The Problem of Normativity in Kant s Philosophy of Logic

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Problem of Normativity in Kant s Philosophy of Logic"

Transcription

1 The Problem of Normativity in Kant s Philosophy of Logic Rebecca Victoria Millsop April 16, 2010 Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for Honors in Philosophy at the University of California, Berkeley I want to express my gratitude to Professor John MacFarlane for being my advisor for this project; working with him has been an invaluable philosophical experience. I also want to thank the following individuals for their sustained support, advice, and comments on previous drafts of this essay: Gus Holcomb, Eugene Chislenko, Yuan Wu, Laura Davis, Justin Bledin, Nathana O Brien, Devin Rusky, Lara Krisst, Paolo Mancosu, Branden Fitelson, Hannah Ginsborg, Daniel Warren, Markus Kohl, and my mom. I would also like to thank the audience in Branden Fitelson s Logic, Formal Methods, and Epistemology seminar, as well as Berkeley s Undergraduate Philosophy Forum.

2 Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 A Law as a Norm 4 3 Kant s General Logic Abstraction and Necessity The Constitutive Interpretation The Normative Interpretation The Moral Law and the Laws of Logic Both Normative and Non-Normative The Two Standpoints and Relational Normativity Analogy Pure and Applied as Noumenal and Phenomenal Conclusion 38 A Appendix: Kant s Transcendental Idealism 40 A.1 Cognitive Faculties and the Discursivity Thesis A.2 The Two-Aspects Interpretation

3 1 Introduction Throughout his discussions on logic, Immanuel Kant claims that the laws of logic are normative for thought; in other words, logic as a science does not tell us how the understanding is and does think and how it has previously proceeded in thought, but rather how it ought to proceed in thought (Jäsche Logic, 14), where the understanding is taken to be our cognitive capacity for thought in general. If the laws of logic provide us with the correct way to think, then it should be possible to think incorrectly, or deviate from those laws in some way. Christine Korsgaard makes this claim clear when she states, There is no normativity if you cannot go wrong (Korsgaard (1996b, 162)). Thus, Kant must be able to explain how logical error is possible. This is a problem as he also claims that the laws of logic are in some way essential to, or constitutive of, the activity of thought, and essential laws cannot be violated in the way a norm can be violated. He admits this problem in the following passage: It is hard to comprehend how a power can deviate from its own laws, since it acts only according to certain laws. If these laws are essential, then the power cannot deviate from them[;] if, then, among the formal laws of the understanding that logic expounds an essential one is possible, then the understanding cannot deviate from it. (Vienna Logic, 824) Error is only possible when the sensibility, which is the capacity (receptivity) for receiving representations through the mode in which we are affected by objects, (Critique of Pure Reason, A19/B22) somehow interferes with the activity of the understanding. The understanding does not err in its own right, and our thought must, in some way, adhere to the laws of logic. Otherwise, it cannot be considered a product of the understanding: A man can never err completely and utterly... Total error would be a complete opposition to the laws of the understanding. But then it could not arise from the understanding, which can produce nothing that conflicts with its nature... (Vienna Logic, 825-6). Thus, any product of the 1

4 understanding must comply with its own laws, which just are the laws of logic. But now it seems that the laws of logic do not possess the desired normative force; it seems that there are at least some laws of logic that describe how we do think because they are essential to the act of thought itself. We have run into what seems to be a serious problem for Kant s claims regarding the nature of logic. As described above, Kant makes the following claims: (N) The laws of logic are normative for thought. (Jäsche Logic, 14) (ES) There are laws of logic which are essential for, or constitutive of, the act of thought. (Jäsche Logic, 13) (V) A law that is essential for the activity of the understanding (or any faculty by itself) cannot be violated. (Vienna Logic, 824) And we also want to hold that (ER) For a law to be normative, it must be possible to violate it in some way. In other words, an ought implies can err. (V) and (ES) together imply that there are laws of logic which cannot be violated. This along with (ER) implies that there are some laws of logic which are not normative for thought, which contradicts (N). How are the laws of logic supposed to be normative if there is no possible way of violating them? The goal of this essay is to propose and evaluate an interpretation of Kant s logic that explains all four claims above while also explaining away the contradictory consequence that apparently follows from the conjunction of these claims. My interpretation will focus on the taxonomic distinctions that Kant makes throughout the Critique of Pure Reason and his Lectures on Logic regarding the nature of the different kinds of logic. 1 It is generally assumed that the laws of logic that Kant describes as both normative and essential for thought are 1 The Lectures on Logic are a collection of four texts from different periods of Kant s career as a lecturer on logic. The first three texts are transcripts from his lectures, and the fourth, titled the Jäsche Logic, is the textbook that he had a student compile based on the lecture notes he had accrued throughout his career. The last two parts, the Vienna Logic and the Jäsche Logic, are the two I will use in this essay, as they were written near or during the periods of his more mature critical philosophy. 2

5 those laws Kant defines as pure general laws of logic; however, I claim that this assumption is not textually based and leads to the contradiction described above. Instead, I will argue, the laws that Kant describes as normative for and essential of thought are the laws of general logic; it is because we can then represent these laws as either pure or applied that these laws have the dual nature described. The laws under the broader description of general can be thought of as both normative and essential. In the end pure general and applied general logic do not consist of two separate kinds of logic, rather they are two distinct ways of representing the same laws. The pure general laws are strictly essential for, or constitute of, thought, while the applied general laws are those that we can violate and those that Kant takes as normative for thought. In the end, I claim that the normativity of the pure general laws of logic is at best externally conferred, rather than essentially inherent (Tolley (2006), 375); our nature as thinking human beings is such that the laws of pure general logic are essential for thought yet our cognitive capacities allow for empirical-psychological rules to override the laws of pure general logic while retaining the illusion of thought. It is because we are beings with these different cognitive capacities which are in relation to one another that the laws of logic are viewed as normative. I will begin by explaining what is to be expected of a normative interpretation of such laws, how a constitutive interpretation of Kant s laws of logic does not meet these expectations, and then go on to discuss how different normative interpretations of Kant s laws of logic attempt to meet these expectations. I then go on to consider how the normative interpretation may be justified in light of an analogy with Kant s description of the moral law as constitutive and normative for action. In making this analogy I will emphasize the two standpoint view that Kant puts forth in the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, and conclude that the moral law is not essentially normative but rather normative in relation to certain kinds of beings, or relationally normative. My goal from that point on will be to show how the two-standpoint view in the moral case is analogous to the distinction between 3

