6: DEDUCTIVE LOGIC. Chapter 17: Deductive validity and invalidity Ben Bayer Drafted April 25, 2010 Revised August 23, 2010

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "6: DEDUCTIVE LOGIC. Chapter 17: Deductive validity and invalidity Ben Bayer Drafted April 25, 2010 Revised August 23, 2010"

Transcription

1 6: DEDUCTIVE LOGIC Chapter 17: Deductive validity and invalidity Ben Bayer Drafted April 25, 2010 Revised August 23, 2010 Deduction vs. induction reviewed In chapter 14, we spent a fair amount of time introducing the distinction between inductive and deductive reasoning. To explain the distinction, we made an analogy to the difference between the packing and unpacking of luggage. Induction is the process by which we pack together observations in a retainable cognitive form that is usable in the future. Deduction is the process of unpacking that knowledge, of using it in application to specific situations. Previously, we contrasted induction from deduction in order to focus on induction, the source of generalization and scientific knowledge. Now that we have already dwelled on that contrast, we will briefly dwell on some very basic principles of deductive reasoning in this, the last section of our book. We will discuss only the most basic principles of deduction, because many logicians have written a great deal explaining these principles elsewhere. From ancient Greece, where geometers perfected the first formal deductive systems and where Aristotle first reflected on the principles that governed these systems and human reasoning more generally to the Middle Ages, when philosophers extended and perfected Aristotle s logic to the late 19 th and early 20 th century, when mathematicians and philosophers developed a new system that supplemented, and in some cases, may have highlighted limitations of Aristotle s system we can see that logicians understand the rules of deductive logic with far greater systematicity and precision than they do the rules of inductive logic. If you want to learn more about the rules of deductive logic, there are whole other texts and courses available on this subject alone. 1

2 Recall that induction is defined as the form of inference that generates conclusions taken to be wider (more universal) in content than the observations contained in the premises, whereas deduction is the form of inference in which the conclusion states no more content than that stated in the premises (and is necessitated by them). Part of the reason deduction is understood so well is that it is confined to unpacking the content of the stated premises. Deduction works with a finite number of premises which contain a finite amount of information; as a consequence, there are only so many implications one can derive from them. The rules of deductive reasoning help to delimit precisely which implications one can derive, and how. This is in contrast to inductive inference, which works with an entire body of observations and background knowledge as its starting point, not all of which can easily be summarized in the form of stated premises. This makes it much harder to know what conclusions follow from the starting points of induction: it is, after all, very hard even to specify these starting points. None of this should be taken as disparaging the usefulness of deduction. The fact that its rules are well-understood does not mean that they are always easy to apply or that the conclusions of deductive arguments are obvious. Neither is true. Recall, for example, the deduction we used to solve the riddle in chapter 14 ( Brothers and sisters have I none, but this man s father is my father s son ). And though we cannot possible study the content or even all of the method used to perform them, we should mention just a few examples of sophisticated deductive argumentation that have helped scientists uncover surprising new facts about the world. Induction may be the indispensible fuel of human reasoning power, but deduction is where the rubber hits the road. Way back in chapter 1 when we were discussing the ancient evidence for the conclusion that the Earth is a sphere, we mentioned that the Greeks were even able to infer the size of the Earth from (literally) mundane observations to within a small margin of error of the correct conclusion. Their argument was deductive, beginning with premises taken from trigonometry and observations of measured quantities. Here is Eratosthenes proof of the Earth s circumference: 2

3 1. The angle of the shadow at noon at Alexandria is Alternating interior angles are equal. 3. Therefore, the angle between Alexandria and Syene is The distance from Alexandria to Syene is 500 miles. 5. But (Circumference of earth/500 miles)=360 / Therefore Circumference of earth = 25,000 miles. 7. But Circumference/π = Diameter, 25,000/3.14 = 8,000 miles. 8. Therefore, the diameter of earth is 8,000 miles. Using knowledge of the size of the Earth, and a related argument for the size of the moon, the Greeks were even able to determine the distance to the sun: 1. The angle between the sun and the moon during a half moon is Cos 87 = moon distance/sun distance 3. Sun distance/moon distance = 1/cos 87 = Therefore, the sun s distance from the earth is 19 times its distance to the moon. Through mere connections of deductive logic, the Greeks were able to travel millions of miles with their minds. A final example of the amazing power of deductive reasoning is so complicated that we cannot even represent the argument in symbolic terms here that the reader is likely to understand. Using fundamental laws of electricity and magnetism that he himself had formulated, James Clerk Maxwell, famously constructed a proof in 1864 showing that a change in a electrical field would induce a corresponding change in the magnetic field. But it was already known that the reverse was true, that a changing magnetic field would cause a change in the electrical field. It followed logically that the first would cause the second, which would in turn cause the first, and then the second, etc. Maxwell was predicting the existence of what we now call electromagnetic waves. He even predicted their speed, which corresponded closely to the known speed of light: Maxwell had shown that light was an electromagnetic wave. His discovery was the basis of countless innovations in 20 th century electronics. 3

