EXPLANATION, CAUSATION AND DEDUCTION

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "EXPLANATION, CAUSATION AND DEDUCTION"

Transcription

1 EXPLANATION, CAUSATION AND DEDUCTION

2 THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE A SERIES OF BOOKS IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, METHODOLOGY, EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, HISTORY OF SCIENCE, AND RELATED FIELDS Managing Editor ROBERT E. BUTTS Dept. of Philosophy, University of Western Ontario, Canada Editorial Board JEFFREY BUB, University of Western Ontario L. JONATHAN COHEN, Queen's College, Oxford WILLIAM DEMOPOULOS, University of Western Ontario WILLIAM HARPER, University of Western Ontario JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University, Tallahassee CLIFFORD A. HOOKER, University of Newcastle HENRY E. KYBURG, JR., University of Rochester AUSONIO MARRAS, University of Western Ontario JURGEN MITTELSTRASS, Universitiit Konstanz JOHN M. NICHOLAS, University of Western Ontario GLENN A. PEARCE, University of Western Ontario BAS C. VAN FRAASSEN,Princeton University VOLUME 26

3 FRED WILSON Philosophy Department, University of Toronto, Canada EXPLANATION, CAUSATION AND DEDUCTION D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY A MEMBER OF THE KLUWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP DORDRECHT/BOSTON/LANCASTER

4 Libraty of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Wilson, Fred, Explanation, causation, and deduction. (The University of Western Ontario series in philosophy of science; v.26) Bibliography: p. Includes indexes. 1. Explanation (Philosophy) 2. Logic. 3. Causation. I. Title. II. Series. BD237.W ISBN-J3: e-isbn-j3: DOl: / Published by D. Reidel Publishing Company, P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, Holland Sold and distributed in the U.S.A. and Canada by Kluwer Academic Publishers, 190 Old Derby Street, Hingham, MA 02043, U.S.A. In all other countries, sold and distributed by Kluwer Academic Publishers Group P.O. Box 322, 3300 AH Dordrecht, Holland D. Reidel Publishing Company is a member of the Kluwer Group. All Rights Reserved 1985 by D. Reidel Publishing Company Softcover reprint of the hardcover 1st edition 1985 No part of the material protected by this copyright notice may be reproduced or utilized in any foim or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the copyright owner

5 To Gustav Bergmann

6 TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER 1 / THE DEDUCTIVE MODEL OF EXPLANATION: A STATEMENT 1.1. Explanation and Deduction 1.2. The Humean Account of Laws 1.3. The Evidential Worth of Law-Assertions 1.4. That Some Explanations Are Better than Others 1.5. That Technical Rules of Computation Are Laws ix CHAPTER 2 / THE REASONABILITY OF THE DEDUCTIVE MODEL Why Ought the Deductive Model Be Accepted? Are There Reasoned Predictions Which Are Not Explanations? Is Correlation Less Explanatory than Causation? Is Causation Inseparable from Action? Are There Explanations Without Predictions? Explanation and Judgment 159 CHAPTER 3 / EXPLANATIONS AND EXPLAININGS 3.1. Explanations in the Context of Communication 3.2. Formalist Criticisms of the Deductive Model 3.3. Explanations and Explanatory Content 3.4. Narrative and Integrating Explanations 3.5. Are Laws Evidence for, or Part of, Explanations? 3.6. Can We Know Causes Without Knowing Laws? CONCLUSION NOTES Notes to Chapter 1 Notes to Chapter vii

7 viii T ABLE OF CONTENTS Notes to Chapter Notes to Conclusion 365 BIBLIOGRAPHY 367 NAME INDEX 375 SUBJECT INDEX 377

8 The purpose of this essay is to defend the deductive-nomological model of explanation against a number of criticisms that have been made of it. It has traditionally been thought that scientific explanations were causal and that scientific explanations involved deduction from laws. In recent years, however, this three-fold identity has been challenged: there are, it is argued, causal explanations that are not scientific, scientific explanations that are not deductive, deductions from laws that are neither causal explanations nor scientific explanations, and causal explanations that involve no deductions from laws. The aim of the present essay is to defend the traditional identities, and to show that the more recent attempts at invalidating them fail in their object. More specifically, this essay argues that a Humean version of the deductive-nomological model of explanation can be defended as (1) the correct account of scientific explanation of individual facts and processes, and as (2) the correct account of causal explanations of individual facts and processes. The deductive-nomological model holds that to explain an event E, say that a is G, one must find some initial conditions C, say that a is F, and a law or theory T such that T and C jointly entail E, and both are essential to the deduction. Thus, if the law T is 'All Fare G', or, iii symbols, '(x) (Fx :J Gx)" then the argument, assuming its premisses are true, and that the general premiss is a law, T: (x) (Fx :J Gx) C:Fa E: Ga will be an explanation of a's being G, and equally, if a's being F is observed prior to its being observed to be G, it will be a prediction of a's being G. Thus, to defend the deductive-nomological model of explanation is also to defend the symmetry thesis, that every explanation is a potential prediction an that every prediction - that is, every reasoned prediction, every prediction based on laws - is an explanation. The criticisms we shall be examining proceed largely by way of counterexample. One group attacks the model by way of the symmetry thesis, ix