6 pure and applied general logic, and explain how we can make sense of the normative claims that Kant makes in light of this distinction. I will end the essay with a discussion of how this interpertation allows for all four of the claims mentioned above to coexist while eliminating the contradictory conclusion. 2 A Law as a Norm If any normative interpretation of Kant s laws of logic can be made sense of, the requirements for a law being normative instead of descriptive must be set forth. A law that is descriptive, for example, the law stating that the speed of light is 186,282 miles per second, simply describes the way light is. The law doesn t make any normative claims about how fast light should travel, it states how fast light does travel. In an attempt to get at what it is for a law to be a norm on Kant s account I will consider the two conditions that Clinton Tolley, in his essay Kant on the Nature of Logical Laws, (Tolley (2006, 375)) suggests: 2 (1) Error Any being subject to the law must both be able to succeed and be able to fail to act (or be) in accordance with the law. (2) Identity Even when a being subject to the law does not act in accordance with the law, the subject still identifies itself as being subject to the law regardless. These are the conditions that he claims, on Kant s account, give a law normative force; such laws prescribe correct action to a being that is subject to the law. To illustrate these conditions I will use the example of fidelity as a norm imposed on a subject in a monogamous 2 Tolley provides a third condition, Bindingness: The laws must retain their validity or bindingness over their subjects regardless of the (lack of) actual adherence to the norms by their subjects though, to be sure, there must be the possibility of such adherence (to uphold the traditional formula that ought implies can ) Tolley (2006, 375). I will not be using this condition because I do not see how it adds significantly to the set of conditions, as much of what is important in this third condition is captured by the second condition. And there are several counterexamples to its validity. For example, consider the following law: all residents of Berkeley cannot leave Berkeley. But this law is only binding on people in Berkeley, thus if you leave you are no longer bound by the law. I believe there are ways of addressing this counterexample; however, the best way to address the issue is by referring to the second condition, identity. Thus, I will exempt this third condition from my discussion. 4

7 relationship, that typically imposed by the bond of marriage. The cases I am discussing are those in which two subjects have agreed that the law of fidelity is binding over their relationship. The first condition, Error, is obviously met: either of the two subjects are capable of an act of infidelity, while also capable of adhering to the law. A being who never engages in a monogamous relationship will not be subject to the law of fidelity, just as inanimate objects can never be subject to this law. This condition is the same one discussed in the introduction; we can think of it as saying that ought implies can err. The second condition, Identity, is quite clear in the case of fidelity; if one of the subjects fails to act according to the law of fidelity, they feel guilt (to some degree) because they still identify themselves as subject to the law. Although this condition clearly holds in the case of fidelity, there are other cases where this is less clear; for example, the case of traffic laws. Perhaps I am unaware of a specific traffic law; assume this is the law that says that I must drive under 30mph on the city streets. It is difficult to say that I identify myself with this law given that I am unaware that it is binding on me. It is clear that this law is still normative for my action, as the content prescribes how fast I ought to drive, not how fast I am driving. Thus, this seems to be a counterexample to the second condition. However, even though I do not identify myself as being subject to this law, it is the case that I identify myself as being subject to all of the pertinent traffic laws. As Tolley notes, this condition is important, as it implies that evaluative ascriptions in light of norms (e.g., x as in or out of accord ) institute a division within some otherwise well-defined class (Tolley (2006, 375)). Given that I take myself to be subject to the traffic laws, when I disobey some law, even those I am unaware of, my action is evaluated as being out of accord with the laws I identify myself with. There is a stronger response against the second condition, however. Instead of being unaware of the law, I may consider myself above the law. In this case I am aware what the law expects of me, but I do not identify myself with the law whatsoever. The law in this case 5

8 is still binding over my action as a driver, and thus it seems like the law is still normative despite my lack of identification with it. This seems like a clear case where a law is a norm yet does not satisfy the second condition. This examples brings out an important distinction between normativity in general and normativity on Kant s account; this distinction is further brought out by considering the differences in the fidelity and traffic laws cases. In the fidelity case the subject has bound themselves to the law and in that way the subject has internalized the law as a norm. In the case of the traffic laws the laws are externally conferred on the subject, which is why one can opt out of identifying with the law despite the fact that other people still view the law as normatively binding on that subject. In a discussion of Kant s account of the moral law being normative, Korsgaard makes the following claims: Here we come to an important distinction, between norms that are constitutive of, and so internal, to the activities that they claim to govern, and norms that are external to those activities... External norms give rise to further questions, and space for skeptical doubt. But if we can identify something as an internal norm, the question why you should conform to the norm answers itself. (Korsgaard (2008, 61)) Given this description, our example of traffic laws can be seen as external norms; the activity of driving is not constituted by the traffic laws. Whereas the law of fidelity is constitutive of a monogamous relationship. To be in a monogamous relationship is to identify yourself with the law of fidelity, and in this way the law is internally normative. Thus, it seems that the condition of identity is a condition of a law being a constitutive norm. And the goal of this essay is to interpret Kant s laws of logic such that they can be taken as both constitutive of and normative for thought. So although the condition of identity is not a condition on normativity in general, it is a condition for the kind of norm that we are considering given Kant s account. I shall therefore refer to these conditions throughout the rest of the essay when considering the different interpretations of Kant s laws of logic. 6