4 We cannot hope even to begin to teach you how to be an Eratosthenes or a Maxwell. The deductions you will learn to perform will be comparable simple. But you have to walk with simple syllogisms before you can run with whole chains of sophisticated deduction. Picture credit 1: Two requirements of reasoning in general, and of deduction in particular Before we describe some basic rules of deductive reasoning and methods of evaluating the quality of deductive argument, it is worth reviewing the most general requirements of reasoning of any kind. Recall our three basic rules: 1. The premises of the argument must be known and known better than the conclusion (they must be well-evidenced). 2. The premises must be relevant to the conclusion (they must be likely to establish the conclusion as true). 3. The argument s premises must contain all of the known relevant evidence. The first requirement applies to deductive arguments no differently than it applies to inductive ones. Premises can be shown to be wellevidenced if they are either derived from some form of direct awareness, or from some further premises that are themselves derived from a form of direct awareness. Either way, the premises must be ultimately derived from some form of direct knowledge, like sensory observation. We discussed this requirement in more detail in chapter 3. Regarding the second requirement, in good non-deductive arguments premises are relevant to their conclusion when they are such that if they are true, the conclusion is at the very least highly likely to be true. (Some might suggest that inductive arguments can still establish conclusions that are made necessary not only by stated premises, but by the totality of unstated background knowledge.) The relevance relationship between the premises and conclusion of a good deductive argument, on the other hand, is of such a special type of relevance that if these premises are true, the conclusion absolutely must be true, and this follows from nothing more than its premises. We will explore this special type of relevance in the next section: it is called validity. 4

5 Back in chapter 7, we also discussed how the third requirement applies differently to inductive and deductive reasoning. The whole function of deductive inference is just to unpack the implications of some stated premises. If a given conclusion is not an implication of these premises, the argument containing the conclusion is simply not valid. If the conclusion is an implication of these premises, the argument containing it is valid, and no assessment of other relevant evidence is needed to see this: those premises are all the relevant evidence there is. This is not the case in inductive inference, which can establish conclusions as at least somewhat probable independently of other considerations, and the probability of an inductive conclusion can change for better or worse as more evidence is brought in. All of this, however, is dependent on understanding the nature of the difference between deductive and inductive relevance. We will now focus exclusively on the topic of deductive relevance, i.e., validity. As a preliminary introduction to the uniqueness of deductive relevance, consider the following two arguments. Which one is inductive, and which is deductive? Is there any difference between the kinds of relevance you see in each? All rain is from condensed cloud vapor. Rain is falling in New Orleans. Therefore, cloud vapor is condensing in New Orleans. We know that water evaporates when it is hot. We know that water condenses on cool surfaces. We see clouds present whenever it rains. All rain is from condensed cloud vapor. Deductive validity, soundness, and invalidity The name given to deductive relevance is validity. An argument is said to be deductively valid if its conclusion cannot be false if its premises are assumed to be true; i.e., it is such that if its premises are true, its conclusion must be true. A key part of this definition is that validity is a fact about arguments conditioned on the assumption that their premises are true. It is purely an assessment of the relevance of these premises, independent of whether or not they are really true. Judging validity involves a kind of pretense: we pretend that the premises are true, and see what follows even if we know they are not. Validity, then, is distinct from soundness: an argument is said to be deductively sound just in case its conclusion follows validly from premises, 5

6 when all these premises are known to be true. Every sound argument is valid, but not every valid argument is sound. An argument can be valid even if its premises are known to be false: what makes it valid is that it is such that if the premises were true, they conclusion would be true. We need examples to bring out this distinction. Our favorite stock example of a deductively valid argument is also an example of a deductively sound argument: All men are mortal. Socrates was a man. Therefore, Socrates was mortal As we demonstrated in chapter 14 through the use of simple circle diagrams, if these premises are true, the conclusion has to be true. What makes this argument sound in addition to valid is that the relationship between the premises and conclusion is not merely hypothetical: we do accept that these premises are true, and hence that the conclusion is, as well. Contrast the Socrates argument with the following pair of valid but unsound arguments: All men are immortal. Fido is a man. Therefore, Fido is immortal. All dogs are philosophers. Socrates is a dog. Therefore, Socrates is a philosopher. And surely this instinct of the dog is very charming; your dog is a true philosopher. Why? Why, because he distinguishes the face of a friend and of an enemy only by the criterion of knowing and not knowing. And must not an animal be a lover of learning who determines what he likes and dislikes by the test of knowledge and ignorance? Most assuredly. And is not the love of learning the love of wisdom, which is philosophy? --Plato, Republic, Book II Suppose that Fido, per his name, really is a dog. In that case, the first argument scores a trifecta of unsoundness: each and every statement, both premises and the conclusion, is false. But the argument is valid. If all men were immortal and Fido were a man, he would be immortal. The same can be said for the second example, though in this case, we have two false premises in effect cancelling each other out and yielding a true conclusion. You should think of deductive validity as a testing a purely hypothetical relationship between premises and conclusion. When we evaluate validity, we are, in a way, performing a test in our imagination. But it is a test in the imagination that is constrained rigorously by our premises 6

7 and our understanding of the meaning of any statements of the form S is P : if All S is P, and Fido is an S, then Fido must also be a P. Deductive validity involves a special kind of relevance because its relevance is based strictly on the form of its premises and conclusion. We will say more about what this means shortly. If you really understand the concept of deductive relevance, i.e. of validity, you will appreciate why the following is a fairly clear example of an invalid argument: All men are mortal. All mice are mortal. Therefore, all mice are men. We know both of the premises to be true. But the conclusion is quite obviously false. Recall: a valid argument is one whose conclusion cannot be false if its premises are assumed to be true. In this case, not only can we assume the premises to be true, we know they are! So we know that the truth of this conclusion could not follow from assuming the truth of these premises, because we know the conclusion is false, even as we know that the premises are true. Examples like this, in which we know the premises are true but the conclusion false, are case studies of invalid arguments. Knowing that these are the most obvious case studies proves to be useful for evaluating arguments as invalid even when we do not know whether their premises and conclusion are true or false. If you really, really understand the concept of validity, you will even be able to discern why the following are examples of invalid arguments: All people are animals. All animals move. Therefore, all philosophers are people. Picture credit 2: 2RKpV2ORj- Zwhttp://picasaweb.google.com/lh/photo/zXenfB_2 m42rkpv2orj-zw This example is tricky to someone who is new to the rules of validity, because each premise is true and so is the conclusion. Yet it is invalid. The premises All people are animals and All animals move says something about animals, and we might think this is a common factor that could yield some new conclusion. But the conclusion, All philosophers are people, is one which, 7

