CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35. Guidance and Belief

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35. Guidance and Belief"

Transcription

1 CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY Supplementary Volume 35 Guidance and Belief There is a difference between those things one does that manifest agency and those things that merely happen to one or that are the effects of one s agency. My typing these words manifests my agency is an action of mine whereas growing older is merely happening to me and making sounds as I type is but an effect of my action. Actions are sometimes but not always done for reasons and are characteristically but perhaps not invariably known by the agent without observation or inference. I m typing in order to get my paper done on time, and I don t need to look to know that this is what I am doing, though I wouldn t know without hearing it that I am making noises as I type. In this paper I will offer an account of these facts about action. The account starts from the idea that an agent performing an action guides what she is doing. The account I will develop is meant to contrast with what is now the dominant view, which aims to understand action and acting for a reason in causal terms. This dominant view has three parts. One is a causal theory of action. It holds that whether what a person is doing manifests agency depends on what caused her to do it, on the events that brought the action about. A second part is a causal theory of acting for a reason. It holds that when a person is doing something for a reason, those reasons caused her to be doing it. On one version of the dominant view, all actions are done for reasons, so that a person is performing an action only if her reasons made her do it. The third part of the dominant view is a causal conception of beliefs, desires, and intentions. It holds that these are internal bodily states fit to cause actions, and so fit to be reasons for action. My typing these words is an action, on this picture, because my doing it was caused by the internal psychological states that are the reasons for my 63

2 typing. 1 This package of views, linking a causal conception of action and of acting for a reason with a causal conception of belief and other psychological states, forms a familiar and compelling picture. But the conception of action at the core of this picture is not mandatory. Some theorists hold that whether something is an action depends on what else is true of the agent at the time of the action and not on the action s causes. Harry Frankfurt (1978) holds that an agent is performing an action when she is guiding what she is doing. Elizabeth Anscombe (1963) claimed that an agent is doing something intentionally performing an action when she knows independently of observation what she is doing. Though there are important differences in their views on action, Frankfurt and Anscombe agree that whether an agent is performing an action depends on what else is true of the agent at the time of the action, and not on what caused her to perform it. 2 This non-causalist view of action does not fit comfortably with the other two parts of the dominant picture. If something s being an action is not a matter of its causes, then why should an action s being done for a reason be a matter of its causes? And if an action s reasons are not among its causes, then why should we think that beliefs, desires, and intentions must be internal bodily states fit to cause actions? Indeed, why even think that beliefs, desires, and intentions 1 Two additional theses are usually added to this package. One concerns the identity of actions and holds that actions are in every case identical with bodily movements. The other thesis concerns explanation and holds that reasons both cause and explain actions. I won t discuss either additional thesis here in any depth. 2 One striking difference is that whereas Frankfurt was a compatibilist about free will and determinism, Anscombe is not. It is not clear to me whether Frankfurt would agree with Anscombe that actions are essentially known without observation. He says that his construals of having reasons and of rational behaviour do not include any essential reference to beliefs (Frankfurt 2002, 62). While he allows that spiders and snakes are capable of rational behaviour, he is reluctant to ascribe beliefs to them, saying that they are not sufficiently self-conscious to understand or to articulate for themselves what they are up to. I agree that spiders and snakes cannot articulate what they are up to, but I deny that it follows that they do not know or have beliefs about what they are up to. But I am also not sure what substantive matter hangs on this. It might be a merely terminological choice about how to use the word belief. 64

3 Guidance and Belief are reasons for action in the first place? Abandoning a causal conception of action thus makes room for us to consider alternative conceptions of acting for a reason and of the nature of belief, desire, and intention. Here is the alternative I propose. An agent is performing an action when she is guiding what she is doing, regardless of what caused her to be doing it. Guiding what one is doing is a matter of being ready to adjust one s performance in the face of obstacles and to move on to the next phase or part of the action when the time is right. To say that someone is performing an action is thus to say something about her guidance dispositions. Guidance dispositions are also relevant to understanding acting for a reason and the nature of belief. To describe an agent s reasons for doing something and to say what she believes is to say something, not about internal states fit to cause actions, but about her guidance dispositions, about how she is likely to act and react in various situations as she goes about performing her actions. One virtue of this proposal is that it provides a straightforward explanation of Anscombe s insight that agents know what they are doing without the need for observation or inference: the dispositions involved in guiding an action are the very same as those involved in being aware of it. Guidance is the practical face and belief the theoretical face of a single phenomenon. This proposal can be a genuine alternative to the dominant view only if its central notion of guidance is not itself a causal notion. It is very natural to think that for an agent to guide what she s doing is for her (or for her internal states) to be ready to cause changes in the flow or direction of her behaviour. This would be to think of our relation to our actions as like that of a captain to his ship, or a driver to her car. Some causal theorists have even adopted a guidance condition, so that actions, on their view, are propelled and then guided in a certain way by beliefs in conjunction with desires and/or intentions. So unless guidance can be understood in some other way than as causal intervention, a guidance account of action and belief will constitute no real alternative to the dominant causal view. Fully developing and defending a guidance conception of action, belief and reason that does not collapse into a causal account is beyond the scope of this paper. My aim here is to sketch the outlines of such 65

4 a conception and to show that it constitutes a viable alternative to the traditional causal conception. 3 I will start, in section 1, but offering a dispositional way to understand the thought that agents guide what they are doing when they act. In section 2, I use this notion of guidance to ground an account of belief. In section 3, I show that these notions of guidance and belief can help us to understand what it is to act for one reason rather than another and why it is that agent s tend to know independently of observation what action they are performing. I conclude, in section 4, by rejecting reasons to think that the central notion of guidance must ultimately be understood in causal terms. 1. Action and Guidance When one performs an action one guides what one is doing. Guiding what one is doing involves being ready to respond to obstacles that threaten to block one s performance and being ready to move on to the next phase or stage of the action when the time is right. Guiding what one is doing thus requires having what I will call guidance dispositions. This means that action statement both report actual events and predict possible ones. To say that Jones is making tea reports an actual event, since the statement is false if no event of tea-making is in fact underway, and it predicts possible ones, since the statement is false if Jones is not disposed to do what it takes to get the tea made. The aim of this section is to elaborate on these points. Let me start by saying something about how I am using the word action. 4 (I will sometimes say that an agent performing an action is doing the thing intentionally.) I use it to mark those cases where an agent s doing something manifests her agency. I have in mind a contrast between things that an agent herself does and things that merely happen to (or within) her, or that she does but only as a consequence of and not as a manifestation of her agency. So there are in fact many 3 For recent non-causalist views of action, see Scott Sehon (2005) and Fred Schueler (2003). One difference between their views and mine is that, as far as I can see anyway, both Sehon and Schueler hold that actions are invariably done for reasons. In the cited works, both offer non-causal, teleological accounts of the explanation of actions in terms of reasons. I won t say much here about explanation. 4 This usage is described by Frankfurt (1978). 66