9 x purporting to discover explanations which are not predictions and (reasoned) predictions which are not explanations. Another group attacks the model on formalist grounds, giving examples which satisfy the requirement of law-deduction but which do not seem to be explanations, or showing how, formally, any event seems to be able to explain any other event. A third group attacks the model on grounds that it fails to do justice to the pragmatics of explanation. A fourth group attacks the model on grounds that there are explanations, and, specifically, causal explanations, which do not involve laws or deduction from laws. Interestingly enough, as we shall see, the last three groups are not unrelated. For a matter-of-fact generalization 'All Fare G' to serve as a premiss in an explanatory argument, it must be a law. A necessary condition for a matter-of-fact generalization to be a law, is that it be true. This is not sufficient for a generalization to be a law, however, since there are true matter-of-fact generalizations, e.g., "all the coins now in my pocket are copper", which are, as one says, accidental generalities, i.e., not laws. In order to discuss the criticisms indicated above, it is necessary for this essay to take some stand on the issue of what constitutes a law. The position adopted is that of Hume (Treatise of Human Nature) and Mill (System of Logic) that what distinguishes those generalizations that count as laws and those that do not is contextual or pragmatic. Lawfulness is not a syntactic or semantic feature of generalizations but rather is, as Rescher (Scientific Explanation) puts it, a matter of imputation. A generalization is accepted as a law, or, as I shall say, is law-asserted just in case that we are prepared to use it for purposes of explanation, prediction, and the support of contrary-tofact conditionals. And one is justified in law-asserting a generalization just in case that the evidence for its truth has been collected in accordance with the rules of the scientific method. This is the position proposed by Humeand defended by Mill, and, more recently, Bergmann (Philosophy of Science), Nagel (The Structure of Science), and Rescher. The present essay does not undertake a full-scale defence of this Humean account of laws. It has, of course, come under attack recently, both by those, e.g., Armstrong (Universals and Scientific Realism), who speak of primitive necessary connections among properties - a theme that goes back to Aristotle - and by those, e.g., Lewis (Counterfactuals), who propose to analyze lawfulness in terms of possible worlds. But as a single essay cannot do everything, many of the points raised by these critics are not dealt with; the aim is not so much to look at objections to the Humean account of laws as to look at objections to the deductive-nomological model of explanation. For

10 xi this reason, while we adopt the Humean account of lawfulness, its defence is only sketched in, just enough for our purposes with no full-scale discussion attempted. In adopting the Humean account of laws, we introduce not merely the objective conditions of validity and true premisses for an argument to count as an explanation but also the subjective condition of the general premiss being supported by scientific evidence for an argument to be acceptable as an explanation. It is subjective because the evidence available varies from time to time and from person to person, so that a generalization may not be lawassertible at one time or for one person but law-assertible at another time or for another person. It therefore varies from subject to subject; and, unlike validity and truth, is not objective, independent of the subject. The thesis we are defending, then, is that law-deduction is necessary and sufficient for scientific explanations, bearing in mind that what renders a generalization a law is not a matter of either syntax or semantics nor, indeed, of truth alone, but also evidential context. Included in this thesis are the subtheses that there are no scientific explanations which are not potentially predictions, and no (law-based) predictions which are not explanations. Furthermore, also included is the subthesis that all causal explanations, insofar as they are genuine explanations, are scientific and therefore both deductive from laws and potentially predictions. Several gambits will be used in replying to the critics of the deductivenomological model as we attempt to show how their proposed counterexamples really do fit with that model. Thus. one of the immediate consequences of the Humean-contextualist account of laws is that an argument may be acceptable as explanatory in one evidential context but not in another. We shall make use of this point in several of our replies to critics of the deductive-nomological model of explanation. Another of the immediate consequences of the Humean account of laws is that, since we observe only a sample and not the population, and since a generalization is about a population and not the sample, we never have conclusive evidence that a generalization we assert or law-assert is true. It may well be, then, that a generalization the law-assertion of which is supported by available data is in fact false. Thus, an argument may well be subjectively acceptable as an explanation but still not an explanation if the objective condition of true premisses is not fulfilled We shall also make use of this point in replying to critics of the deductive-nomological model of explanation.

11 xii Deductive-nomological explanations interest us because they provide knowledge that permits prediction and control. That is, we have certain pragmatic interests in obtaining such knowledge. We also are sometimes interested in such explanations for their own sake; i.e., to speak with Veblen, we are interested in them out of idle curiosity. Now, one explanation may better satisfy these cognitive interests - pragmatic interests and idle curiosity - than does another. This permits us to distinguish better and worse among explanations according to the extent to which they satisfy the cognitive interests that motivate us to obtain explanations. We shall make extensive use of this point when we reply to critics of the deductive-nomological model. In particular, we shall discover that many of them fail to distinguish, what we shall insist are distinct, an argument being a non-explanation from an argument being a weak explanation. Those who claim to find predictions which are not explanations are often guilty of this confusion. It should be noted, by the way, that while our cognitive interests, that is, our subjective values, determine a scale of better and worse among explanatins, once that scale is give then whether or not an explanation falls at a higher or lower place on this scale is an objective matter. If we have two explanations available, and one is better than another on the scale of worth defined by our cognitive interests, then, other things being equal, it would be wrong to use the weaker, less desirable, explanation as an act of explaining something to someone. It is important to distinguish (I) and explanation, i.e., an argument, (2) the acceptability of an argument as an explanation, and (3) the use of an acceptable explanation in an act of explaining. In particular, an argument may be acceptable as an explanation but for all that not appropriate for use in an act of explaining. Critics of the deductive-nomological model often confuse an argument's being inappropriate for use in an act of explaining with its being a non-explanation. Some critics of the model tend to rely upon an assumption that any deductive-nomological explanation can have a law-premiss no more complicated in logical form than 'All F and G'. This is often the case with those who claim to have found explanations which are not predictions. These criticisms can be shown to be invalid once it is noted that there are laws in such explanations, and that these laws do not violate the symmetry thesis, but that the logical form of the explanatory argument is more complex than that of a syllogism in Barbara. The same point also serves to rebut criticisms based on the idea that some explanations somehow rely upon 'intuitive judgment' rather than scientific reason to determine their acceptability; and is relevant, too, to