8 though we know to be true, seems to have nothing at all to do with the premises. The premises, after all, said nothing about philosophers. If you understand the concept of deductive validity, you should now clearly see why validity is entirely a matter of the relationship of relevance between the premises and the conclusion. In this argument, all of the premises are true, as is the conclusion, but the premises do not make the conclusion true. Nothing links the premises to the conclusion. As a final test of your understanding of validity, consider a second example: All human beings are mortal All philosophers are mortal. Therefore, all philosophers are human beings Unlike the previous example, there is no new concept that appears in the conclusion that makes it obviously irrelevant to draw. The conclusion mentions something about philosophers and their relationship to people, and both were mentioned in the premises. Making things trickier still is the fact that both premises are true, as is the conclusion. But if you remember that not every set of true premises is related to every true conclusion, you should remember that these true premises do not necessarily make this true conclusion true. We could imagine a situation in which, though the premises are true, the conclusion is false. Suppose that all people are mortal, as are all philosophers. But it turns out that some philosophers are mortal Martians. In this case, it would not follow that all philosophers are people. Even though the present conclusion is true given the facts we know about philosophers, we would not be averse to changing it if we discovered new kinds of philosophers in the universe, even if we continued to accept the premises as true. If, in order for an argument to be sound, it must be both valid and in possession of true premises, it follows that every invalid argument is also unsound (though some unsound arguments are valid). All of the possible combinations are summarized on the following table: 8

9 As you can see, no special combination of premise types (true or false) will make an argument valid. Any of the four possible combinations in the first column can be invalid. Of the valid arguments, only one possibility allows the argument to be sound: the case in which the argument has true premises and a true conclusion. Of course there are examples of valid arguments where this does not hold: valid arguments can have false premises with a true conclusion, or false premises with a false conclusion. What makes them valid is that if their premises were true, their conclusion would be as well. And all of the invalid arguments are of course also unsound: to be sound an argument must be valid as well. With these distinctions in mind, can you tell which if any of the following arguments are valid? And which of the valid ones are also sound? All U.S. senators are federal representatives. All federal representatives work in Washington, DC. Therefore, all U.S. senators work in Washington, DC Some politicians are promise-makers. Some promise-makers are sincere. Therefore, some politicians are ambitious. Some politicians are liars. Some liars are killers. Some politicians are killers. Some politicians are truth-tellers. Some truth-tellers are fools. Therefore, some politicians are fools. 9

10 The counterexample method of testing validity How easy was it for you to tell that any of the above arguments were invalid? It is particularly hard to tell in cases where you think that the premises and the conclusion are true. How can you tell whether or not the true premises make the conclusion true? In the last section, we mentioned a way of evaluating this by trying to think of a situation in which the premises could be true but the conclusion false. If we think of the way in which true premises make conclusions true as analogous to a kind of cause and effect relationship, then when are looking for an example in which the premises might be true but the conclusion false, we are doing something like applying Mill s negative method of difference for refuting causal claims. We re looking for a case in which the alleged cause (the truth of the premises) is present, but the effect (the truth of the conclusion) is absent. Any time we find an argument with true premises and a false conclusion, we know it cannot be valid for this reason. This is reflected by the one block missing examples in our table of different possible argument types: What if we simply can t think of a situation in which the given premises are true, but the conclusion false? What if we don t even know when the premises of a given argument are true and its conclusion false? It can be difficult to know how to do either, and our failure to do either doesn t show that the argument is valid; we might simply lack imagination. We need a more systematic method of finding counterexamples, so that if we fail even 10

11 after applying this method, it is at least more likely that what we have in the end is a valid argument. We need a method that helps us transform arguments into equivalents for which counterexamples are easier to find. There is such a method that works with some understanding of what it is it about a set of premises that makes a conclusion true. Consider a case where true premises obviously do make the conclusion true. All men are mortal All mortals are living All men are living. What makes these premises guarantee the truth of the conclusion? It is something about the abstract pattern of the argument. Notice in this case that there are terms in the premises that also appear in the conclusion ( men.... living ). A third term ( mortal ) is common to both premises, but missing from the conclusion. And there is something about the order in which these terms appear that is important. After all, the following argument with the exact same terms would clearly not be valid: All men are mortal All living things are mortal. All living things are men. The only difference between this argument and the previous is that the terms in the second premise and the conclusion have been reversed. The second premise is still true, but the conclusion is false. So there is something about the abstract pattern of the terms in the premises and conclusion that makes one argument valid and the other invalid. So what happens when we turn to an entirely different argument, composed of different terms, but possessing the same abstract pattern, the same form? An argument of exactly the same form would also have the same deductive validity and, we presume, because it has the same form. For example: All vampires are immortal. All immortals are undead. All vampires are undead. 11

12 What exactly do we mean by the form of an argument? The form of a statue, for example, is its shape, as opposed to its matter or stuff. We can make copies of a statue using many different materials marble, bronze, plaster, etc. but they are copies of that statue as long as they are of the same shape. When we speak of the form of an argument, we mean the shape of the statements composing it, the order in which various terms appear in premises, and the order of the same terms in the conclusion. If it is the form of an argument that allows its premises to determine the truth of its conclusion of a deductive argument, perhaps Picture credit 4: having the wrong form could account for the invalidity of deductive arguments. Let s look at an example of an argument that we can agree is obviously invalid, with premises that are obviously true and a conclusion that is obviously false: All men are mortal. All mice are mortal. All mice are men. If it is an argument s form that allows the truth of the premises to guarantee the truth of its conclusion, what is the form of the argument above? We represent it this way: All A are B. All C are B. All C are A. Picture credit 3: davenger/ /sizes/m/in/ photostream/ We know that an argument of this form can include true premises and a false conclusion, because the All mice or men argument is of this form. So if any other argument has this same form, we know that nothing about its form guarantees that true premises must be accompanied by true conclusions. And since form is the source of deductive validity, missing the right form means the argument cannot be valid. Picture credit 5: y7171/ / 12