5 Guidance and Belief contrasts here. Though examples seem easy to come by, there are also a variety of borderline cases, and it is not easy to find a general characteristic. My typing these words is an action, whereas my getting older and my falling toward the centre of the Earth are not, even though I am doing both things. They are merely happening to me. So the notion of action I have in mind is meant to capture a contrast between being active and being passive. But there are other contrasts in the neighbourhood. My cat is climbing the stairs and this is an action. But in doing so she is also moving dust particles, and this is not an action, though she is not exactly passive with respect to it. Moving the particles is a consequence of her agency, not a manifestation of it. So action in the sense I have in mind is also meant to contrast with those things an agent does but only as a byproduct of exercises of her agency. Part of the problem of action, of course, is to try to bring some clarity and system to these contrasts. Two more contrasts are worth mentioning here. Actions are sometimes intended, in the sense that the agent planned in advance on doing them. But actions are not invariably intentional in this sense. My cat s climbing the stairs is an action, even if, as seems reasonable given her limited cognitive capacities, it is not something that the cat intended or decided in advance to do. The fish s swimming in the tank is an action, but not one that was planned or intended in advance. So while all intended actions are of course actions, not all actions are intentional, in this sense. A related point is that actions are sometimes done for a reason or with a purpose in mind, but this too is not invariably the case. 5 My pacing back and forth as I lecture is an action, but not one done for a reason. 6 My cat might be climbing the stairs to get to the litter box, but she might also just be climbing them for no particular reason. Her climbing would be an action would be 5 What I have called the dominant view tends to neglect such cases of action, focusing instead on actions done for a reason. This focus might be due to the fact that the original dialectic concerned the explanation of actions in terms of reasons, with causalists and non-causalists in opposing camps on this issue. I won t say much here about how to explain actions, whether done for reasons or not. 6 Sergio Tenenbaum calls such actions non-intentional but voluntary (2007, 90 99). What is important for my purposes is the fact that they manifest agency. I won t discuss voluntary action here. 67

6 something that she is doing, as opposed to something that is merely happening to her or that is a mere consequence of her agency even though she is not doing it for a reason. That action statements report actual happenings is not controversial. 7 It is entailed by the standard view that an action just is an event caused in a certain way. But it is worth noting that it does not follow that action statements report current bodily movements. For an action statement may be true even when the agent is not engaged in any movement relevant to the action, and even when she is motionless. 8 I may be making a pot of tea as I sit reading my book, even though none of my current movements are parts of my tea-making activity. My tea-making does not call for me to move. I am waiting for the water to boil. I think that a good deal of what I am now doing (writing a book on belief, paying down my mortgage, training for a running race, and so on) does not at this moment call for me to move. So the fact that action statements report current happenings does not mean that action statements report current bodily movements. Still, even with this qualification, the idea that to say what someone is doing is to report an actual event or happening is not controversial. 9 It is also not controversial that an action statement predicts possible happenings, though this is perhaps less often noted. An action statement involves two sorts of predictions, one concerning how the 7 I should note that some theorists hold that actions are not themselves events. On one such view, actions are the causings of bodily behaviours, and causings are not themselves events. See Bach (1980), and Alvarez and Hyman (1998). But this view is compatible with the claim that an action statement reports an occurrence of an event, though on this view the event reported would not be the action reported. I won t consider this view here. 8 Falvey (2000) characterizes this as the broadness of actions describable with the progressive aspect. The relevance of this to an account of action is stressed in Thompson (2008). 9 Another terminological note. One might want to reserve the word event for something that comes to pass as opposed to something that is merely underway. It is often noted that something that is underway might never come to pass: I was making a pot of tea even though no tea-making ever happened, because I changed my mind or was prevented from finishing. One might want to describe this by saying that no tea-making event occurred, even though a tea-making was underway. I won t take a stand on this issue. 68

7 Guidance and Belief agent would respond to obstacles to the successful performance of the action and the other concerning the progress of the action through its typical phases or stages. That an action statement involves these predictions reflects the fact that in performing an action an agent guides what she is doing. Harry Frankfurt introduced the idea that in acting an agent guides what she s doing by considering when the complexity in an agent s behaviour indicates that the she is performing an action: Complexity of bodily movement suggests action only when it leads us to think that the body, during the course of its movements, is under the agent s guidance. The performance of an action is accordingly a complex event, which is comprised by a bodily movement and by whatever state of affairs or activity constitutes the agent s guidance of it. Given a bodily movement which occurs under the agent s guidance, the person is performing an action regardless of what features of his prior causal history account for the fact that this is occurring. He is performing an action even if its occurrence is due to chance. And he is not performing an action if the movements are not under his guidance as they proceed, even if he himself provided the antecedent causes in the form of beliefs, desires, intentions, decisions, volitions or whatever from which the movement has resulted. (Frankfurt 1978, 73) On Frankfurt s view, an agent is doing something intentionally performing an action only when she is guiding what she is doing. To say that an agent is guiding what she is doing is to say something about her dispositions, about what she would do in various situations. It is thus to make a kind of prediction. Frankfurt says that action is intentional movement, by which I take it he means intentional bodily movement. I agree that actions often involve bodily movements and it may be that only a being able to perform bodily movements could be an agent. But, as I noted above, one can be performing an action without bodily movements. And there are cases where the agent s guidance seems to be aimed at something other than bodily movement. Guiding the steeping of the tea is part of what it is to make tea. After I pour the water into the teapot, I m ready to intervene if needed to ensure that the steeping is not interrupted (by my cat, say) and to make sure that it does not proceed too long. My guidance 69