9 3 Kant s General Logic Before addressing the constitutive and normative interpretations I want to briefly describe the nature of Kant s logic, as well as describe one of the two important taxonomic distinctions that I will be focusing on throughout this essay: the distinction between general and particular logics. The second distinction, the distinction within general logic between pure and applied logic, will be discussed in detail in later sections of this essay. It is clear that the laws of logic that Kant describes as both normative and essential for all thought are to be of the general kind, not of the particular kind, as in all the relevant texts the important claims he makes are all in regard to general logic. However, it is generally assumed that when Kant discusses the laws of logic he is discussing pure general logic only, and that we should set applied general logic aside because it is not really logic. As we shall see below, I claim that the distinction between pure and applied is the most important for making sense of a constitutive and normative interpretation of Kant s logical laws. However, before delving into that topic, I will first examine the general/particular distinction and try to get at what is definitive of general logic. Through this examination the ambiguity in Kant s description of general logic as necessary will be illustrated; does he mean the laws of general logic are necessary in an essential way, or in a normative way? It is not clear because he never spells it out for us. I will walk through several passages in the Critique of Pure Reason and the Jäsche Logic in which he describes his distinction between general and particular logics, emphasizing the ambiguity of the term necessary. 3.1 Abstraction and Necessity Kant claims that general logic is distinguished from particular logic in that the former abstracts away from all objects of thought. It is because of this abstraction that logic 7

10 provides the necessary laws of thought. 3 After having abstracted away from all objects of thought whatever is left will be something that all acts of thought share without exception. The only exception would come about because of a particular kind of content, which would result in the use of the understanding that is particular. Kant states there is, for example, a use of the understanding in mathematics, in metaphysics, morals, etc. (JL, 12). When thinking about any one particular area, then, there are laws of a particular logic that are applicable. But general laws of logic are applicable to all thought. His descriptions of general logic are similar in both major texts: Now logic in turn can be undertaken with two different aims, either as the logic of the general or of the particular use of the understanding. The former contains the absolutely necessary rules of thinking, without which no use of the understanding takes place, and it therefore concerns these rules without regard to the difference of the objects to which it may be directed. (Critique of Pure Reason, B76/A52) If now we put aside all cognition that we have to borrow from objects and merely reflect on the use just of the understanding, we discover those of its rules which are necessary without qualification, for every purpose and without regard to any particular objects of thought, because without them we would not think at all. Thus we can have insight into these rules a priori, i.e., independent of all experience, because they contain merely the conditions for the use of the understanding in general, without distinction among its objects, be that use pure or empirical. (Jäsche Logic, 12) Given his descriptions, there are two main features of general logic: 1) Abstraction from all content of thought. 2) Because of this abstraction, we are left with the necessary rules of the use of the understanding. Thus, we must understand these two features in more detail, and how they are related to one another. The first thing to understand is exactly what Kant means by abstracting away from the objects of thought. He describes the abstraction as leaving only the relations between 3 Note that I will be using laws of thought synonymously with laws of general logic, as Kant does, unless otherwise stated. 8

11 thoughts, or, as he describes this, the mere form of thinking (Critique of Pure Reason, B78/A54). For example, if we abstract away from the content of the following inference: All objects on the table are green. This cup is on the table. Therefore, this cup is green. we are left with the relation of these thoughts to one another. This leaves us with a skeleton, so to speak, which can be classified as a specific form of logical syllogism that can then be analyzed. The content of these thoughts are the objects related to the concepts object on the table, green, and cup. The understanding has related these contents to one another according to the following form: 1) All F s are Gs. 2) S is a F. S is a G. Premise 1 is the major premise; in this case it is a universal proposition; premise 2 is the minor premise; in this case it is an affirmative proposition. This is an instance of the first figure of inference, from this the following rules for the three latter figures emerge (Jäsche Logic, 127). Much of his discussion of general logic is put in terms of the formal aspects of thought, and thus it is important to explain the relationship between Kant s logic being general and its being formal. This is discussed in detail in John MacFarlane s paper Frege, Kant, and the Logic in Logicism, in which he argues that Frege and Kant can be considered as having the same view of the nature of logic because they both claim that logic should be general; where general here is of a normative sort discussed below. In the process of providing his argument, MacFarlane shows that the formality of Kant s logic is actually a consequence of the generality of logic, and not an independent feature. Thus, whenever we discuss the formal 9

12 nature of logic, it is imperative to realize that this formality stems from logic s generality. Although we can separate them conceptually, it is not possible to have one without the other. At this point we understand that general logic abstracts away from the content of thought, and the laws of logic are in some way derived from this abstraction. However, this does not further clarify our understanding of the way Kant uses the term necessary in his description of general logic. Given different pieces of textual evidence we can interpret Kant as intending to mean different things. Thus, at this point there are two ways to understand what Kant means by absolutely necessary in the phrase absolutely necessary rules of thinking. There is a stronger interpretation of necessary which suggests that every act of thought adheres to these laws of logic; this coincides with the constitutive interpretation. If this is correct then every thought is logical. As we shall see, this interpretation is supported by sections of the texts where he claims that the faculty of the understanding, when considered by itself, cannot think in opposition to its own rules. The weaker, normative interpretation takes this necessity to imply that the laws of logic are normatively binding on the rational individual, and given the conditions for a law being a norm this interpretation attempts to make sense of logical error. 3.2 The Constitutive Interpretation The constitutive, essential interpretation claims that thought must adhere to the laws of logic if the action is considered thought at all. The term constitutive can be understood as, in a sense, descriptive. Just as there is a law which states how fast the speed of light is, the laws of logic, on this interpretation, describe how the understanding works. Thus, if the understanding is in use it must be the case that the thought produced by the understanding abides by, or adheres to, those general laws of logic. This is one way of explaining what it means for rules to be necessary without qualification; in other words, this interpretation takes the laws of logic to be necessary conditions for every act of thought. This interpretation 10