13 Suppose, for example, that we were asked to evaluate the validity of these arguments: All whales are cetaceans. All dolphins are cetaceans. All dolphins are whales. All derivatives are options. All futures are options. All futures are derivatives. All naiads are fairies. All dryads are fairies. All dryads are naiads. Notice that each of these arguments has the same bad form as the All mice are men argument. If the abstract form of that argument is consistent with having true premises and a false conclusion, we know that nothing about the form of these arguments will guarantee a true conclusion. So even if we don t know what a cetacean is, what the difference between a derivative and an option is, or the meaning of any of the terms in the last argument, we can still know without knowing whether any of these statements are true or false that these arguments simply lack the necessary form to be valid. They lack the necessary form, because they are all instances of the form All A are B, All C are B; Therefore all C are A. These observations help give us a recipe for finding counterexamples that prove the invalidity of many arguments. We know that if an argument has true premises and a false conclusion, it cannot be valid. But if the form of another argument would permit the substitution of the obviously invalid argument, we know that that the other argument itself does not have the form that it needs to be valid. Here, then, are the steps by which this counterexample method works. 1. First, we break the argument down into premises and conclusions. Suppose we want to test the following argument for validity: Some traders are not brokers. All buyers are traders. Some buyers are not brokers. 13

14 2. Next, we find the abstract form of the argument, as follows: Some A are not B. All C are A. Some C are not B. 3. Finally, we find substitution instances for each of these abstract variables that amount to an argument in which the premises are obviously true, and the conclusion obviously false. Here is one such example: Some animals are not mammals. All dogs are animals. Some dogs are not mammals. It is useful, for the purposes of the counterexamples involved in this method, to work with concepts like animals, mammals, and dogs, for which we already have clear knowledge of the category relationships in question. We know that it is obviously true that animals are not mammals if we know of fish and birds. We know it is true that all dogs are animals (none are plants). And yet, we know that the conclusion here is false: it s false that some dogs are not mammals. Does someone think they are reptiles or amphibians? Since the argument about traders, brokers, and buyers has the form that permits this obviously invalid argument, nothing about the form of the traders/brokers/buyers argument supports its validity. We can conclude it is invalid. This three-step method helps clarify the concept of validity for us, especially insofar as it may have been difficult to detect when arguments containing actually true premises and actually true conclusions could still fail to be valid. Here we return to the example of this type of argument mentioned before: Some politicians are truth-tellers. Some truth-tellers are fools. Therefore, some politicians are fools. The abstract form of this argument is as follows: 14

15 Some As are Bs. Some Bs are Cs. Therefore, some As are Cs. But there are fairly straightforward counterexamples (and probably many more) to any argument utilizing this pattern: Some friends are unhappy people. Some unhappy people are enemies. Therefore, some friends are enemies. Consider a final analogy to help explain how an argument s form helps determine its validity. Arguments are not the only things that have a form. Anything with a physical shape also has a form (as our earlier example of statues brought out). Sometimes in matters outside of logic, the physical form or shape of a thing can also determine whether or not it has a relevant property or power to get something done. To take a somewhat curious example, the shape of a thing can determine what kinds of spaces it can fit through. Suppose we have a triangular hole of a specific size cut into a wall. Non-triangular objects greater than a specific surface area could not fit through the hole, because of its shape. Suppose we use a bundt cake mold to create circular objects of a larger size. Well then the circular form of the cake mold does not make objects of the right size to fit through this triangular hole: 15

16 But suppose that we can fill that cake mold with many different substances. We can fill it with water and freeze it, or with concrete mix, or with Jello. Many of these substances will yield cakes that will be too solid to fit through the hole. Using Jello, the size and shape will still be wrong to fit easily through the hole, but perhaps the right kind of squeezing can still accomplish the task. The Jello example is analogous to the examples above in which argument s form is invalid even if the premises and conclusion are true. In these cases, there is nothing about the form of the argument that transmits truth from the premises to the conclusion. Still, the conclusion is true, but it s true as a matter of luck. Likewise, in this example, it s not the form of the cake as supplied by the bundt that allows it to pass through the triangular hole. All things being equal it wouldn t have so passed. But by chance, the material in this case is squishy enough that it can pass through after all, just like a conclusion might have been true by chance. Sadly, this doesn t mean that testing validity is always a piece of cake. Here, then, for final practice, is another example of an argument that may be tested for validity using this counterexample method: Some philosophers are not poets, for some singers are not poets (P) and some poets (P) that are not singers (S) are philosophers. Which of the following best captures the form of this argument? 1. Some S are not P. Some P are F. Some F are not P. 2. Some P that are not S are F. Some P are not F. Some S are not P. 3. Some S are not P. Some P that are not S are F. Some F are not P. 4. Some F are not P. Some S are not P. Some P that are not S are F. 5. Some F are not P. Some S are not P. All P that are not S are F. 16

17 If you look carefully, you will see that it has to be 3. So which of the following substitutions gives us a counterexample, a case in which we have two true premises and a false conclusion which shows that the argument as presented is not valid?: 1. P = mammals, S = animals, F = dogs. 2. P = cats, S = trees, F = animals. 3. P = mammals, S = cats, F = animals. 4. P = animals, S = trees, F = cats. 5. P = fish, S = dogs, F = mammals. 17

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity

Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics. Critical Thinking Lecture 1. Background Material for the Exercise on Validity Philosophy 1100: Introduction to Ethics Critical Thinking Lecture 1 Background Material for the Exercise on Validity Reasons, Arguments, and the Concept of Validity 1. The Concept of Validity Consider

More information

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv)

A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary. Jason Zarri. 1. An Easy $10.00? a 3 c 2. (i) (ii) (iii) (iv) A Primer on Logic Part 1: Preliminaries and Vocabulary Jason Zarri 1. An Easy $10.00? Suppose someone were to bet you $10.00 that you would fail a seemingly simple test of your reasoning skills. Feeling

More information

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe.