8 dispositions are aimed, it seems, not at my body s movements, but at the changes in the tea. This is so even though the interventions that would manifest this guidance would involve guided bodily movements. So the guidance involved in action is not, as Frankfurt seems to suggest, limited to the guidance of bodily movements. There are two confusions about guidance to be avoided here, though the first is probably harmless. One is to think that it is the action that the agent guides. The idea, rather, is that it is what the agent is doing, not the action, that the agent is guiding. As the cat climbs the stairs, she is guiding her progress up the stairs, and the fact that she is guiding it is what makes what she is doing the performance of an action it is what makes it a manifestation of her agency. To guide an action would be, on this usage, to guide a guided doing. It might make sense to think of guiding someone else s action, as when a piano teacher guides a student s playing. But in such a case the student s playing the guided action would not be a manifestation of the teacher s own agency. It is best, I suggest, to think of an action as guided doing. Still, this confusion is probably harmless, in the way that speaking of the justification for a piece of knowledge is harmless, when strictly speaking it is the belief that is justified, not the knowledge. A second confusion is perhaps more significant. It is to think that an agent s guidance of what she s doing is itself an action or that it somehow involves her acting on her bodily movements or on what she s doing. Guiding what one is doing is not something that one does: it is, rather, a way of doing something. To say that an agent is guiding what she s doing is to describe her dispositions, not to describe something else that she is doing over and above the action she is performing. The passive formulation, a doing that is under the agent s guidance is better than the active, guiding what she is doing, at capturing this aspect of the account. A related confusion would be to think that guiding what one is doing must involve acting on one s bodily movements. This is the confusion of thinking of our selves as like a captain who guides his ship s course by acting on the rudder, or like a driver who guides her car s movements by acting on the steering wheel or the brakes. I take it that an agent is not related in that way to her bodily movements when she is performing an action. Guiding what one is doing is not itself an action, nor is it a matter of acting on bodily movements. Rather, guiding what one is doing 70

9 Guidance and Belief is a matter of how one is disposed to move or act in various situations. The trick, of course, is to understand how guidance, understood purely dispositionally, can make the difference between something that manifests agency and something that does not. How can adding something that seems essentially passive yield agency? I think this question is at the heart of the problem of agency and I will return to it below. Though guiding what one is doing is not itself an action, it can and perhaps always does involve being ready to perform actions. As the cat intentionally climbs the stairs she is ready to move to the side should she encounter an obstacle, and were she to move to the side this would likely be something that she would do intentionally; it would also be guided behaviour. So the dispositions that constitute her guidance may include dispositions to perform actions of one sort or another. This is, I think, the typical case. But from the fact that guiding one s behaviour includes being disposed to perform actions it does not follow that guiding one s behaviour is itself an action or that it somehow involves acting on one s behaviour. Guiding what one is doing involves two sorts of dispositions. First, it requires being ready to make adjustments in response to possible obstacles. Frankfurt drew attention to these cases. Here is how Kent Bach, another of the first theorists to draw attention to the need for guidance in an analysis of action, put the point: [S]ome actions are more routine than others, requiring little if any attention, no decisions or flexibility during performance, hence minimal awareness. Indeed, if the action is not only routine but repetitive, maximal efficiency may require minimal awareness too much attention may slow one down and cause unwanted variations in performance. On the other hand, a novel, intricate action, like attempting an untried surgical technique, may require continuous, detailed, and accurate awareness of what one is doing. On must be alert to the slightest unforeseen contingency and be ready to alter one s course of action accordingly. (Bach 1978, 368) If Jones is turning on the light intentionally, then he must be ready as he raises his hand towards the switch to adjust his movements in whatever ways would be needed in order to get the light switched on. 71

10 He must, for instance, be ready to use more force if he finds that the switch is stuck. A cat intentionally climbing the stairs must be ready, if the situation calls for it, to adjust his path up the stairs if he encounters an obstacle. Of course, one possible response in the face of an obstacle is to abandon the action altogether. So whether an agent is doing something intentionally whether his doing it counts as an action of his depends on whether he is ready to adjust what he s doing in response to unforeseen contingencies. Because unforeseen contingencies are always possible for any action, guidance is essential to action. Guiding what one is doing also requires a second kind of disposition. It requires being ready to perform the next phase or part of the action when the time is right. This is clear in cases when the action is a complex one. Making an omelette involves breaking eggs into a container of some kind, mixing them, heating a pan, pouring the eggs into the pan, etc. When we say that Sarah is making an omelette, we are saying that she is more or less ready to perform each stage or phase when the time is right. Some actions involve a strictly ordered sequence of parts or phases, while others do not. But all actions, even such a simple one as switching on the light, involve parts or phases. Turning off the light requires first reaching up to the light switch, touching the switch, pushing it, etc. All actions, even the simplest ones, take time and so consist of parts or phases. This means that performing an action always requires being ready to perform the next part or phase when the time is right. Performing an action requires having guidance dispositions, but this does not mean that we can specify for each action type a set of dispositions that is necessary and peculiar to its performance. There are many reasons for this. For one thing, there are usually different ways to perform an action of a certain kind even in a given context, and the range of potential obstacles may vary from one circumstance to another. For another thing, some agents are better than others at performing certain actions, and this is a matter of training and experience among other things. Knowing this may influence what dispositions we expect an agent to have when we say that they are performing some action. So what dispositions we expect an agent to have when we make an action statement is a context-dependent matter. Let me summarize what I have been saying about guidance and action. To say that an agent is doing something intentionally is both 72

11 Guidance and Belief to report an actual event and to predict possible ones. Performing an action requires being ready to adjust one s behaviour as needed in order to get the job done, either because obstacles have emerged or because it is time for a next phase or stage in the action. These guidance dispositions typically include dispositions to perform various actions. Thus, to say that an agent is doing something is not to make a purely categorical statement about the occurrence of some event, nor is it to make a purely dispositional claim about the agent of the event. It is, rather, to make what Ryle once called a mongrel statement, one that both reports an actual event and predicts possible ones Guidance and Belief I want to turn now to belief. To say what an agent believes is to describe her conception of things, to characterize the world as she takes it to be. An agent s conception interacts with her actions in different ways. For one thing, an agent s conception of her world may include the fact that she is performing some action. It may even include facts about why and how she is doing it. I think that doing something intentionally requires believing that you are doing it, and in the next section I will consider how we should understand this requirement. But an agent s beliefs are also relevant to her guidance of what she is doing, and understanding this gets us to the nature of belief itself. The aim of this section is to develop this idea. All sides can agree that to say what an agent believes is to say something about what she would do in various situations. Here is one way to put the thought: to believe that p is to be disposed to act as if it were the case that p. But it would be good to elaborate on acting as if it were the case. The fact that action requires guidance suggests the following elaboration: to believe that p is to guide what one is doing in ways that would be effective if it were the case that p. According to this proposal, the dispositions associated with belief are guidance dispositions. I said that an action statement is a sort of mongrel statement involving both a report and a prediction. The same, I think, is true of belief ascriptions. In saying what someone believes, we are not just 10 Gilbert Ryle (1949, 141). 73