12 xiii criticisms based on the idea that there are explanations which are causal but which do not involve laws, or law-deduction. Finally, the distinction between better and worse among explanations enables one to distinguish laws into various kinds, e.g. process laws, causal laws, correlations. Criticis of the deductive-nomological model are often guilty of confusing the concept of explanation with one of the special cases, very often that of causal explanation. However, while a law that gives a correlation may not yields a causal explanation, and may be weaker, or worse as an explanation, than a causal explanation, it does not follow, as too many wrongly infer, that correlations have no explanatory power, that arguments with correlations as their law-premisses are non-explanatory. The Humean version of the deductive-nomological model that we propose to defend is laid out in Chapter 1. This chapter is essentially exposition, rather than defence. It begins by stating briefly the thesis that explanation of individual events is by deduction from generalities and initial conditions. However, not all generalities yield explanations: for the latter, the general premiss must be a law. The thesis we are defending is that the Humean account of laws suffices. On this account, the characteristic of being lawlike is contextual: a generality is lawlike just in case that we are prepared to use it to support the assertion of counterfactual conditionals. It is then argued that some generalities are more worthy of being treated as lawlike than others; a generality is worthy of being treated as lawlike just in case that evidence for it has been gathered, or at least advanced, in terms of the norms of scientific research. This involves a crucial distinction between the objective and the subjective (or contextual) conditions that a deduction must satisfy before it can count as, or reasonably be used as, an explanation. Among the relevant contextual elements are matters of evidence. It is not the point of this essay to analyze the logic of confirmation. (Some aspects of this problem - or set of problems - are discussed in my Reasons and Revolutions, currently being prepared for publication.) But clearly, the topic is important enough for what we are about that the issues cannot be wholly avoided, and so a brief discussion of these matters is included. It is suggested that the basic patterns of confirmation are those described by Hume and John Stuart Mill. But, using some ideas of Peirce, it is also suggested that these patterns are compatible with ideas more recently presented by Kuhn. However, no full discussion of these points is attempted. Mill's account of the Principle of Causation leads directly to the idea of what Bergmann has called "process knowledge". It has been suggested by

13 xiv Bergmann that this notion provides an ideal or standard of excellence for the evaluation of explanations of individual facts and processes. This notion of better and worse explanations is developed in Chapter 1, and will play an important role in what follows. Again, the thrust of the discussion at this point is expository; defence of the notion will be given in Chapter 2. John Stuart Mill's views on confirmation have often been condemned as foolish. Chapter 1 attempts to show that Stuart Mill's position on the justification of the Principle of Causality and, more generally, on the confirmation of laws about laws is a position that is at least plausible, sufficiently plausible, anyway, to permit us to rely upon them for our limited purpose. That purpose is the defence of the Humean version of the deductivenomological model of explanation. This defence begins in Chapter 2. This chapter begins by outlining the positive reasons for accepting the model as one that -- relative to certain cognitive interests - ought to be adopted. It then proceeds to discuss various ways in which the deductive-nomological model has been challenged. It argues that, contrary to some, there are no reasoned predictions (Le., predictions based on deductions from laws) that are not explanations. It argues that, contrary to some, correlations provide explanations just as do causal relations. It argues that, contrary to some, the concept of causation is independent of that of action. It argues that, contrary to some, there do not exist explanations that are not also predictions. Throughout these arguments the distinction between process laws and imperfect knowledge that falls short of this ideal plays a crucial role: in general the argument is that the objections to the deductive-nomological model that we discuss appear successful only if this distinction is ignored. The chapter closes with a criticism of the views of those who hold that 'judgment' plays a role in explanation that is not allowed for by those who defend the deductive-nomological model. Chapter 3 develops the contrast between explanations and acts of explaining. In this context, it examines and rejects a number of recent formalist criticisms of the deductive-nomological model. The chapter then goes on to discuss whether laws are part of, rather than merely presupposed by, certain sorts of scientific explanation, and whether causes can be known, e.g., by 'judgment', without our also knowing laws. It is argued that laws are indeed part of scientific explanations, and that in knowing a cause one ipso facto knows a law. Generally speaking, aspects of the deductive-nomological model are developed only to the extent that they are needed for replying to critics. For example, the defence of the criteria for better and worse scientific

14 xv explanations of individual fact is merely sketched. Again, since our concern is with explanations of individual facts and events, another sort of deductive explanation, that of laws by theories, receives very little attention. Both these topics -- criteria for better and worse, and the nature of theoretical explanation - receive a more detailed discussion in my forthcoming Reasons and Revolutions. In this connection it is perhaps worth noting a proposal concerning explanations advanced by a number of recent authors such as Michael Friedman (,Explanation and Scientific Understanding', 1974) and Philip Kitcher (,Explanatory Unification', 1981). While these authors disagree about what constitutes unification (cf. Kitcher, 'Explanation, Conjunction and Unification', 1976), they do agree that "to explain is to unify" - Kitcher cites E. M. Forster's injunction: "Only connect" - and argue that models developed in accordance with this injunction ought to replace the now discredited covering law or deductive-nomological model. Now it seems obvious that in a sense I do not agree with this position, since the whole thrust of the present essay is to argue that the deductivenomological model has in fact not been discredited. That being so, there is no need to replace it. On the other hand, the injunction is not without merit: there is indeed a real point to the idea that explanation consists in unification. But of course, the deductive-nomological model already acknowledges this point. This model asserts that to explain an event is to subsume it and another, independent event, under a law that connects the two. It is part of the very idea of the deductive-nomological model that explanation of individual events consists in unifying those events by means of laws. There are, of course, degrees of unifying power. The connection between events that some laws establish is tighter than the connection established by other laws. What we argue below is that, so far as concerns individual events, the ideal of explanation is process knowledge. When one explains an event in terms of process knowledge, that event is located as part of the ongoing development of a system over time, a development for which the process knowledge enables one, on the basis of a knowledge of the present state of the system, to predict the state of the system at all future times and at all past times. Process knowledge fills in all details of a process. Thus, when an event is explained by means of process knowledge it is gaplessly connected to all other events in an ongoing process. In the case of individual events, then, the injunction "Only connect" is fulfilled to the greatest degree possible when process knowledge is attained.