Intro Viewed from a certain angle, philosophy is about what, if anything, we ought to believe. Overview Philosophy & logic 1.2 What is philosophy? 1.3 nature of philosophy Why philosophy Rules of engagement Punctuality and regularity is of the essence You should be active in class It is good to

More information

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic

Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Logic Appendix: More detailed instruction in deductive logic Standardizing and Diagramming In Reason and the Balance we have taken the approach of using a simple outline to standardize short arguments,

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments.

Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion TOPIC: Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments. TOPIC: Lecture 4.2 Aquinas Phil Religion Aquinas Cosmological Arguments for the existence of God. Critiques of Aquinas arguments. KEY TERMS/ GOALS: Cosmological argument. The problem of Infinite Regress.

More information

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff!

Logic Book Part 1! by Skylar Ruloff! Logic Book Part 1 by Skylar Ruloff Contents Introduction 3 I Validity and Soundness 4 II Argument Forms 10 III Counterexamples and Categorical Statements 15 IV Strength and Cogency 21 2 Introduction This

More information

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity

1.5. Argument Forms: Proving Invalidity 18. If inflation heats up, then interest rates will rise. If interest rates rise, then bond prices will decline. Therefore, if inflation heats up, then bond prices will decline. 19. Statistics reveal that

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness

MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC. 1. Logic is the science of A) Thought. B) Beauty. C) Mind. D) Goodness MCQ IN TRADITIONAL LOGIC FOR PRIVATE REGISTRATION TO BA PHILOSOPHY PROGRAMME 1. Logic is the science of-----------. A) Thought B) Beauty C) Mind D) Goodness 2. Aesthetics is the science of ------------.

More information

Unit 4. Reason as a way of knowing. Tuesday, March 4, 14

Unit 4. Reason as a way of knowing. Tuesday, March 4, 14 Unit 4 Reason as a way of knowing I. Reasoning At its core, reasoning is using what is known as building blocks to create new knowledge I use the words logic and reasoning interchangeably. Technically,

More information

Basic Concepts and Skills!

Basic Concepts and Skills! Basic Concepts and Skills! Critical Thinking tests rationales,! i.e., reasons connected to conclusions by justifying or explaining principles! Why do CT?! Answer: Opinions without logical or evidential

More information

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism

Unit. Categorical Syllogism. What is a syllogism? Types of Syllogism Unit 8 Categorical yllogism What is a syllogism? Inference or reasoning is the process of passing from one or more propositions to another with some justification. This inference when expressed in language

More information

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms

A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 1 A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 5 A Brief Introduction to Key Terms 1.1 Arguments Arguments crop up in conversations, political debates, lectures, editorials, comic strips, novels, television programs,

More information

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Introduction Symbolic Logic An Introduction to Symbolic Logic Copyright 2006 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved CONTENTS Chapter One Sentential Logic with 'if' and 'not' 1 SYMBOLIC NOTATION 2 MEANINGS OF THE SYMBOLIC NOTATION

More information

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises

Deduction. Of all the modes of reasoning, deductive arguments have the strongest relationship between the premises Deduction Deductive arguments, deduction, deductive logic all means the same thing. They are different ways of referring to the same style of reasoning Deduction is just one mode of reasoning, but it is

More information

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo "Education is nothing more nor less than learning to think." Peter Facione In this article I review the historical evolution of principles and

More information

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1 BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1. What is Logic?... 2 2. Inferences and Arguments... 2 3. Deductive Logic versus Inductive Logic... 5 4. Statements versus Propositions... 6 5. Form versus Content... 7 6. Preliminary

More information

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments

Critical Thinking 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments 5.7 Validity in inductive, conductive, and abductive arguments REMEMBER as explained in an earlier section formal language is used for expressing relations in abstract form, based on clear and unambiguous

More information

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1

The Appeal to Reason. Introductory Logic pt. 1 The Appeal to Reason Introductory Logic pt. 1 Argument vs. Argumentation The difference is important as demonstrated by these famous philosophers. The Origins of Logic: (highlights) Aristotle (385-322

More information

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2016 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 06 06 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 06 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic

Deduction by Daniel Bonevac. Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic Deduction by Daniel Bonevac Chapter 1 Basic Concepts of Logic Logic defined Logic is the study of correct reasoning. Informal logic is the attempt to represent correct reasoning using the natural language

More information

A short introduction to formal logic

A short introduction to formal logic A short introduction to formal logic Dan Hicks v0.3.2, July 20, 2012 Thanks to Tim Pawl and my Fall 2011 Intro to Philosophy students for feedback on earlier versions. My approach to teaching logic has

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism Issues: I. Problem of Induction II. Popper s rejection of induction III. Salmon s critique of deductivism 2 I. The problem of induction 1. Inductive vs.