12 predicting possible occurrences, for her current actions are also being guided in accordance with that conception. To say what an agent believes is to say something about the path that she is in fact taking. In describing an agent s beliefs we are identifying a world in which she is doing certain things, for certain reasons, and in certain ways. In fact, we identify a space of possible worlds, differing one from another in terms of possible obstacles and effective responses. In identifying this space, we are characterizing the path that she would follow in a world that is as she takes the actual world to be. Belief ascriptions are thus also a sort of mongrel statement: they both predict possible occurrences (how she would behave in counterfactual worlds) and report on actual ones (how she acting in the actual world.) The guidance account of belief helps us to understand why citing a belief might be relevant in explaining an agent s action even if, as I think, citing a belief is not citing a cause of the action. To ascribe a belief is to say something about the path along which the agent is guiding what she s doing. Suppose we see Jones on the neighbour s front porch, pressing a button. When asked why he s doing that, we explain that he is trying to find the neighbours and believes that the button is a doorbell. In saying that our agent believes that the button is a doorbell we are saying that he is guiding his activity that of seeing if the neighbours are at home in a way that would be effective in a world in which that button is a doorbell. We are saying something, not about the causes of his behaviour, but about the path that behaviour is in fact taking, and the paths it would take in various possible situations. We are, in other words, saying something about how he is going about doing what he is doing and about what he would do if various obstacles arose. On this account, citing an agent s belief can explain his actions by providing a richer understanding of the how and why of that action. This result should not be surprising if, as I have suggested, both action-ascriptions and belief-ascriptions are mongrel statements, both reporting an actual occurrence and predicting possible ones. If this is right, then it is a confusion to think that in ascribing beliefs we are saying something altogether different about an agent than what we are saying in ascribing actions. One might have thought that in ascribing an action we are only mentioning an event, whereas in ascribing a belief we are only mentioning a disposition. But if such ascriptions are 74

13 Guidance and Belief both mongrel statements, both reporting an actual occurrence and predicting possible ones, then there is no such deep distinction in subject matter between belief ascriptions and action ascriptions. Both sorts of ascriptions describe the very same phenomenon, though from a different perspective or with a different focus. Action reports tend to focus on the actual occurrence while belief reports focus more on the possible ones, though both say something about both kinds. If this is the right way to think of belief ascriptions, then it ought not to be surprising that belief ascriptions can explain actions without citing causes. Fully developing this conception of belief is beyond the scope of this paper. In the remainder I want to explore the idea that agency can be grounded in mere dispositions. I realize that this idea can seem puzzling, even paradoxical. Dispositions can seem to be the paradigm of passivity, the polar extreme of action. Some theorists have argued, for different reasons, that guidance itself must be understood in causal terms if it is to ground agency. I don t agree and think that the urge to appeal to causation may rest on confusion about agency and possibility. In the next two sections, I will argue that the guidance account of belief and action can help us to understand fundamental features of agency: acting for a reason and the special awareness agents seem to have of their own actions. I will then end the paper by considering, and rejecting, reasons to think that guidance must in the end be understood in causal terms Guidance and Acting for a Reason The guidance accounts of action and belief can help us to understand several key marks of agency. First, it allows us to distinguish what an agent is doing intentionally from what she is doing knowingly but non-intentionally. Second, it allows us to understand what it is for an agent to act on one reason rather than another. Finally, it allows us to understand the special sort of awareness that an agent seems to have 11 I have not offered a reductive account of action. Guidance dispositions include dispositions to perform actions. One might think that this threatens a vicious regress, one that could only be stopped by something categorical (as opposed to dispositional) or by something dispositional that is not a disposition to act. I won t consider this threat here. 75

14 of her own action. Each of these is an essential mark of agency. So a guidance account of action can help us to understand at least some of what seems central to agency. In this section I consider the first two points, and I turn to the third point in the next section. Whether an agent is doing something intentionally depends on her guidance dispositions. This means that guidance dispositions are relevant to determining what actions an agent is performing. Whether my cat is climbing the stairs intentionally depends (inter alia) on whether she is prepared to do what it takes to accomplish that to act to overcome obstacles should an obstacle emerge and to move on to the next stage or phase of the action when the time is right. That guidance dispositions are relevant in this way is now, I think, fairly widely accepted among theorists of action. But it is perhaps not as widely recognized that guidance dispositions are also relevant to marking off those things that an agent is doing intentionally from those things that she is doing knowingly but non-intentionally. As I type these words I am making noises, and I know that I am. But I am not making them intentionally, whereas I am typing intentionally. The relevant difference is that, while I am ready to make adjustments in my behaviour to ensure that my typing gets done, I am not ready to make adjustments to ensure that the noise is being made. Indeed, given that my daughters are asleep in the next room and might be woken by the noise, I d be happy if I could type without making the noise. The air-force bomber who knowingly kills the civilians while intentionally destroying the factory is not killing them intentionally unless he is ready to adjust his behaviour as needed to ensure that they are killed and this is so even if he knows that he is killing them by bombing the factory. So a guidance account of action can help us to distinguish an agent s actions from things that she is doing knowingly but that are not actions. A guidance account of action can also help us to understand what it is for agents to act for reasons. By acting for a reason I have in mind cases when an agent does something with a further goal or aim in mind. We ordinarily describe such cases using a sentence like: S is doing X in order to Y. I put the kettle of water on to boil in order to make tea. The cat is climbing the stairs in order to get to her litter box, or because she wants to get to her litter box. (There are important differences here, but since they won t matter for my purposes, I will set them aside.) 76

15 Guidance and Belief One point to keep in mind is that something s being an action is not the same as its being done for a reason or on purpose, and the guidance account of action can help us to understand this. A fish that swims from one side of her tank to another is manifesting her agency, but she may not be swimming for any reason. When I pace back and forth, my pacing is something that I am doing and not merely something that is happening to me, or a consequence of my actions. But I may be pacing for no reason at all. I m just pacing. So what an agent is doing might manifest her agency even though she has no further goal or aim in mind. The guidance account of action shows why, since in these cases the agent is guiding what she s doing, even though she s doing it for no reason. She s guiding it, and this manifests her agency, even though she is not doing it for a reason. It may be, of course, that not all of an agent s actions can be done for no reason. This certainly seems to be so in the case of mature humans. It is hard to make sense of the possibility of a person going through life or even through a significant stretch of time performing actions but all for no reason. But it is hard to know what to make of this fact, if it is a fact. It may point to something fundamental about agency itself. But it may instead point to the fact that mature humans have or develop rational capacities capacities to plan or to predict the future, say whose normal operation makes non-rational actions rare even though these capacities are not strictly needed for mere agency. In any case, it is clear that something s being a manifestation of agency is not the same as its being done for a reason, and the guidance account of action can help us to see this. The guidance account of action can also help us to understand what s going on in cases when an agent does act for a reason. More specifically, guidance dispositions are relevant to determining what reason an agent is acting on when she has several different reasons for doing what she is doing. 12 Suppose that Jones has two equally good reasons for marching: by marching he would obey his commander 12 Davidson (1963) had charged that a non-causal account of action explanation could not mark this difference. On his view, the best way to understand what it is for an agent to have acted on one set of reasons rather than another is for that first set to have caused the action. The response I develop in the text is also found in Sehon (2005). 77