15 xvi Kitcher, Friedman, and others who adopt their position are thus mistaken in their view that defending the deductive-nomological model is somehow incompatible with defending the thesis that explanation consists in unification. The notion that I'to explain is to unify" is, however, one that has its greatest impact at the level not of explanation of individual facts but at the level of theoretical explanation, the explanation of laws. Our cognitive interest in scope, as well as our interest in theories that can guide research into hitherto undiscovered laws, both lead us to seek theories that unify bodies of law. Such laws about laws (to use Mill's phrase) explain the laws they unify, and, insofar as they apply to areas where the specific laws are not yet known, they predict, and guide researchers to the discovery of, new laws. It is hard to over-estimate the importance of such unifying laws. Yet a thorough discussion of the issues would be out of place in t~e present essay, which has as its main focus of concern the explanation of individual facts rather that the explanation of laws. To this extent, then, a pur sua 1 of these aspects of the issues raised by Kitcher and Friedman is out of place. On the other hand, the issue cannot entirely be avoided, if only because the laws about laws, the unifying laws that explain other laws, can themselves at times be used to explain individual facts. The discussion of Mill in Chapter I gives an account of how certain sorts of generic over-hypotheses can unify more specific hypotheses. According to Kitcher ('Explanatory Unification', p. 519), "The problem of explanation is to specify which set of arguments we ought to accept for explanatory purposes given that we hold certain sentences to be true". The constraints on such arguments are contraints on the laws that appear in these explanatory arguments; and these constraints are themselves factual, that is, lawful. These conditions "jointly imposed by the presence of nonlogical expressions in the pattern and by the filling instructions" as well as "conditions on logical structure" (ibid., p. 518) are precisely the constraints imposed by the generic laws about laws that Mill discussed. The view that we sketch, then, of how theoretical explanation proceeds by unification is close indeed to that of Kitcher. Kitcher does not develop his position at any length. He does not attend to the two specific forms of theoretical unification that have played so great a role in the actual history of science, to wit, unification by means of a composition law, and unification by reducing one area (the macro-area) to another (the micro-area). Nor does Kitcher develop the idea that unifying theories are indispensable tools for guiding research. For a detailed analysis of a generic law and its role in concept formation, one might look at my essay 'Is Operationism Unjust to Temperature?'; and for their role in research

16 xvii two other essays 'Kuhn and Goodman: Revolutionary vs. Conservative Science', and 'A Note on Hempel on the Logic of Reduction', are relevant. Some aspects of the latter issue are also dealt with in Section 3.3, below. The whole complex of issues is discussed in some detail in another forthcoming essay of mine, Empiricism and Darwin's Science. Another topic that is certainly worth discussing is that of statistical explanations; but this too is almost completely ignored. This in spite of the fact that it is of considerable relevance to what we are about. I can only plead by way of excuse that one cannot deal at once with all the objections to the deductive-nomological model. The objections I have considered all fit together, so it is they that I have discussed, rather than challenges to the deductive-nomological model based on so-called 'statistical explanations'. If the reader wishes some very brief indication of my views on the latter, he might glance at my review of N. Rescher's Scientific Explanation. A number of critics of the deductive-nomological model who shall be discussed have been heavily influenced by the doctrine of so-called 'Oxford philosophy' that 'meaning is use'. I have critically evaluated the latter doctrine in a monograph, Meaning Is Use, currently being prepared for publication. Certain parts of the present work supplement and elaborate points about scientific explanation made more briefly in this latter monograph. It is my belief that many objections to the deductive-nomological model depend upon an inadequate analysis of certain examples of scientific theories and of certain historical developments of science. For that reason, I have ventured detailed analyses where appropriate. In particular, an extended analysis of geometrical optics occurs in Chapter 3. Much of this is straightforward physics, or history of science, yet I am convinced that only by presenting these straightforward things in a deliberately philosophical context can many objections to the deductive-nomological model be adequately met. It is also my view that it is sometimes important to know not only that a conclusion follows but also how it follows. Sometimes a knowledge of the logic of the deduction is important to understanding its philosophical implications. This is particularly so with respect to some points of Davidson and of Kim that are discussed in Chapter 3. I have therefore tried to present such deductions in sufficient detail to make clear what is going on. The result is no doubt more symbolic logic than is comfortable for many. My only excuse is that experience with students and colleagues over the years has convinced me that clear understanding can be attained only by a patient workingthrough of the details.