More information

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC

BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC BASIC CONCEPTS OF LOGIC 1. What is Logic?...2 2. Inferences and Arguments...2 3. Deductive Logic versus Inductive Logic...5 4. Statements versus Propositions...6 5. Form versus Content...7 6. Preliminary

More information

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS

1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. B. DEDUCTIVE AND INDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS I. LOGIC AND ARGUMENTATION 1 A. LOGIC 1. To arrive at the truth we have to reason correctly. 2. Logic is the study of correct reasoning. 3. It doesn t attempt to determine how people in fact reason. 4.

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions

5.3 The Four Kinds of Categorical Propositions M05_COI1396_13_E_C05.QXD 11/13/07 8:39 AM age 182 182 CHATER 5 Categorical ropositions Categorical propositions are the fundamental elements, the building blocks of argument, in the classical account of

More information

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT

HOW TO ANALYZE AN ARGUMENT What does it mean to provide an argument for a statement? To provide an argument for a statement is an activity we carry out both in our everyday lives and within the sciences. We provide arguments for

More information

16. Universal derivation

16. Universal derivation 16. Universal derivation 16.1 An example: the Meno In one of Plato s dialogues, the Meno, Socrates uses questions and prompts to direct a young slave boy to see that if we want to make a square that has

More information

PRACTICE EXAM The state of Israel was in a state of mourning today because of the assassination of Yztzak Rabin.

PRACTICE EXAM The state of Israel was in a state of mourning today because of the assassination of Yztzak Rabin. PRACTICE EXAM 1 I. Decide which of the following are arguments. For those that are, identify the premises and conclusions in them by CIRCLING them and labeling them with a P for the premises or a C for

More information

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice.

7. Some recent rulings of the Supreme Court were politically motivated decisions that flouted the entire history of U.S. legal practice. M05_COPI1396_13_SE_C05.QXD 10/12/07 9:00 PM Page 193 5.5 The Traditional Square of Opposition 193 EXERCISES Name the quality and quantity of each of the following propositions, and state whether their

More information

Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle. Identifying Arguments i

Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle. Identifying Arguments i Phil 3304 Introduction to Logic Dr. David Naugle Identifying Arguments Dallas Baptist University Introduction Identifying Arguments i Any kid who has played with tinker toys and Lincoln logs knows that

More information

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments

Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments Logic: The Science that Evaluates Arguments Logic teaches us to develop a system of methods and principles to use as criteria for evaluating the arguments of others to guide us in constructing arguments

More information

Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Chapter 1 - Basic Training Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall, Stetson University Chapter 1 - Basic Training 1.1 Introduction In this logic course, we are going to be relying on some mental muscles that may need some toning

More information

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3.0. Overview Derivations can also be used to tell when a claim of entailment does not follow from the principles for conjunction. 2.3.1. When enough is enough

More information

Aquinas, The Divine Nature

Aquinas, The Divine Nature Aquinas, The Divine Nature So far we have shown THAT God exists, but we don t yet know WHAT God is like. Here, Aquinas demonstrates attributes of God, who is: (1) Simple (i.e., God has no parts) (2) Perfect

More information

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5

Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 Lesson Seventeen The Conditional Syllogism Selections from Aristotle s Prior Analytics 41a21 41b5 It is clear then that the ostensive syllogisms are effected by means of the aforesaid figures; these considerations

More information

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering

Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems. Prof. Deepak Khemani. Department of Computer Science and Engineering Artificial Intelligence: Valid Arguments and Proof Systems Prof. Deepak Khemani Department of Computer Science and Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module 02 Lecture - 03 So in the last

More information

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments

Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments Lecture 3 Arguments Jim Pryor What is an Argument? Jim Pryor Vocabulary Describing Arguments 1 Agenda 1. What is an Argument? 2. Evaluating Arguments 3. Validity 4. Soundness 5. Persuasive Arguments 6.

More information

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens. INTRODUCTION TO LOGICAL THINKING Lecture 6: Two types of argument and their role in science: Deduction and induction 1. Deductive arguments Arguments that claim to provide logically conclusive grounds

More information

How to Write a Philosophy Paper

How to Write a Philosophy Paper How to Write a Philosophy Paper The goal of a philosophy paper is simple: make a compelling argument. This guide aims to teach you how to write philosophy papers, starting from the ground up. To do that,

More information

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments

1.5 Deductive and Inductive Arguments M01_COPI1396_13_SE_C01.QXD 10/10/07 9:48 PM Page 26 26 CHAPTER 1 Basic Logical Concepts 19. All ethnic movements are two-edged swords. Beginning benignly, and sometimes necessary to repair injured collective

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness

Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness Lecture 1: Validity & Soundness 1 Goals Today Introduce one of our central topics: validity and soundness, and its connection to one of our primary course goals, namely: learning how to evaluate arguments

More information

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan

Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: Jonathan Chan A03.1 Introduction Tutorial A03: Patterns of Valid Arguments By: With valid arguments, it is impossible to have a false conclusion if the premises are all true. Obviously valid arguments play a very important

More information

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts.

PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1. W# Section (10 or 11) 4. T F The statements that compose a disjunction are called conjuncts. PHILOSOPHY 102 INTRODUCTION TO LOGIC PRACTICE EXAM 1 W# Section (10 or 11) 1. True or False (5 points) Directions: Circle the letter next to the best answer. 1. T F All true statements are valid. 2. T

More information

Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy Jeff Speaks What is philosophy?

Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy Jeff Speaks What is philosophy? Philosophy 10100 Introduction to Philosophy Jeff Speaks jspeaks@nd.edu What is philosophy? What is philosophy? Philosophy comes from the ancient Greek φιλοσοφία philosophia. philosophia = philo + sophia

More information

Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic)

Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic) Chapter 3: More Deductive Reasoning (Symbolic Logic) There's no easy way to say this, the material you're about to learn in this chapter can be pretty hard for some students. Other students, on the other

More information

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications Applied Logic Lecture 2: Evidence Semantics for Intuitionistic Propositional Logic Formal logic and evidence CS 4860 Fall 2012 Tuesday, August 28, 2012 2.1 Review The purpose of logic is to make reasoning

More information

Philosophical Arguments

Philosophical Arguments Philosophical Arguments An introduction to logic and philosophical reasoning. Nathan D. Smith, PhD. Houston Community College Nathan D. Smith. Some rights reserved You are free to copy this book, to distribute

More information

Summer Preparation Work

Summer Preparation Work 2017 Summer Preparation Work Philosophy of Religion Theme 1 Arguments for the existence of God Instructions: Philosophy of Religion - Arguments for the existence of God The Cosmological Argument 1. Watch

More information

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10

9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations. Today s Lecture 3/30/10 9.1 Intro to Predicate Logic Practice with symbolizations Today s Lecture 3/30/10 Announcements Tests back today Homework: --Ex 9.1 pgs. 431-432 Part C (1-25) Predicate Logic Consider the argument: All

More information

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence

Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence Why is there something rather than nothing? Leibniz Avicenna, Proof of the Necessary of Existence Avicenna offers a proof for the existence of God based on the nature of possibility and necessity. First,

More information

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy

PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy PHI 1500: Major Issues in Philosophy Session 3 September 9 th, 2015 All About Arguments (Part II) 1 A common theme linking many fallacies is that they make unwarranted assumptions. An assumption is a claim

More information

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then

But we may go further: not only Jones, but no actual man, enters into my statement. This becomes obvious when the statement is false, since then CHAPTER XVI DESCRIPTIONS We dealt in the preceding chapter with the words all and some; in this chapter we shall consider the word the in the singular, and in the next chapter we shall consider the word

More information

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic

MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic MPS 17 The Structure of Persuasion Logos: reasoning, reasons, good reasons not necessarily about formal logic Making and Refuting Arguments Steps of an Argument You make a claim The conclusion of your

More information

Three Kinds of Arguments

Three Kinds of Arguments Chapter 27 Three Kinds of Arguments Arguments in general We ve been focusing on Moleculan-analyzable arguments for several chapters, but now we want to take a step back and look at the big picture, at

More information

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms

Chapter 8 - Sentential Truth Tables and Argument Forms Logic: A Brief Introduction Ronald L. Hall Stetson University Chapter 8 - Sentential ruth ables and Argument orms 8.1 Introduction he truth-value of a given truth-functional compound proposition depends

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES

SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES SOME RADICAL CONSEQUENCES OF GEACH'S LOGICAL THEORIES By james CAIN ETER Geach's views of relative identity, together with his Paccount of proper names and quantifiers, 1 while presenting what I believe

More information

Criticizing Arguments

Criticizing Arguments Kareem Khalifa Criticizing Arguments 1 Criticizing Arguments Kareem Khalifa Department of Philosophy Middlebury College Written August, 2012 Table of Contents Introduction... 1 Step 1: Initial Evaluation

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 5 May 14th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary pm Krabbe Dale Jacquette Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Instructor s Manual 1

Instructor s Manual 1 Instructor s Manual 1 PREFACE This instructor s manual will help instructors prepare to teach logic using the 14th edition of Irving M. Copi, Carl Cohen, and Kenneth McMahon s Introduction to Logic. The

More information

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions

2017 Philosophy. Higher. Finalised Marking Instructions National Qualifications 07 07 Philosophy Higher Finalised Marking Instructions Scottish Qualifications Authority 07 The information in this publication may be reproduced to support SQA qualifications only

More information

Overview of Today s Lecture

Overview of Today s Lecture Branden Fitelson Philosophy 12A Notes 1 Overview of Today s Lecture Music: Robin Trower, Daydream (King Biscuit Flower Hour concert, 1977) Administrative Stuff (lots of it) Course Website/Syllabus [i.e.,

More information

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims).

Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims). TOPIC: You need to be able to: Lecture 2.1 INTRO TO LOGIC/ ARGUMENTS. Recognize an argument when you see one (in media, articles, people s claims). Organize arguments that we read into a proper argument

More information

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction

Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Semantic Entailment and Natural Deduction Alice Gao Lecture 6, September 26, 2017 Entailment 1/55 Learning goals Semantic entailment Define semantic entailment. Explain subtleties of semantic entailment.

More information

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations

Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations An Exposition of Symbolic Logic with Kalish-Montague derivations Copyright 2006-13 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved Aug 2013 Preface The system of logic used here is essentially that of Kalish &

More information

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Do we have knowledge of the external world? Do we have knowledge of the external world? This book discusses the skeptical arguments presented in Descartes' Meditations 1 and 2, as well as how Descartes attempts to refute skepticism by building our

More information

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School

Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School Illustrating Deduction. A Didactic Sequence for Secondary School Francisco Saurí Universitat de València. Dpt. de Lògica i Filosofia de la Ciència Cuerpo de Profesores de Secundaria. IES Vilamarxant (España)

More information

Introduction to Philosophy

Introduction to Philosophy Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Russell Marcus Hamilton College, Fall 2013 Class 1 - Introduction to Introduction to Philosophy My name is Russell. My office is 202 College Hill Road, Room 210.