13 takes Kant s laws of logic as failing to meet the first condition of normativity, Error. Although this interpretation may seem a bit extreme, and seems to go against what we ve seen Kant says about the normative nature of logic, it is supported throughout both the Critique of Pure Reason and the Jäsche Logic when he discusses how the understanding cannot err because it necessarily adheres to its own laws:... a total error would be a complete opposition to the laws of the understanding and of reason. But how could that, as such, in any way come from the understanding and, insofar as it is still a judgment, be held to be a product of the understanding. (Jäsche Logic, 54)... it is hard to comprehend how error in the formal sense of the world, i.e., how the form of thought contrary to the understanding is possible, just as we cannot in general comprehend how any power should deviate from its own essential laws. (Jäsche Logic, 53) hence neither the understanding by itself (without the influence of another cause), nor the senses by themselves, can err; the first cannot, because while it acts merely according to its own laws, its effect (the judgment) must necessarily agree with these laws. (Critique of Pure Reason, B350/A294) The constitutive interpretation draws from these quotes that there are laws of logic that cannot be violated in thought. The understanding acts according to the laws of logic, and the resulting judgment must agree with them. This last quote is especially strong: the effect is not just assessable by the laws, the result does agree with these laws. 4 This interpretation requires an explanation of what it is for thought to be untainted by the influence of other faculties, and how it is that this purity relates to the strong necessity claim. The constitutive interpretation of necessity thus makes sense of the textual claims that Kant makes regarding error. However, it leads us to the unsatisfactory conclusion that logical error is impossible. And, as we discussed above, if logical error is impossible the logical laws 4 I draw this conclusion from Kant s usage of the phrase must necessarily in the passage. It may be argued that this phrase could be taken deontically, so that the passages implies that judgment ought to agree with these laws. This would imply some sort of normative interpretation. However, if this were the case, then there should be a deontic interpretation of can err in the preceding sentence. This does not seem correct at all, which is why I am taking must necessarily agree with these laws as a metaphysical necessity. 11

14 do not meet the requirement for being a normative law. As the nature of logical error is important to our discussion, I will briefly comment on Kant s claims regarding the existence of error. As pointed out above, the understanding itself cannot err, and neither can any faculty alone err. Instead, error is the product of some kind of interference with the use of the understanding. In the discussion of truth and error in the Jäsche Logic Kant claims that the ground for the origin of all error will therefore have to be sought simply and solely in the unnoticed influence of sensibility upon the understanding, or to speak more exactly, upon judgment (Jäsche Logic, 53-4). Sensibility is our capacity for taking in the world, and all cognition requires input from sensibility and conceptual activity from the understanding. Thus, the laws of logic only govern the use of our higher cognitive abilities, and our ability to think badly stems not from any fault of the understanding itself, but rather from its interaction with objects in the world. Another way of saying this is that error stems from how our passive faculty of sensibility comes together with our active faculty of understanding. It seems, then, given the connection we have been discussing between the ability to err and normativity, it follows that the laws of logic are taken to be normative only insofar as there is this possibility of this external interference. It could be that the seemingly normative nature of the laws of logic stems from some relation between the different cognitive faculties that beings like us possess. 3.3 The Normative Interpretation Despite Kant s claims about the laws of logic being essential for the activity of thought, throughout the Lectures on Logic he makes several explicit claims regarding the normative nature of these laws of logic. If this is the case then the laws of logic should meet the two conditions for normativity. The most oft-cited quote is from the Jäsche Logic, where in describing the laws of general logic he makes the following claim: 12

15 As a science of the necessary laws of thought, without which no use of the understanding or of reason takes place at all, laws which consequently are conditions under which the understanding can and ought to agree with itself alone the necessary laws and conditions of its correct use logic is, however, a canon. (Jäsche Logic, 13) This is the first place the word ought shows up in this text, and suggests that this ought is a consequence of the necessity of the laws of thought. Here Kant also talks of the laws of logic as also being conditions for the use of the understanding, and it is in terms of conditions that he speaks of the correct use of the understanding. Thus, general logic consists of the necessary laws of thought and from these laws the conditions for correct thought follow. Unless Kant is using the term ought in some non-normative way, it must be possible to make sense of the laws of general logic in some way to fulfill the two conditions provided above for a law to be a norm. Thus, we cannot rule out the possibility that normativity is somehow essential to the nature of general logic; the question at hand, however, is whether or not normativity is definitive of generality. At this point it is worth noting that in the Critique of Pure Reason Kant does not mention the normative nature of general logic explicitly, neither in the section On Logic in General nor anywhere else in the text. 5 If the generality being discussed were inherently normative, meaning that this generality could be explained by normativity, it could be expected to see use of the term ought in this discussion. However, in the Critique he explains generality only in terms of abstraction, not normativity. This will only make 5 By explicitly I mean the explicit use of the word ought. However, it could be argued that the normativity is explicitly referenced in both texts on when Kant talks about the laws of logic being rules for thought. For example, in the Critique of Pure Reason Kant describes these laws as the absolutely necessary rules of thinking (Critique of Pure Reason, B76/B52). And in the Jäsche Logic the laws of logic are those rules which are necessary without qualification (Jäsche Logic, 12). However, at the very beginning of the introduction to the Jäsche Logic Kant claims that Everything in nature, both in the lifeless and in the living world, takes place according to rules... Water falls according to the laws of gravity, and with animals locomotion also takes place according to rules. The fish in water, the bird in air, move according to rules (Jäsche Logic, 11). The laws of gravity are not normative, they are descriptive, and the fact that Kant is suggesting that these laws are to be considered rules shows that we should not take Kant s description of the laws of logic as rules to be indicating any sort of normativity. 13