16 and he would impress his girlfriend who is watching from the sidelines. Whether in the end he is marching to follow orders or to impress his girlfriend depends on how he would behave in various possible situations. Would he continue to march about once his commander is satisfied, or would he stop marching in that case, even if his girlfriend had not yet seen his marching? How he would act in these different cases is relevant to determining which reason is the one he is acting on. So guidance dispositions are relevant to determining what reasons an agent is in fact acting on in cases when she has more than one reason to act. It is worth noting that an agent may perform some action for many reasons at the same time, or even change reasons in mid-stream. Maybe Jones is ready both to do what it takes to satisfy his commander and to do what it takes to impress his girlfriend. If you ask him why he s marching, he ll mention both considerations. Perhaps as his marching progresses he ll drop one of those reasons in favour of the other. This would be reflected in a change in his dispositions. Or perhaps he ll adopt new reasons for marching, perhaps deciding that improving his own skills is at that moment more important than either obeying his commander of impressing his girlfriend. Again, such a change in his reasons would be reflected in a change in his dispositions. His action would remain the same, though his reason for performing it would change, and this would be marked by a change in how he is disposed to act in various situations. A guidance account of action can make perfectly good sense of cases where an agent acts on several distinct reasons or changes reasons in mid-performance. I have been arguing that guidance dispositions are relevant to explaining why an agent is performing an action. These dispositions are also relevant to determining how she is performing it. There are usually different ways to perform some action. Suppose that there are three ways to turn off the light. Since each of the ways of doing it is itself an action, each way of turning off the light requires a different set of guidance dispositions. So whether Jones is doing it one way or another will depend on her dispositions. This means that what guidance dispositions an agent has is relevant to determining not just why she is performing an action but also how she is performing it. 78

17 Guidance and Belief 4. Guidance and Agential Awareness I want to turn now to a further mark of agency, the fact that performing an action seems to require believing independently of observation that one is doing it. 13 It is not perfectly clear just what the requirement is here or what the relevant notion of observational independence is. But it does seem that an account of action and belief ought to help us to understand why there appears to be some such requirement. My aim in this section is to develop the following account of this: action seems to require belief because the dispositions that constitute an agent s guidance of her action also constitute her belief in it. The first point to make is that when an agent is performing an action the dispositions associated with her belief that she is are guidance dispositions. Consider again the idea that to believe that p is to guide one s actions in ways that would be effective if it were the case that p, and suppose that I am making a pot of tea. If I believe that the water is boiling, then I am ready to guide my tea-making in ways that would be effective in a world where the water is boiling. That s clear enough. But now consider my belief that I am making tea. This is a belief about an action that I am performing. What dispositions are associated with this belief? Well, my believing that I am making tea requires my being ready to guide my tea-making (which is an action) in ways that would be effective if I were making tea. What could this readiness be other than my being ready to do what it takes to make the tea? In other words, the dispositions involved in believing that I am making tea, when I am making tea, would seem to be the very dispositions associated with guiding my tea-making. This suggests that when someone is performing an action and believes that she is, that belief involves the very same dispositions as the action itself. But it also suggests more than this. It suggests that when an agent is performing an action, she will have the very dispositions that we would expect her to have if we took her to believe that she was doing it. The guidance dispositions I have as I make the tea are (or anyway, 13 That it does was a widely held view until the mid-1960s. It plays a central role in Anscombe (1963), Hampshire (1959) and Melden (1961). Davidson (1963) argued against it and these arguments seemed to hold sway until the idea was revived in Velleman (1989). There is now a large literature, some of it listed in the footnotes below. 79

18 seem to include) the dispositions that I would have (or would be expected to have) if I believed that I was making tea. In a way, this is not surprising, since the account of belief I have offered defines belief in terms of guidance. But this is not an objection, since any plausible account of belief will define it in terms of action. The point is that in the special case of an agent s beliefs about her own actions, the dispositions involved in that belief seem to be guidance dispositions. When viewed from the perspective of action, these dispositions seem practical, but when viewed from the perspective of belief, they look like cognitive dispositions. If this is right, then it suggests that action and belief, and perhaps even freedom and knowledge, are but two sides of a single coin. Exploring this is something I will save for another occasion. So a guidance account of action and belief can help us to understand why it might seem that performing an action requires belief in it. But it can also help us to understand why this belief might seem to be independent of observation. 14 It is worth distinguishing two ideas here. One concerns justification and holds that for an agent to be doing something intentionally her justification or evidence for believing that she is doing it must be independent of observation. The second idea concerns acquisition and holds that the fact that the agent has the belief must be independent of observation if she is to be doing it intentionally. I want to set aside the idea about justification and focus on the one about acquisition. The point I want to make is that if the dispositions associated with performing an action are or include those associated with believing in it, then this offers a simple explanation of the fact that such beliefs seem to be independent of observation, at least in terms of acquisition. An agent s guidance dispositions as she performs an action are independent of observation. It is true, of course, that guiding what one is doing requires being ready to respond to observations. I am ready to lift the kettle and pour the water into the pot once I see that the water has come to a boil. We can put this by saying that guidance dispositions are (or anyway include) sensitivities to what is observed. Doing something intentionally requires being ready to respond to the 14 This idea has roots in the works of Anscombe (1963) and Hampshire (1959). Recent discussion of it is in Moran (2004), Hursthouse (2000), and Falvey (2000). 80