17 xviii I would also like to thank the following authors for permission to quote. from the works cited: S. Bromberger: 'Why-Questions'. First appeared in Mind and Cosmos: Essays in Contemporary Science and Philosophy, Robert Colodny, editor. Copyright by the University of Pittsburgh Press, Used by permission. A. W. Collins: 'Explanation and Causality'. Mind 7S (1966). Used by permission of the editor of Mind. D. Davidson: 'Causal Relations'. First published in Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967). Reprinted in D. Davidson: Actions and Events, Oxford University Press, Quoted from the latter by permission of the Oxford University Press. S. Toulmin: Philosophy of Science. Hutchison, Used by permission. G. H. von Wright: 'On the Logic and Epistemology of the Causal Relation'. First appeared in Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science IV, P. Suppes et al., editors. North-Holland Publishing Co., Used by permission. Portions of the following publications have been incorporated into the present essay: 'Hurne and Ducasse on Causal Inference from a Single Experiment', Philosophical Studies 3S (1979), pp Copyright 1979, D. Reidel Publishing Co. 'Goudge's Contribution to Philosophy of Science', in L. W. Sumner, J. G. Slater, and F. Wilson, (eds.), Pragmatism and Purpose: Essays in Honour of T. A. Goudge, University of Toronto Press, Toronto, Copyright 1980, University of Toronto Press. 'Mill on the Operation of Discovering and Proving General Propositions', Mill News Letter 17 (1982), pp Copyright 1982, University of Toronto Press. Editors and publishers are thanked for permission to include this material. A number of key ideas in this essay were developed at a Working Conference on Causality held at Dalhousie University, July-August All the participants should be thanked for the stimulation they provided. The organizer, David Braybrooke, deserves special thanks. So, too does the Canada Council which partially funded the conference. The draft of the book was completed while I was on leave from the University of Toronto in , made possible by a leave fellowship granted by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada.

EMPIRICISM AND DARWIN'S SCIENCE

EMPIRICISM AND DARWIN'S SCIENCE EMPIRICISM AND DARWIN'S SCIENCE THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE A SERIES OF BOOKS IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, METHODOLOGY, EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, HISTORY OF SCIENCE, AND RELATED

More information

HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. & ISAAC LEVI

HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. & ISAAC LEVI HENRY E. KYBURG, JR. & ISAAC LEVI PROFILES AN INTERNATIONAL SERIES ON CONTEMPORAR Y PHILOSOPHERS AND LOGICIANS EDITORS RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINIL UOTO, University of Helsinki EDITORIAL

More information

PROFILES EDITORS EDITORIAL BOARD. RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINILUOTO, University of Helsinki VOLUME 4

PROFILES EDITORS EDITORIAL BOARD. RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINILUOTO, University of Helsinki VOLUME 4 D.M.ARMSTRONG PROFILES AN INTERNATIONAL SERIES ON CONTEMPORAR Y PHILOSOPHERS AND LOGICIANS EDITORS RADU J. BOGDAN, Tulane University ILKKA NIINILUOTO, University of Helsinki EDITORIAL BOARD D. FQ>LLESDAL,

More information

EPISTEME. Editor: MARIO BUNGE Foundations and Philosophy of Science Unit, McGill University. Advisory Editorial Board:

EPISTEME. Editor: MARIO BUNGE Foundations and Philosophy of Science Unit, McGill University. Advisory Editorial Board: FORBIDDEN KNOWLEDGE EPISTEME A SERIES IN THE FOUNDATIONAL, METHODOLOGICAL, PHILOSOPHICAL, PSYCHOLOGICAL, SOCIOLOGICAL, AND POLITICAL ASPECTS OF THE SCIENCES, PURE AND APPLIED Editor: MARIO BUNGE Foundations

More information

SYNTHESE HISTORICAL LIBRARY

SYNTHESE HISTORICAL LIBRARY PIERRE GASSENDI SYNTHESE HISTORICAL LIBRARY TEXTS AND STUDIES IN THE HIS TOR Y OF LOGIC AND PHILOSOPHY Editors: N. KRETZMANN, Cornell University G. NUCHELMANS, University of Leyden Editorial Board: J.

More information

Managing Editor: Editors:

Managing Editor: Editors: SELF AND OTHERS SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University, Tallahassee Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON,

More information

The Oceanic Feeling. The Origins of Religious Sentiment in Ancient India

The Oceanic Feeling. The Origins of Religious Sentiment in Ancient India The Oceanic Feeling The Origins of Religious Sentiment in Ancient India Volume 3 Editors: Bimal K. Matilal Spalding Professor of Eastern Religions and Ethics, Oxford University, England J. Moussaieff Masson

More information

INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY

INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY INQUIRY AS INQUIRY: A LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC DISCOVERY JAAKKO HINTIKKA SELECTED PAPERS VOLUME 5 1. Ludwig Wittgenstein. Half-Truths and One-and-a-Half-Truths. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4091-4 2. Lingua Universalis

More information

THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT AND LEFT

THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT AND LEFT THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT AND LEFT THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONT ARlO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE A SERIES OF BOOKS IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, METHODOLOGY, EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, HISTORY OF SCIENCE, AND

More information

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood

Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood Detachment, Probability, and Maximum Likelihood GILBERT HARMAN PRINCETON UNIVERSITY When can we detach probability qualifications from our inductive conclusions? The following rule may seem plausible:

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD The Possibility of an All-Knowing God Jonathan L. Kvanvig Assistant Professor of Philosophy Texas A & M University Palgrave Macmillan Jonathan L. Kvanvig, 1986 Softcover

More information

SCIENCE IN REFLE CTiON

SCIENCE IN REFLE CTiON SCIENCE IN REFLE CTiON BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor ROBERT S. COHEN, Boston University Editorial Advisory Board ADOLF GRUNBAUM, University of Pittsburgh SYL VAN S. SCHWEBER, Brandeis

More information

JUSTICE, LAW, AND ARGUMENT

JUSTICE, LAW, AND ARGUMENT JUSTICE, LAW, AND ARGUMENT SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: J AAKKO HINTIKKA, Florida State University Editors: DONALD DAVIDSON,

More information

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis Mark Schroeder November 27, 2006 University of Southern California Buck-Passers Negative Thesis [B]eing valuable is not a property that provides us with reasons. Rather, to call something valuable is to

More information

PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC AND LOGICAL PHILOSOPHY

PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC AND LOGICAL PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHICAL LOGIC AND LOGICAL PHILOSOPHY Editorial Committee: Peter I. Bystrov, Institute of Philosophy, Russian Academy of Sciences, Moscow, Russia Arkady Blinov, Institute of Philosophy, Russian Academy

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

NOTES NOTES TO CHAPTER 1. rather than the more tedious "deducing a sentence about the explanandum".