16 sense if we find that this abstraction is itself inherently normative. Although it is left unclear exactly how these laws are also essential conditions for the activity of thought, the normative interpretation views Kant as going on to further forge the connection between necessity and normativity as inherent, as he claims in the Jäsche Logic: In logic, however, the question is not about contingent but about necessary rules; not how we do think, but how we ought to think... In logic we do not want to know how the understanding is and does think and how it has previously proceeded in thought, but rather how it ought to proceed in thought. Logic is to teach us the correct use of the understanding. (Jäsche Logic, 14) Here we can interpret Kant as drawing a parallel between descriptive laws and contingency, and normative laws and necessity. Thus, there is some connection between the laws of general logic and how we ought to think, although it is not described explicitly any further in his works. The laws of general logic, then, are normative for thought in some way, yet it has not been shown that this normativity is definitive of why general logic is to be thought of as general. Why should the mere abstraction from all content of thought result in normative rules? This normativity seems to be adding something to the idea of general logic, but Kant never specifies what. Thus, in order for the normative interpretation of necessity to hold, it must be able to explain how the nature of general necessity as abstraction from all content of thought entails the normative claims that we find in the Jäsche Logic MacFarlane s Normative Interpretation John MacFarlane, in his paper briefly discussed above, titled Frege, Kant, and the Logic in Logicism, advocates a version of the normative interpretation of Kant s general logic. He claims that normativity is definitive of Kant s general logic: The generality of logic, for Frege as for Kant, is a normative generality: logic is general in the sense that it provides constitutive norms for thought as such, regardless of its subject matter (MacFarlane (2002, 35)). In this 14

17 section I will present and evaluate MacFarlane s claims regarding the normative generality of logic, concluding that the outcome of his explanation of logical laws as constitutive norms is attractive, but that it is does not fully account for the second condition of normativity because it does not explain how the laws of logic are active in thought. MacFarlane first presents and explains his distinction between descriptive laws and normative laws, and then goes on to explain that Kant s logic must be of a normative generality because Kant s laws of logic are to be thought of as constitutive norms given the textual evidence just discussed above. He distinguishes between the two types of laws as follows: A normative law prescribes what one ought to do or provides a standard for the evaluation of one s conduct as good or bad. A descriptive law, on the other hand, describes certain regularities in the order of things typically those with high explanatory value. (MacFarlane (2002, 35)) Given this distinction, then, we can draw a parallel with the constitutive and normative interpretations of necessity associated with generality. A descriptive characterization of generality is going to align with the constitutive interpretation, wherein the laws describe some aspect of the process of thought which is necessary in that this description is of something which always occurs. A normative characterization of generality is one in which the laws are standards for the evaluation for some act in general; in other words, in order to perform such an act one must necessarily be assessable in light of those laws. The laws of logic are general in this way, MacFarlane claims, in that to count an activity as thinking at all is to hold it assessable in light of the laws of logic (MacFarlane, 37). The laws that are normatively general in this way are to be taken to be constitutive norms. MacFarlane provides an example of how the laws of physics are constitutive norms for making judgments about the physical world: [The laws of physics] have prescriptive consequences for anyone engaged in the game of thinking about the physical world: such a thinker ought not make 15

18 judgments that are incompatible with them. Indeed, insofar as one s activity is to count as making judgments about the physical world at all, it must be assessable for correctness in light of the laws of physics. In this sense, the laws of physics provide constitutive norms for the activity of thinking about the physical world. (MacFarlane (2002, 37)) MacFarlane claims that the laws are constitutive because they are unconditionally binding on the activity itself; in other words, the activity cannot be performed without those laws as standards for evaluation of the activity. For example, if I begin to posit the existence of flying pigs it is either that I have opted out of the activity of thinking about the physical world, and thus am no longer assessable by the laws of physics, or I am having incorrect thoughts about the physical world despite the fact that I am attempting to think correctly because I consider my thoughts to be assessable by the laws of physics. Thus, constitutive norms are also normative because it is possible to think incorrectly; it is only necessary that the thought be assessable in light of those norms. MacFarlane s goal in his essay is to show how both Frege and Kant think of logic as general in the normative sense, and most of his discussion of the normative characterization of generality is in light of Frege s claims. However, in the section titled Kant s Characterization of Logic as General, he quotes from Kant to support this claim. He quotes the distinction in the Jäsche Logic between general logic being necessary and particular laws being contingent, where Kant describes the laws of general logic as those without which no use of the understanding would be possible at all (Jäsche Logic, 12), a quote which we are now quite familiar with at this point. And, as we have seen, generality and necessity go together on Kant s account, although the nature of this necessity has been ambiguous. This is the interesting move: MacFarlane assumes that Kant s general necessity is normative. The necessary rules are necessary, not in the sense that we cannot think contrary to them, but in the sense that they are unconditionally binding norms for thought norms, that is, for thought as such. (Compare the sense in which Kant calls the categorical imperative necessary. ) Similarly, the contingent rules of 16