19 Guidance and Belief passing scene. But guidance dispositions are independent of observation in the sense that the agent acquires the dispositions as she begins the action and loses them when she stops the action, and this correlation is independent of what she observes. It is what an agent is doing that determines her guidance dispositions, not what she is observing, and this determination is not undermined by the fact that observations may inform her actions. I will retain my dispositions to do what it takes to make the pot of tea so long as I am still making it, regardless of what I may observe, unless I decide to stop doing it. But if, as I have suggested, the dispositions associated with guiding an action are or include those associated with belief in it, then the fact that guidance dispositions are independent of observation in this sense would explain the fact that the belief seems also to be independent of observation. When an agent is performing an action, it will seem that she believes that she is and that this belief is independent of observation, since it is acquired once the action starts and disappears only when the action ends, regardless of what the agent may observe. I start believing that I am making a pot of tea as soon as I start to make the pot of tea and I stop believing it as soon as I stop what I m doing. I did not acquire my belief that I was making a pot of tea by observing my behaviours or movements or anything else. Likewise, I won t change my mind about whether I am making tea by observing my behaviours or movements, at least not so long as I am still in the process of making it. If I stop making a pot of tea, which I might do if I decide to make coffee instead or if I realize that I don t have enough time to make tea, then I will stop believing that I am. My belief is independent of observation in the sense that its duration coincides with changes in my activity and not with changes in my observations. It starts and stops with the action itself. The guidance account of action and belief thus promises a very elegant explanation of the fact (if it is a fact) that performing an action requires believing independently of observation that one is doing it. Some have tried to explain the belief requirement in terms of a special sense of agency, a perception-like capacity that produces and sustains the required belief, but I find the proposed capacity obscure and anyway this proposal would leave it a mere coincidence that acting requires practical and theoretical dispositions that are observationally 81

20 independent. 15 Others have tried to explain the belief requirement in terms of intention, either a prior intention or an intention-in-action, but like the appeal to a sense of agency this suggestion would leave it a mere coincidence that action requires observationally independent dispositions of both a practical and theoretical nature. 16 Another suggestion is that the action and believing share a cause, perhaps a prior intention, or a set of beliefs and desires, or a process of deliberation, or an act of willing. 17 But this couldn t be the general story since not all actions are antecedently intended, or result from deliberation, or are willed. My cat did not intend or deliberate about climbing the stairs, but she climbed them intentionally all the same, guiding and believing in her actions as she did. And even if this story could explain why the acting and believing begin together, it is not clear how it could explain why they persist together. I submit that the guidance explanation I have sketched promises a simpler and more satisfying account of the fact that performing an action seems to require special agential awareness. My proposal offers a neat explanation of the belief requirement: since acting requires guidance, if guidance constitutes belief then acting also requires belief. And it offers a neat explanation of the required belief s observational independence: since the guidance starts and stops when the acting starts and stops, if guidance constitutes belief then that belief will also start and stop with the action s start and stop (unless sustained in some other way). This proposal does not involve positing special perception-like capacities; it does not rely on ascribing essentially practical mental states like sustaining intentions; and since it does not imply that action is always a result of deliberation, it respects what is common across human 15 For a sample of recent views on this, see the essays in Roessler and Eilan (2003). 16 Moser and Mele (1994). Bach holds that guidance dispositions are associated with non-conscious mental representations, what he calls executive representations. He considers the idea that these representations might also be called intentions but dismisses it because, he says, calling non-conscious representations intentions would be Pickwickian (1978, 371). 17 For a development of the view that the belief is produced by deliberation, see Rödl (2007) and O Brien (2007). For a different version of the same idea, see Velleman (1989) and Setiya (2008). 82

21 Guidance and Belief and non-human action. Most importantly, it provides a satisfying explanation of the coincidence of theory and practice, a coincidence that will seem mysterious so long as guidance and belief are viewed as distinct phenomena. 5. Guidance and Causal Mechanisms I have argued that a guidance account of action and belief can help us to understand several key marks of agency. But it is central to this account that whether something is an action has nothing to do with its causes. It has seemed to many that only a causal account can explain agency. Causation can enter analyses of action and belief in various places and for various purposes. Frankfurt (1978) held that the notion of guidance is itself a causal one, to be understood in terms of an underlying mechanism set to produce changes in the agent s behaviour. Rowland Stout (2005), who follows Frankfurt on this point, has argued that only if such a causal mechanism is present can it be correct to say that the agent is the one guiding what she is doing. His hope is to rule out cases of deviant causation, where the agent s dispositions are grounded in external causal powers and not in the agent s own active powers. A similar hope prompted some causal theorists to say that the dispositions that indicate guidance are grounded in intentions (or intention-like) states that causally sustain the action and keep it on its path. I doubt that the concepts of action and belief require such causal mechanisms, and I am sceptical that appeal to them can help with cases of causal deviance. The aim of this section is to explain why. In denying that something s being an action is a matter of its causes, I do not mean to deny that the bodily movements involved in action are as likely as any other events to have causes. The movements of the cat s legs as she climbs the stairs are caused by something, and even if the physiological and physical story about these causes is not yet very well understood, I am not sceptical that some story involving physiological states, mechanisms, and properties can explain those movements. So the causal scepticism I want to develop in this section is not aimed at the movements themselves. Rather, what I doubt is, first, that the concepts of action and belief must be understood in terms of causal states or mechanisms and, second, that appealing to such states 83

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION

Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION Philosophical Writings Vol. 43 No.1 Special Issue: Proceedings of the British Post-Graduate Philosophy Association Annual Conference 2014 HOW NOT TO NATURALISE ACTION University College London Abstract:

More information

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect.

THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect. THE ROAD TO HELL by Alastair Norcross 1. Introduction: The Doctrine of the Double Effect. My concern in this paper is a distinction most commonly associated with the Doctrine of the Double Effect (DDE).

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1 DOUBTS ABOUT UNCERTAINTY WITHOUT ALL THE DOUBT NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH Norby s paper is divided into three main sections in which he introduces the storage hypothesis, gives reasons for rejecting it and then

More information

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements

Moral requirements are still not rational requirements ANALYSIS 59.3 JULY 1999 Moral requirements are still not rational requirements Paul Noordhof According to Michael Smith, the Rationalist makes the following conceptual claim. If it is right for agents

More information

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES?

DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES? MICHAEL S. MCKENNA DOES STRONG COMPATIBILISM SURVIVE FRANKFURT COUNTER-EXAMPLES? (Received in revised form 11 October 1996) Desperate for money, Eleanor and her father Roscoe plan to rob a bank. Roscoe

More information

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires.

Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires. Shieva Kleinschmidt [This is a draft I completed while at Rutgers. Please do not cite without permission.] Conditional Desires Abstract: There s an intuitive distinction between two types of desires: conditional

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

A New Argument Against Compatibilism Norwegian University of Life Sciences School of Economics and Business A New Argument Against Compatibilism Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Working Papers No. 2/ 2014 ISSN: 2464-1561 A New Argument

More information

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility

A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility A Compatibilist Account of Free Will and Moral Responsibility If Frankfurt is right, he has shown that moral responsibility is compatible with the denial of PAP, but he hasn t yet given us a detailed account

More information

Act individuation and basic acts

Act individuation and basic acts Act individuation and basic acts August 27, 2004 1 Arguments for a coarse-grained criterion of act-individuation........ 2 1.1 Argument from parsimony........................ 2 1.2 The problem of the relationship

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH

Reasons With Rationalism After All MICHAEL SMITH book symposium 521 Bratman, M.E. Forthcoming a. Intention, belief, practical, theoretical. In Spheres of Reason: New Essays on the Philosophy of Normativity, ed. Simon Robertson. Oxford: Oxford University

More information

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases

Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases Freedom, Responsibility, and Frankfurt-style Cases Bruce Macdonald University College London MPhilStud Masters in Philosophical Studies 1 Declaration I, Bruce Macdonald, confirm that the work presented

More information

Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley

Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley Primitive normativity and scepticism about rules Hannah Ginsborg, University of California, Berkeley In his Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language 1, Saul Kripke develops a skeptical argument against

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning?

Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning? Is mental content prior to linguistic meaning? Jeff Speaks September 23, 2004 1 The problem of intentionality....................... 3 2 Belief states and mental representations................. 5 2.1

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is

Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is The Flicker of Freedom: A Reply to Stump Note: This is the penultimate draft of an article the final and definitive version of which is scheduled to appear in an upcoming issue The Journal of Ethics. That

More information

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris

In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris. Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE. reviews/harris Defining free will away EDDY NAHMIAS ISN T ASKING FOR THE IMPOSSIBLE Free Will by Sam Harris (The Free Press),. /$. 110 In his pithy pamphlet Free Will, Sam Harris explains why he thinks free will is an

More information

Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person

Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person Harry Frankfurt Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person Up to this point we have been discussing the compatibility of determinism and what we might call free action. Our question has been: if determinism

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00. 106 AUSLEGUNG Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001. 303 pages, ISBN 0-262-19463-5. Hardback $35.00. Curran F. Douglass University of Kansas John Searle's Rationality in Action

More information

Belief as the Power to Judge

Belief as the Power to Judge Belief as the Power to Judge Nicholas Koziolek Forthcoming in Topoi Abstract A number of metaphysicians of powers have argued that we need to distinguish the actualization of a power from the effects of

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk.

Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x Hbk, Pbk. Nancey Murphy, Bodies and Souls, or Spirited Bodies? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). Pp. x +154. 33.25 Hbk, 12.99 Pbk. ISBN 0521676762. Nancey Murphy argues that Christians have nothing

More information

Agency Implies Weakness of Will

Agency Implies Weakness of Will Agency Implies Weakness of Will Agency Implies Weakness of Will 1 Abstract Notions of agency and of weakness of will clearly seem to be related to one another. This essay takes on a rather modest task

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy Volume 3, Number 9 Editor in Chief Kevin C. Klement, University of Massachusetts Editorial Board Gary Ebbs, Indiana University Bloomington Greg Frost-Arnold,

More information

Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism

Walter Terence Stace. Soft Determinism Walter Terence Stace Soft Determinism 1 Compatibilism and soft determinism Stace is not perhaps as convinced as d Holbach that determinism is true. (But that s not what makes him a compatibilist.) The

More information

Mental Causation and Ontology, S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, R. D. Ingthorsson, Mar 21, 2013, Philosophy, 272 pages. This book demonstrates the importance o

Mental Causation and Ontology, S. C. Gibb, E. J. Lowe, R. D. Ingthorsson, Mar 21, 2013, Philosophy, 272 pages. This book demonstrates the importance o Personal Agency: The Metaphysics of Mind and Action, E. J. Lowe, OUP Oxford, 2010, 0199592500, 9780199592500, 222 pages. Personal Agency consists of two parts. In Part II, a radically libertarian theory

More information

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY Michael Huemer, Skepticism and the Veil of Perception Chapter V. A Version of Foundationalism 1. A Principle of Foundational Justification 1. Mike's view is that there is a

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism?

Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism? Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism? Richard Swinburne [Swinburne, Richard, 2011, Could Anyone Justiably Believe Epiphenomenalism?, Journal of Consciousness Studies, vol 18, no 3-4, 2011, pp.196-216.]

More information

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31

A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31 A guide to Anscombe s Intention, 1-31 Jeff Speaks February 12, 2009 1 Different kinds of intention ( 1)......................... 1 2 Intentions to act and prediction ( 2-4)..................... 1 3 Intentional

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox

Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Wittgenstein and Moore s Paradox Marie McGinn, Norwich Introduction In Part II, Section x, of the Philosophical Investigations (PI ), Wittgenstein discusses what is known as Moore s Paradox. Wittgenstein

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Anscombe on 'Practical Knowledge'

Anscombe on 'Practical Knowledge' Anscombe on 'Practical Knowledge' RICHARD MORAN Among the legacies of Elizabeth Anscombe's 1957 monograph Intention are the introduction of the notion of 'practical knowledge' into contemporary philosophical

More information

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Self-ascriptions of mental states, whether in speech or thought, seem to have a unique status. Suppose I make an utterance of the form I

More information

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill

SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP. Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill Philosophical Issues, 14, Epistemology, 2004 SKEPTICISM, ABDUCTIVISM, AND THE EXPLANATORY GAP Ram Neta University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill I. Introduction:The Skeptical Problem and its Proposed Abductivist

More information

Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory

Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory Agency, Ownership, and the Standard Theory Markus E. Schlosser Forthcoming in J. Aguilar, A. Buckareff, and K. Frankish (eds.) New Waves in Philosophy of Action, Basingstoke: Macmillan This is the author

More information

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON

DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON NADEEM J.Z. HUSSAIN DISCUSSION THE GUISE OF A REASON The articles collected in David Velleman s The Possibility of Practical Reason are a snapshot or rather a film-strip of part of a philosophical endeavour

More information

Active Belief. The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters

Active Belief. The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Active Belief The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Boyle, Matthew. Forthcoming. Active belief. Canadian Journal

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle

Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle 1 Why I Am Not a Property Dualist By John R. Searle I have argued in a number of writings 1 that the philosophical part (though not the neurobiological part) of the traditional mind-body problem has a

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with

On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology. In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with On Some Alleged Consequences Of The Hartle-Hawking Cosmology In [3], Quentin Smith claims that the Hartle-Hawking cosmology is inconsistent with classical theism in a way which redounds to the discredit

More information

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social

Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Lecture One: The Aspiration for a Natural Science of the Social Explanation These lectures presuppose that the primary task of science is to explain. This does not mean that the only task of science is

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

Logical behaviourism

Logical behaviourism Michael Lacewing Logical behaviourism THE THEORY Logical behaviourism is a form of physicalism, but it does not attempt to reduce mental properties states, events and so on to physical properties directly.