NOTES NOTES TO CHAPTER 1. rather than the more tedious deducing a sentence about the explanandum. NOTES NOTES TO CHAPTER 1 1 Logic of Scientific Discovery, p. 59; his italics. 2 The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. II, p. 362, n. 7. 3 Book III, Ch. xii, Sec. 1. 4 Cf. M. Scriven, 'Explanations, Predictions,

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL

ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL ESSAYS IN HONOR OF CARL G. HEMPEL SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MATHEMATICAL METHODS OF SOCIAL

More information

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of

Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of Logic: Inductive Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises and a conclusion. The quality of an argument depends on at least two factors: the truth of the

More information

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1,

Logic: inductive. Draft: April 29, Logic is the study of the quality of arguments. An argument consists of a set of premises P1, Logic: inductive Penultimate version: please cite the entry to appear in: J. Lachs & R. Talisse (eds.), Encyclopedia of American Philosophy. New York: Routledge. Draft: April 29, 2006 Logic is the study

More information

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism

The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism The Problem of Induction and Popper s Deductivism Issues: I. Problem of Induction II. Popper s rejection of induction III. Salmon s critique of deductivism 2 I. The problem of induction 1. Inductive vs.

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism. Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument 1. The Scope of Skepticism Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 4: Skepticism Part 1: The Scope of Skepticism and Two Main Types of Skeptical Argument The scope of skeptical challenges can vary in a number

More information

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D.

Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws. William Russell Payne Ph.D. Some Good and Some Not so Good Arguments for Necessary Laws William Russell Payne Ph.D. The view that properties have their causal powers essentially, which I will here call property essentialism, has

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC

CONTENTS A SYSTEM OF LOGIC EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION NOTE ON THE TEXT. SELECTED BIBLIOGRAPHY XV xlix I /' ~, r ' o>

More information

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel

A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i. (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London. and. Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel A Puzzle about Knowing Conditionals i (final draft) Daniel Rothschild University College London and Levi Spectre The Open University of Israel Abstract: We present a puzzle about knowledge, probability

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility

Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Constructive Logic, Truth and Warranted Assertibility Greg Restall Department of Philosophy Macquarie University Version of May 20, 2000....................................................................

More information

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE LIKENESS TO TRUTH THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE A SERIES OF BOOKS IN PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, METHODOLOGY, EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, HISTORY OF SCIENCE, AND RELATED FIELDS

More information

International Institute of Philosophy Institut International de Philo sophie

International Institute of Philosophy Institut International de Philo sophie International Institute of Philosophy Institut International de Philo sophie La philosophie contemporaine Chroniques nouvelles par les soins de GUTTORM FL0ISTAD Universite d'oslo Tome 3 Philosophie de

More information

PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY

PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY PHENOMENOLOGICAL ASPECTS OF WITTGENSTEIN'S PHILOSOPHY SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Managing Editor: JAAKKO HINTIKKA, Boston University Editors:

More information

SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT]

SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT] SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MA TERIALISM [DIAMAT] J. M. BOCHENSKI SOVIET RUSSIAN DIALECTICAL MATERIALISM [DIAMAT] D. REIDEL PUBLISHING COMPANY DORDRECHT-HOLLAND Der Sowjet-Russische Dialektische Materialismus

More information

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1 DOUBTS ABOUT UNCERTAINTY WITHOUT ALL THE DOUBT NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH Norby s paper is divided into three main sections in which he introduces the storage hypothesis, gives reasons for rejecting it and then

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS

ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS ROBERT STALNAKER PRESUPPOSITIONS My aim is to sketch a general abstract account of the notion of presupposition, and to argue that the presupposition relation which linguists talk about should be explained

More information

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science.

We aim to cover in some detail a number of issues currently debated in the philosophy of natural and social science. UNIVERSITY of BERGEN DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY FIL 219 / 319 Fall 2017 PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE VITENSKAPSFILOSOFI Lectures (in English) Time Place Website Email Office Course description Prof. Sorin Bangu,

More information

THE EVENT OF DEATH: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ENQUIRY

THE EVENT OF DEATH: A PHENOMENOLOGICAL ENQUIRY MARTINUS NIJHOFF PHILOSOPHY LIBRARY VOLUME 23 For a complete list of volumes in this series see final page of the volume. The Event of Death: A Phenomenological Enquiry by Ingrid Leman-Stefanovic 1987

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony 700 arnon keren On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony ARNON KEREN 1. My wife tells me that it s raining, and as a result, I now have a reason to believe that it s raining. But what

More information

KNOWLEDGE AND DEMONSTRATION

KNOWLEDGE AND DEMONSTRATION KNOWLEDGE AND DEMONSTRATION The New Synthese Historical Library Texts and Studies in the History of Philosophy VOLUME 56 Managing Editor: SIMO KNUUTTILA, University of Helsinki Associate Editors: DANIEL