19 the understanding provided by geometry or physics are contingent, not in the sense that they could have been otherwise, but in the sense that they are binding on our thought only conditionally: they bind us only to the extent that we think about space, matter, or energy. (MacFarlane (2002, 47)) Surely we can make sense of this interpretation, as the normative interpretation is attractive for explaining the claims that Kant makes regarding the ought in the Jäsche Logic, but it is unclear still why we should interpret the necessity as normative. The main problem is that MacFarlane does not go on to mention the other more explicit normative claims that Kant makes about the laws of logic, nor does he go on to say anything else to support his interpretation. If the necessity under discussion is normative, then this will make sense of Kant s claims in the Critique of Pure Reason as well as the Jäsche Logic regarding the normative nature of general logic. But further justification is not provided. MacFarlane s idea of a constitutive norm is certainly an attractive one for explaining the nature of Kant s laws of logic. The laws have a constitutive component that makes them unconditionally binding on the thinking subject, which, it could be argued, meets the second condition of normativity, identity. His account definitely allows for error, which is the first condition for a law to be a norm, because his concept of a constitutive norm is defined in terms of assessibility. As mentioned above the laws of physics are normative in that in thinking about the physical world the subject s thought is assessable in light of the laws of physics. The laws of logic are unconditionally binding in that in order to be considered thinking at all, one must be assessable by the laws of logic. Thus, MacFarlane s interpretation assumes that the laws can be adhered to and not adhered to, which allows for error. However, it is not so clear exactly how MacFarlane s explanation accounts for the second condition. At first, it seems he could meet this condition through some explanation of the unconditional binding on the thinking subject; the laws of logic constitute the act of thought and thus are internally conferred laws. Yet MacFarlane s explanation of this binding is in 17

20 terms of assessability, which is a passive notion. It is unclear how the notion of assessability is supposed to make such a strong binding claim on the subject. Consider the case of the law of fidelity; my action is surely assessable in light of the law of fidelity, but that is because I identify myself as a being in a monogamous relationship. It is not that because my action is assessable in light of the law of fidelity that I identify myself as a being in a monogamous relationship. Assessability is a consequence of the two conditions of normativity, not the other way around. These norms should have the feature of being used in the assessment of whether or not a logical law is abided by, but it is unclear how this assessment can be definitive of the constitutive nature of the laws. In his explanation MacFarlane notes that the necessity inherent in the laws of logic is to be taken as analogous to the necessity inherent in the moral law. This suggests that the moral law is also unconditionally binding on action insofar as action is assessed in light of the moral law. However, a being subject to the moral law is not merely bound because their action is assessable by the moral law; the moral law actively guides the subject. The way in which the moral law is active will be discussed in more detail below. Given that MacFarlane s notion of assessability is a passive one, it does not account for the active force that the necessary laws of logic should play in Kant s account. On MacFarlane s interpretation, every act of thought is to be assessable by these norms, but Kant s description of the use of the understanding requires that these laws be active. These laws are constitutive of the activity of the understanding itself, thought, and the use of the understanding is a spontaneous activity which imposes conceptual form onto all objects of experience. Kant describes the spontaneous nature of the faculty of the understanding throughout his works, but most heavily in the Transcendental Logic of the Critique of Pure Reason: If we will call the receptivity of our mind to receive representations insofar as it is affected in some way sensibility, then on the contrary, the faculty for bringing 18

21 forth representations itself, or the spontaneity of cognition, is the understanding. (B75/A51) Concepts are therefore grounded on the spontaneity of thinking, as sensible intuitions are grounded on the receptivity of impressions. (A68/B93)... the combination of a manifold in general can never come to us through the senses, and therefore cannot already be contained in the pure form of sensible intuition; for it is an act of the spontaneity of the power of representation, and, since one must call the latter understanding, in distinction from sensibility, all combination, whether we are conscious of it or not, whether it is a combination of the manifold of intuition or of several concepts, and in the first case either of sensible or non-sensible intuition, is an action of the understanding... which can be executed only by the subject itself, since it is an act of its self-activity. (B130) In all of these passages the understanding is contrasted to the sensibility, in that the faculty of sensibility receives sensory input, which is why it is considered a passive faculty. The understanding, on the other hand, is spontaneous; it is an active combination of representations into concepts, judgments, and inferences. If the laws of logic are constitutive of the use of the understanding, just as the moral law is for the use of practical reason, then these laws must be guiding the act of thought. Thus, although this notion makes sense of the normative claims that have been discussed, there is something missing from MacFarlane s description; that something is an explanation of the active normative force that Kant s laws of logic seem to impose on all use of the understanding. This notion of normative force is itself not clear, but it can been seen how the necessity involved with Kant s laws of logic, if they are to be considered constitutive norms, must do more than act as passive standards from which all thought is assessed Korsgaard s Normative Interpretation Christine Korsgaard, in the chapter The Metaphysics of Normativity of her book Self- Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity, discusses a somewhat similar notion to Mac- Farlane s constitutive norm, except her notion brings out the active nature of the laws of logic that MacFarlane s discussion lacks. She describes the constitutive norm as uncondi- 19

22 tionally binding because all actions under the power of these norms are necessarily guided by the constitutive norms; not merely assessable in light of them. Korsgaard uses the concept of a constitutive principle, which she describes as follows: In these cases what we say is that if you are not guided by the principle, you are not performing the activity at all. In the case of essentially goal-directed activities, constitutive principles arise from the constitutive standards to which they are directed.... To use a controversial example, it is a constitutive principle of thinking that you swerve when you see a contradiction looming ahead in your path. And in these cases, we can say that unless you are guided by the principle in question, you are not performing that activity at all. (Korsgaard (2009, 29)) On this account the principles are unconditionally binding, except we make sense of this in terms of a kind of self-imposed intention towards always acting, or thinking, according to those principles. In terms of Kant s general laws of logic, we can see this as saying that every act of the understanding strives towards adherence with the laws of logic. It is not just that our thought is assessable in light of these laws, which is also certainly the case on this interpretation, it is that the activity itself is guided by the intention of adhering to those laws. Korsgaard provides an intuitive example of how to further understand this notion of guided by: The presence of both a noun and a verb in an English sentence is constitutive of its being a sentence, that is, of its expressing a complete thought. Yet those of us whose work includes grading papers have all encountered the verbless string of words that wants to be a sentence and fails, and yet is not mere gibberish. There is such a thing as speaking English badly, and it is not quite the same as not speaking at all, although importantly it tends in that direction. For if you ignore the rules of English altogether, what you speak will simply not be English. (Korsgaard (2009, 30)) The act of writing the incorrect yet not gibberish sentence involves striving towards a correct sentence; when I am writing I am not actively aware of the grammatical rules of English, but my action is guided by those rules in that I am writing a sentence in English. The rules of 20

