More information

THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS

THE QUESTION OF UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY? IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS THE QUESTION OF "UNIVERSALITY VERSUS PARTICULARITY?" IN THE LIGHT OF EPISTEMOLOGICAL KNOWLEDGE OF NORMS Ioanna Kuçuradi Universality and particularity are two relative terms. Some would prefer to call

More information

Evidential arguments from evil

Evidential arguments from evil International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48: 1 10, 2000. 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 1 Evidential arguments from evil RICHARD OTTE University of California at Santa

More information

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE A Paper Presented to Dr. Douglas Blount Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for PHREL 4313 by Billy Marsh October 20,

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information