More information

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15

Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15 Philosophy of Science PHIL 241, MW 12:00-1:15 Naomi Fisher nfisher@clarku.edu (508) 793-7648 Office: 35 Beck (Philosophy) House (on the third floor) Office hours: MR 10:00-11:00 and by appointment Course

More information

STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION

STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION A THEODICY OF HELL STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION Volume 20 The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume. A THEODICY OF HELL by CHARLES SEYMOUR SPRINGER-SCIENCE+BUSINESS

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

Mark Schroeder. Slaves of the Passions. Melissa Barry Hume Studies Volume 36, Number 2 (2010), 225-228. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance of HUME STUDIES Terms and Conditions

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. Tractatus 6.3751 Author(s): Edwin B. Allaire Source: Analysis, Vol. 19, No. 5 (Apr., 1959), pp. 100-105 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of The Analysis Committee Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3326898

More information

EDUCATION AND CIVILIZATION

EDUCATION AND CIVILIZATION EDUCATION AND CIVILIZATION Education and Civilization by JAMES K. FEIBLEMAN 1987 MARTINUS NIJHOFF PUBLISHERS a member of t~e KWWER ACADEMIC PUBLISHERS GROUP 1111 DORDRECHT / BaSION / LANCASTER Distributors

More information

is knowledge normative?

is knowledge normative? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California March 20, 2015 is knowledge normative? Epistemology is, at least in part, a normative discipline. Epistemologists are concerned not simply with what people

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Lasersohn Comments on Lasersohn John MacFarlane September 29, 2006 I ll begin by saying a bit about Lasersohn s framework for relativist semantics and how it compares to the one I ve been recommending. I ll focus

More information

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence

Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 561-567 Scientific Progress, Verisimilitude, and Evidence Luca Tambolo Department of Philosophy, University of Trieste e-mail: l_tambolo@hotmail.com

More information

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome Instrumental reasoning* John Broome For: Rationality, Rules and Structure, edited by Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn, Kluwer. * This paper was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish

More information

Realism and instrumentalism

Realism and instrumentalism Published in H. Pashler (Ed.) The Encyclopedia of the Mind (2013), Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, pp. 633 636 doi:10.4135/9781452257044 mark.sprevak@ed.ac.uk Realism and instrumentalism Mark Sprevak

More information

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994):

Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, Sustainability. Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994): The White Horse Press Full citation: Attfield, Robin, and Barry Wilkins, "Sustainability." Environmental Values 3, no. 2, (1994): 155-158. http://www.environmentandsociety.org/node/5515 Rights: All rights

More information

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT

REASONS AND ENTAILMENT REASONS AND ENTAILMENT Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl Erkenntnis 66 (2007): 353-374 Published version available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10670-007-9041-6 Abstract: What is the relation between

More information

BETWEEN HISTORY AND METHOD

BETWEEN HISTORY AND METHOD BETWEEN HISTORY AND METHOD BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE Editor ROBERTS. COHEN, Boston University Editorial Advisory Board THOMAS F. GLICK, Boston University ADOLF GR0NBAUM, University of

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999):

Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): Etchemendy, Tarski, and Logical Consequence 1 Jared Bates, University of Missouri Southwest Philosophy Review 15 (1999): 47 54. Abstract: John Etchemendy (1990) has argued that Tarski's definition of logical

More information

Guides to Straight Thinking With 13 Common Fallacies

Guides to Straight Thinking With 13 Common Fallacies Guides to Straight Thinking With 13 Common Fallacies vii Foreword That was a fine speech the Senator made! I didn t think much of it; they say he never went beyond grade school. What is wrong with this

More information

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN

UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN UNIVERSITY OF ALBERTA MATHEMATICS AS MAKE-BELIEVE: A CONSTRUCTIVE EMPIRICIST ACCOUNT SARAH HOFFMAN A thesis submitted to the Faculty of graduate Studies and Research in partial fulfillment of the requirements

More information

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos):

3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos): Propuesta de curso o seminario 1. Nombre del profesor: Martin Glazier 2. Nombre del curso o seminario: Explanation and ground 3. Campos de conocimiento en los que podría ser anunciado (máximo dos): Metafísica

More information

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE

ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE ON CAUSAL AND CONSTRUCTIVE MODELLING OF BELIEF CHANGE A. V. RAVISHANKAR SARMA Our life in various phases can be construed as involving continuous belief revision activity with a bundle of accepted beliefs,

More information

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism

Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2015 Mar 28th, 2:00 PM - 2:30 PM Van Inwagen's modal argument for incompatibilism Katerina

More information

CBT and Christianity

CBT and Christianity CBT and Christianity CBT and Christianity Strategies and Resources for Reconciling Faith in Therapy Michael L. Free This edition first published 2015 2015 Michael L. Free Registered Office John Wiley

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH

CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH CLASS #17: CHALLENGES TO POSITIVISM/BEHAVIORAL APPROACH I. Challenges to Confirmation A. The Inductivist Turkey B. Discovery vs. Justification 1. Discovery 2. Justification C. Hume's Problem 1. Inductive

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus

Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus University of Groningen Qualitative and quantitative inference to the best theory. reply to iikka Niiniluoto Kuipers, Theodorus Published in: EPRINTS-BOOK-TITLE IMPORTANT NOTE: You are advised to consult

More information

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames Brigham Young University BYU ScholarsArchive All Faculty Publications 1986-05-08 HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames Noel B. Reynolds Brigham Young University - Provo, nbr@byu.edu Follow this and additional

More information

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian?

Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian? Is Epistemic Probability Pascalian? James B. Freeman Hunter College of The City University of New York ABSTRACT: What does it mean to say that if the premises of an argument are true, the conclusion is

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS

SCHAFFER S DEMON NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS SCHAFFER S DEMON by NATHAN BALLANTYNE AND IAN EVANS Abstract: Jonathan Schaffer (2010) has summoned a new sort of demon which he calls the debasing demon that apparently threatens all of our purported

More information

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking

Christ-Centered Critical Thinking. Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking Christ-Centered Critical Thinking Lesson 6: Evaluating Thinking 1 In this lesson we will learn: To evaluate our thinking and the thinking of others using the Intellectual Standards Two approaches to evaluating

More information

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason Alexander R. Pruss Department of Philosophy Baylor University October 8, 2015 Contents The Principle of Sufficient Reason Against the PSR Chance Fundamental

More information

W. K. CLIFFORD AND WILLIAM JAMES ON DOXASTIC NORMS

W. K. CLIFFORD AND WILLIAM JAMES ON DOXASTIC NORMS W. K. CLIFFORD AND WILLIAM JAMES ON DOXASTIC NORMS Alberto OYA Abstract The main aim of this paper is to explain and analyze the debate between W. K. Clifford ( The Ethics of Belief, 1877) and William

More information

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science?

Phil 1103 Review. Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? Phil 1103 Review Also: Scientific realism vs. anti-realism Can philosophers criticise science? 1. Copernican Revolution Students should be familiar with the basic historical facts of the Copernican revolution.

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana

Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana Copyright 2015 by KAD International All rights reserved. Published in the Ghana http://kadint.net/our-journal.html The Problem of the Truth of the Counterfactual Conditionals in the Context of Modal Realism

More information

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief

Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief Introduction: Belief vs Degrees of Belief Hannes Leitgeb LMU Munich October 2014 My three lectures will be devoted to answering this question: How does rational (all-or-nothing) belief relate to degrees

More information

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Author(s): Christopher Belanger Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science,

More information

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS Biophysics of Consciousness: A Foundational Approach R. R. Poznanski, J. A. Tuszynski and T. E. Feinberg Copyright 2017 World Scientific, Singapore. FOREWORD: ADDRESSING THE HARD PROBLEM OF CONSCIOUSNESS

More information

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens.

There are two common forms of deductively valid conditional argument: modus ponens and modus tollens. INTRODUCTION TO LOGICAL THINKING Lecture 6: Two types of argument and their role in science: Deduction and induction 1. Deductive arguments Arguments that claim to provide logically conclusive grounds

More information

PROBLEMS OF THE LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE

PROBLEMS OF THE LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE PROBLEMS OF THE LOGIC OF SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE SYNTHESE LIBRARY MONOGRAPHS ON EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGIC, METHODOLOGY, PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE, SOCIOLOGY OF SCIENCE AND OF KNOWLEDGE, AND ON THE MATHEMATICAL METHODS

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF H1STOR Y AND ACTION

PHILOSOPHY OF H1STOR Y AND ACTION PHILOSOPHY OF H1STOR Y AND ACTION PHILOSOPHICAL STUDIES SERIES IN PHILOSOPHY Editors: WI L F RID S ELL A R S, University of Pittsburgh KEITH LEHRER, University of Arizona Board of Consulting Editors: JONATHAN

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN

Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge. University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN [Final manuscript. Published in Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews] Gary Ebbs, Carnap, Quine, and Putnam on Methods of Inquiry, Cambridge University Press, 2017, 278pp., $99.99 (hbk), ISBN 9781107178151

More information

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne

THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1. Steffen Ducheyne Philosophica 76 (2005) pp. 5-10 THE CHALLENGES FOR EARLY MODERN PHILOSOPHY: EDITORIAL INTRODUCTION 1 Steffen Ducheyne 1. Introduction to the Current Volume In the volume at hand, I have the honour of appearing

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece

What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece What is the Nature of Logic? Judy Pelham Philosophy, York University, Canada July 16, 2013 Pan-Hellenic Logic Symposium Athens, Greece Outline of this Talk 1. What is the nature of logic? Some history

More information

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan

Skepticism is True. Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Abraham Meidan Skepticism is True Copyright 2004 Abraham Meidan All rights reserved. Universal Publishers Boca Raton, Florida USA 2004 ISBN: 1-58112-504-6 www.universal-publishers.com

More information

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction...

The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions. Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction Defining induction... The problems of induction in scientific inquiry: Challenges and solutions Table of Contents 1.0 Introduction... 2 2.0 Defining induction... 2 3.0 Induction versus deduction... 2 4.0 Hume's descriptive

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis The focus on the problem of knowledge was in the very core of my researches even before my Ph.D thesis, therefore the investigation of Kant s philosophy in the process

More information

Class 6 - Scientific Method

Class 6 - Scientific Method 2 3 Philosophy 2 3 : Intuitions and Philosophy Fall 2011 Hamilton College Russell Marcus I. Holism, Reflective Equilibrium, and Science Class 6 - Scientific Method Our course is centrally concerned with

More information

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1

Reductio ad Absurdum, Modulation, and Logical Forms. Miguel López-Astorga 1 International Journal of Philosophy and Theology June 25, Vol. 3, No., pp. 59-65 ISSN: 2333-575 (Print), 2333-5769 (Online) Copyright The Author(s). All Rights Reserved. Published by American Research

More information

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory Journal of Educational Measurement Spring 2013, Vol. 50, No. 1, pp. 110 114 Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory Denny Borsboom University of Amsterdam Keith A. Markus John Jay College of Criminal Justice

More information

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS

AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX. Byron KALDIS AN EPISTEMIC PARADOX Byron KALDIS Consider the following statement made by R. Aron: "It can no doubt be maintained, in the spirit of philosophical exactness, that every historical fact is a construct,

More information