23 English grammar are not normative in that the product of the writing is assessable in light of these rules, but that the activity of writing an English sentence is compelled by those rules. If the laws of logic are constitutive principles in Korsgaard s terms then they should fulfill the two conditions for being norms for thought. It is possible to think incorrectly, yet one is compelled by the laws and is therefore identifying oneself with the laws while also being bound by them. The advantage that Korsgaard s account has over MacFarlane s is that is provides the sense that the laws of logic are active in relation to thought, they play some sort of role in creating the thought instead of being those laws that thought is merely assessable in light of. Despite this advantage over MacFarlane s interpretation, Korsgaard does not fully explain how it is possible to err on her account. It is the case that to think you must be guided by the laws of logic, but this notion of guided by is not made clear and this does not seem to explain why the laws of logic meet the first condition, Error. The laws of logic could constitute thought insofar as these laws guide the use of the understanding, while the understanding always succeeds in adhering to the laws. Thus, this interpretation succeeds in providing an account of the active nature of the laws of logic, but does not succeed in explaining how and why the laws of logic meet the first condition for normativity. My goal in this section has been to provide an example of the normative interpretation of the general nature of Kant s logic, show how it is inadequate as it stands, and go on to suggest ways which this description could be improved upon. Towards this goal I presented MacFarlane s account of Kant s general logic as definitively normative, and then showed how his interpretation, although plausible, is unsupported as it stands. I pointed out that MacFarlane s notion of a constitutive norm is the kind of notion we need to interpret Kant s laws of logic so that the problem described in the introduction can be avoided. Thus, the goal at hand is to find a way to further justify the existence of such constitutive norms for logic, 21

24 and how they stem from the general logic. I also pointed out that the notion of constitutive norm we are searching for should be of an active sort, somehow explaining the normative force that necessarily compels every thought towards logical adherence. MacFarlane draws an analogy between the categorical imperative in Kant s moral philosophy and the constitutive necessity inherent in the laws of logic, and on Korsgaard s account we find a similar analogy as well. In the next section I will explore how the moral law on Kant s account is to be interpreted as normative, constitutive, or both with the goal of drawing the proper analogy with the laws of logic. 4 The Moral Law and the Laws of Logic 4.1 Both Normative and Non-Normative Kant s moral philosophy is taken as a paradigm account of presenting a normative law. The categorical imperative states that one must act only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law (Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, 4:421). 6 The categorical imperative is absolutely general in that it is objectively necessary for all action without reference to another end. The normative nature of the categorical imperative is that it is an imperative, which is defined by Kant in the following way: All imperatives are expressed by an ought and indicate by this the relation of an objective law of reason to a will that by its subjective constitution is not necessarily determined by it (a necessitation). They say that to do or to omit something would be good, but they say it to a will that does not always do something just because it is represented to it that it would be good to do that thing. (Groundwork, 4:413) 6 Throughout the rest of the essay I will abbreviate the title of this work as Groundwork. 22

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez

Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez Logical Mistakes, Logical Aliens, and the Laws of Kant's Pure General Logic Chicago February 21 st 2018 Tyke Nunez 1 Introduction (1) Normativists: logic's laws are unconditional norms for how we ought

More information

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 35 The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper, I will critically examine Christine Korsgaard s claim

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical [Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical Samuel J. Kerstein Ethicists distinguish between categorical

More information

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( )

Important dates. PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since David Hume ( ) PSY 3360 / CGS 3325 Historical Perspectives on Psychology Minds and Machines since 1600 Dr. Peter Assmann Spring 2018 Important dates Feb 14 Term paper draft due Upload paper to E-Learning https://elearning.utdallas.edu

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling Kantian Review, 20, 2,301 311 KantianReview, 2015 doi:10.1017/s1369415415000060 Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling owen ware Simon Fraser University Email: owenjware@gmail.com Abstract In this article

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome Instrumental reasoning* John Broome For: Rationality, Rules and Structure, edited by Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn, Kluwer. * This paper was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions Suppose.... Kant You are a good swimmer and one day at the beach you notice someone who is drowning offshore. Consider the following three scenarios. Which one would Kant says exhibits a good will? Even

More information

A Priori Bootstrapping

A Priori Bootstrapping A Priori Bootstrapping Ralph Wedgwood In this essay, I shall explore the problems that are raised by a certain traditional sceptical paradox. My conclusion, at the end of this essay, will be that the most

More information

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values

J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values J. L. Mackie The Subjectivity of Values The following excerpt is from Mackie s The Subjectivity of Values, originally published in 1977 as the first chapter in his book, Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong.

More information

Overview of Today s Lecture

Overview of Today s Lecture Branden Fitelson Philosophy 12A Notes 1 Overview of Today s Lecture Music: Robin Trower, Daydream (King Biscuit Flower Hour concert, 1977) Administrative Stuff (lots of it) Course Website/Syllabus [i.e.,

More information

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-31-2006 The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Timothy

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will Alex Cavender Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division 1 An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS Philosophical Books Vol. 49 No. 2 April 2008 pp. 125 137 AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS andrews reath The University of California, Riverside I Several

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 As one of the world s great religions, Christianity has been one of the supreme

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Kantian Ethics I. Context II. The Good Will III. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation of Universal Law IV. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation

More information

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7

Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 Issue 1 Spring 2016 Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy Kant On The A Priority of Space: A Critique Arjun Sawhney - The University of Toronto pp. 4-7 For details of submission dates and guidelines please

More information

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals (hereafter Grounding) presents us with the metaphysical

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7 Kantian Deontology Deontological (based on duty) ethical theory established by Emmanuel Kant in The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Part of the enlightenment

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Statements involving necessity or strict universality could never be known on the basis of sense experience, and are thus known (if known at all) a priori.