More information

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents

SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY. Contents UNIT 1 SYSTEMATIC RESEARCH IN PHILOSOPHY Contents 1.1 Introduction 1.2 Research in Philosophy 1.3 Philosophical Method 1.4 Tools of Research 1.5 Choosing a Topic 1.1 INTRODUCTION Everyone who seeks knowledge

More information

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments

Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments Part II: How to Evaluate Deductive Arguments Week 4: Propositional Logic and Truth Tables Lecture 4.1: Introduction to deductive logic Deductive arguments = presented as being valid, and successful only

More information

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics

Critical Thinking. The Four Big Steps. First example. I. Recognizing Arguments. The Nature of Basics Critical Thinking The Very Basics (at least as I see them) Dona Warren Department of Philosophy The University of Wisconsin Stevens Point What You ll Learn Here I. How to recognize arguments II. How to

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Introduction to Philosophy Crito. Instructor: Jason Sheley Introduction to Philosophy Crito Instructor: Jason Sheley Recall again our steps for doing philosophy 1) What is the question? 2) What is the basic answer to the question? 3) What reasons are given for

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic

Announcements. CS243: Discrete Structures. First Order Logic, Rules of Inference. Review of Last Lecture. Translating English into First-Order Logic Announcements CS243: Discrete Structures First Order Logic, Rules of Inference Işıl Dillig Homework 1 is due now Homework 2 is handed out today Homework 2 is due next Tuesday Işıl Dillig, CS243: Discrete

More information

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic

Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Logic for Computer Science - Week 1 Introduction to Informal Logic Ștefan Ciobâcă November 30, 2017 1 Propositions A proposition is a statement that can be true or false. Propositions are sometimes called

More information

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing

What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing What is a logical argument? What is deductive reasoning? Fundamentals of Academic Writing Logical relations Deductive logic Claims to provide conclusive support for the truth of a conclusion Inductive

More information

National Quali cations

National Quali cations H SPECIMEN S85/76/ National Qualications ONLY Philosophy Paper Date Not applicable Duration hour 5 minutes Total marks 50 SECTION ARGUMENTS IN ACTION 30 marks Attempt ALL questions. SECTION KNOWLEDGE AND

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form.

To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form. LOGIC GUIDE 2 To better understand VALIDITY, we now turn to the topic of logical form. LOGICAL FORM The logical form of a statement or argument is the skeleton, or structure. If you retain only the words

More information

Introduction to Logic

Introduction to Logic University of Notre Dame Spring, 2017 Arguments Philosophy has two main methods for trying to answer questions: analysis and arguments Logic is the the study of arguments An argument is a set of sentences,

More information

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training

Study Guides. Chapter 1 - Basic Training Study Guides Chapter 1 - Basic Training Argument: A group of propositions is an argument when one or more of the propositions in the group is/are used to give evidence (or if you like, reasons, or grounds)

More information

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions

7.1. Unit. Terms and Propositions. Nature of propositions. Types of proposition. Classification of propositions Unit 7.1 Terms and Propositions Nature of propositions A proposition is a unit of reasoning or logical thinking. Both premises and conclusion of reasoning are propositions. Since propositions are so important,

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

SCIENCE ASSESSMENT P4-G5 Colour key: Working Scientifically Animals, Including Humans Plants Materials Weather/Seasons/Earth and Space Living Things

SCIENCE ASSESSMENT P4-G5 Colour key: Working Scientifically Animals, Including Humans Plants Materials Weather/Seasons/Earth and Space Living Things SCIENCE ASSESSMENT P4-G5 Colour key: Working Scientifically Animals, Including Humans Plants Materials Weather/Seasons/Earth and Space Living Things And Their Habitats Rocks Light Magnets and Forces Sound

More information

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language

Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language Aquinas Cosmological argument in everyday language P1. If there is no first cause, there cannot be any effects. P2. But we have observed that there are effects, like observing change in the world. C: So

More information

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy

Scientific Method and Research Ethics Questions, Answers, and Evidence. Dr. C. D. McCoy Scientific Method and Research Ethics 17.09 Questions, Answers, and Evidence Dr. C. D. McCoy Plan for Part 1: Deduction 1. Logic, Arguments, and Inference 1. Questions and Answers 2. Truth, Validity, and

More information

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy

Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy Argumentative Analogy versus Figurative Analogy By Timo Schmitz, Philosopher As argumentative analogy or simply analogism (ἀναλογισµός), one calls the comparison through inductive reasoning of at least

More information

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.)

HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) 1 HANDBOOK (New or substantially modified material appears in boxes.) I. ARGUMENT RECOGNITION Important Concepts An argument is a unit of reasoning that attempts to prove that a certain idea is true by

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE

Logic: Deductive and Inductive by Carveth Read M.A. CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE CHAPTER IX CHAPTER IX FORMAL CONDITIONS OF MEDIATE INFERENCE Section 1. A Mediate Inference is a proposition that depends for proof upon two or more other propositions, so connected together by one or

More information

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference

Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference 1 2 3 4 5 6 Argumentation Module: Philosophy Lesson 7 What do we mean by argument? (Two meanings for the word.) A quarrel or a dispute, expressing a difference of opinion. Often heated. A statement of

More information

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to:

Logic & Proofs. Chapter 3 Content. Sentential Logic Semantics. Contents: Studying this chapter will enable you to: Sentential Logic Semantics Contents: Truth-Value Assignments and Truth-Functions Truth-Value Assignments Truth-Functions Introduction to the TruthLab Truth-Definition Logical Notions Truth-Trees Studying

More information

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites

Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 3, November 2010 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Luminosity, Reliability, and the Sorites STEWART COHEN University of Arizona

More information

Being a Scientist. A year 1 scientist. Working scientifically (Y1 and Y2) Physics. Biology. Chemistry

Being a Scientist. A year 1 scientist. Working scientifically (Y1 and Y2) Physics. Biology. Chemistry A year 1 scientist (Y1 and Y2) I can ask simple scientific questions. I can use simple equipment to make observations. I can carry out simple tests. I can identify and classify things. I can suggest what

More information

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will Alex Cavender Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division 1 An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge

More information