More information

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE

PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE PHILOSOPHY ESSAY ADVICE One: What ought to be the primary objective of your essay? The primary objective of your essay is not simply to present information or arguments, but to put forward a cogent argument

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC

PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE OVERVIEW FREGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC AND LANGUAGE JONNY MCINTOSH 1. FREGE'S CONCEPTION OF LOGIC OVERVIEW These lectures cover material for paper 108, Philosophy of Logic and Language. They will focus on issues in philosophy

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Class #26 Kant s Copernican Revolution The Synthetic A Priori Forms of Intuition Marcus, Modern Philosophy,

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics Abstract: Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics We will explore the problem of the manner in which the world may be divided into parts, and how this affects the application of logic.

More information

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/81838/

More information

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism Idealism Enlightenment Puzzle How do these fit into a scientific picture of the world? Norms Necessity Universality Mind Idealism The dominant 19th-century response: often today called anti-realism Everything

More information

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes

Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes Is Truth the Primary Epistemic Goal? Joseph Barnes I. Motivation: what hangs on this question? II. How Primary? III. Kvanvig's argument that truth isn't the primary epistemic goal IV. David's argument

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God? Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God? by Kel Good A very interesting attempt to avoid the conclusion that God's foreknowledge is inconsistent with creaturely freedom is an essay entitled

More information

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. PHI 110 Lecture 29 1 Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. Last time we talked about the good will and Kant defined the good will as the free rational will which acts

More information

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00

The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective. Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00 The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different Perspective Amy Wang Junior Paper Advisor : Hans Lottenbach due Wednesday,1/5/00 0 The Kant vs. Hume debate in Contemporary Ethics : A Different

More information

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth

Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1 Conventionalism and the linguistic doctrine of logical truth 1.1 Introduction Quine s work on analyticity, translation, and reference has sweeping philosophical implications. In his first important philosophical

More information

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY

TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY TWO APPROACHES TO INSTRUMENTAL RATIONALITY AND BELIEF CONSISTENCY BY JOHN BRUNERO JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. 1, NO. 1 APRIL 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BRUNERO 2005 I N SPEAKING

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori Ralph Wedgwood When philosophers explain the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, they usually characterize the a priori negatively, as involving

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions

Practical Rationality and Ethics. Basic Terms and Positions Practical Rationality and Ethics Basic Terms and Positions Practical reasons and moral ought Reasons are given in answer to the sorts of questions ethics seeks to answer: What should I do? How should I

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle Simon Rippon Suppose that people always have reason to take the means to the ends that they intend. 1 Then it would appear that people s intentions to

More information

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker.

2. Refutations can be stronger or weaker. Lecture 8: Refutation Philosophy 130 October 25 & 27, 2016 O Rourke I. Administrative A. Schedule see syllabus as well! B. Questions? II. Refutation A. Arguments are typically used to establish conclusions.

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical Aporia vol. 26 no. 1 2016 Contingency in Korsgaard s Metaethics: Obligating the Moral and Radical Skeptic Calvin Baker Introduction In this paper I offer an account of Christine Korsgaard s metaethical

More information

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the Autonomous Account University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2017 Mar 31st, 10:30 AM - 11:00 AM On the Rawlsian Anthropology and the "Autonomous" Account

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 20 Lecture - 20 Critical Philosophy: Kant s objectives

More information

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities

C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know. D. Discussion of extra credit opportunities Lecture 8: Refutation Philosophy 130 March 19 & 24, 2015 O Rourke I. Administrative A. Roll B. Schedule C. Exam #1 comments on difficult spots; if you have questions about this, please let me know D. Discussion

More information

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA

Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive. Behavior. Jacob Roundtree. Colby College Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME USA Understanding How we Come to Experience Purposive Behavior Jacob Roundtree Colby College 6984 Mayflower Hill, Waterville, ME 04901 USA 1-347-241-4272 Ludwig von Mises, one of the Great 20 th Century economists,

More information

Informalizing Formal Logic

Informalizing Formal Logic Informalizing Formal Logic Antonis Kakas Department of Computer Science, University of Cyprus, Cyprus antonis@ucy.ac.cy Abstract. This paper discusses how the basic notions of formal logic can be expressed

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3.0. Overview Derivations can also be used to tell when a claim of entailment does not follow from the principles for conjunction. 2.3.1. When enough is enough

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial. TitleKant's Concept of Happiness: Within Author(s) Hirose, Yuzo Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial Citation Philosophy, Psychology, and Compara 43-49 Issue Date 2010-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143022

More information

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel FAQ Search Memberlist Usergroups Profile You have no new messages Log out [ perrysa ] cforum Forum Index -> The Religion & Culture Web Forum Split Topic Control Panel Using the form below you can split

More information

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism 25 R. M. Hare (1919 ) WALTER SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG Richard Mervyn Hare has written on a wide variety of topics, from Plato to the philosophy of language, religion, and education, as well as on applied ethics,

More information

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano The discipline of philosophy is practiced in two ways: by conversation and writing. In either case, it is extremely important that a

More information

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary

REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET. Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary 1 REASON AND PRACTICAL-REGRET Nate Wahrenberger, College of William and Mary Abstract: Christine Korsgaard argues that a practical reason (that is, a reason that counts in favor of an action) must motivate

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination MP_C12.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 103 12 Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination [II.] Reply [A. Knowledge in a broad sense] Consider all the objects of cognition, standing in an ordered relation to each

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism

Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Fall 2010 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #14: October 13 Gödel s Platonism I. The Continuum Hypothesis and Its Independence The continuum problem

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2017

More information