More information

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach

Philosophy 5340 Epistemology. Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism. Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Philosophy 5340 Epistemology Topic 6: Theories of Justification: Foundationalism versus Coherentism Part 2: Susan Haack s Foundherentist Approach Susan Haack, "A Foundherentist Theory of Empirical Justification"

More information

Can a behaviourist admit that we have feelings or thoughts that we keep hidden?

Can a behaviourist admit that we have feelings or thoughts that we keep hidden? 1 Can a behaviourist admit that we have feelings or thoughts that we keep hidden? Introduction The term behaviourism is one that is used in many contexts, and so I will begin this essay by describing the

More information

Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects. Thomas James Quinn

Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects. Thomas James Quinn Agency: Humans, Animals and Objects Thomas James Quinn Submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Birkbeck College, University of London April 2017 1 I hereby declare that the work contained in this

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM

POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM POWERS, NECESSITY, AND DETERMINISM Thought 3:3 (2014): 225-229 ~Penultimate Draft~ The final publication is available at http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.1002/tht3.139/abstract Abstract: Stephen Mumford

More information

Reasoning and Regress MARKOS VALARIS University of New South Wales

Reasoning and Regress MARKOS VALARIS University of New South Wales Reasoning and Regress MARKOS VALARIS University of New South Wales m.valaris@unsw.edu.au Published in Mind. Please cite published version. Regress arguments have convinced many that reasoning cannot require

More information

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION BY D. JUSTIN COATES JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JANUARY 2014 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT D. JUSTIN COATES 2014 An Actual-Sequence Theory of Promotion ACCORDING TO HUMEAN THEORIES,

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION 11.1 Constitutive Rules Chapter 11 is not a general scrutiny of all of the norms governing assertion. Assertions may be subject to many different norms. Some norms

More information

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit Published online at Essays in Philosophy 7 (2005) Murphy, Page 1 of 9 REVIEW OF NEW ESSAYS ON SEMANTIC EXTERNALISM AND SELF-KNOWLEDGE, ED. SUSANA NUCCETELLI. CAMBRIDGE, MA: THE MIT PRESS. 2003. 317 PAGES.

More information

Motivation in Agents. The Humean theory of motivation remains the default position in much of the

Motivation in Agents. The Humean theory of motivation remains the default position in much of the Motivation in Agents Christian B. Miller Wake Forest University millerc@wfu.edu Noûs 42 (2008): 222-266 The Humean theory of motivation remains the default position in much of the contemporary literature

More information

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows:

In essence, Swinburne's argument is as follows: 9 [nt J Phil Re115:49-56 (1984). Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague. Printed in the Netherlands. NATURAL EVIL AND THE FREE WILL DEFENSE PAUL K. MOSER Loyola University of Chicago Recently Richard Swinburne

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Kate Nolfi UNC Chapel Hill (Forthcoming in Inquiry, Special Issue on the Nature of Belief, edited by Susanna Siegel) Abstract Epistemic evaluation is often appropriately

More information

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan

4 Liberty, Rationality, and Agency in Hobbes s Leviathan 1 Introduction Thomas Hobbes, at first glance, provides a coherent and easily identifiable concept of liberty. He seems to argue that agents are free to the extent that they are unimpeded in their actions

More information

A Priori Bootstrapping

A Priori Bootstrapping A Priori Bootstrapping Ralph Wedgwood In this essay, I shall explore the problems that are raised by a certain traditional sceptical paradox. My conclusion, at the end of this essay, will be that the most

More information

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) Thomas W. Polger, University of Cincinnati 1. Introduction David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work

More information

Ezio Di Nucci Automatic Actions: Challenging Causalism

Ezio Di Nucci Automatic Actions: Challenging Causalism RMM Vol. 2, 2011, 179 200 http://www.rmm-journal.de/ Ezio Di Nucci Automatic Actions: Challenging Causalism Abstract: I argue that so-called automatic actions routine performances that we successfully

More information

The Zygote Argument remixed

The Zygote Argument remixed Analysis Advance Access published January 27, 2011 The Zygote Argument remixed JOHN MARTIN FISCHER John and Mary have fully consensual sex, but they do not want to have a child, so they use contraception

More information

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues

Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues Aporia vol. 28 no. 2 2018 Phenomenology of Autonomy in Westlund and Wheelis Andrea Westlund, in Selflessness and Responsibility for Self, argues that for one to be autonomous or responsible for self one

More information

is knowledge normative?

is knowledge normative? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California March 20, 2015 is knowledge normative? Epistemology is, at least in part, a normative discipline. Epistemologists are concerned not simply with what people

More information

8 Internal and external reasons

8 Internal and external reasons ioo Rawls and Pascal's wager out how under-powered the supposed rational choice under ignorance is. Rawls' theory tries, in effect, to link politics with morality, and morality (or at least the relevant

More information

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid

Hence, you and your choices are a product of God's creation Psychological State. Stephen E. Schmid Questions about Hard Determinism Does Theism Imply Determinism? Assume there is a God and when God created the world God knew all the choices you (and others) were going to make. Hard determinism denies

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work. Article Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions Thornton, Tim Available at http://clok.uclan.ac.uk/4356/ Thornton, Tim (2011) Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions. Philosophy, Psychiatry,

More information

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2 FREEDOM OF CHOICE Human beings are capable of the following behavior that has not been observed in animals. We ask ourselves What should my goal in life be - if anything? Is there anything I should live

More information

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014

Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy. Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Philosophy 203 History of Modern Western Philosophy Russell Marcus Hamilton College Spring 2014 Class #23 Hume on the Self and Free Will Marcus, Modern Philosophy, Slide 1 Mindreading Video Marcus, Modern

More information

3. Knowledge and Justification

3. Knowledge and Justification THE PROBLEMS OF KNOWLEDGE 11 3. Knowledge and Justification We have been discussing the role of skeptical arguments in epistemology and have already made some progress in thinking about reasoning and belief.

More information

Klesis 2016 : 35 Lectures contemporaines de Elisabeth Anscombe PRACTICAL KNOWLEDGE OF WHAT HAPPENS : A READING OF 45

Klesis 2016 : 35 Lectures contemporaines de Elisabeth Anscombe PRACTICAL KNOWLEDGE OF WHAT HAPPENS : A READING OF 45 PRACTICAL KNOWLEDGE OF WHAT HAPPENS : A READING OF 45 Eylem Özaltun (Koç University, Istanbul) A reading of the passage should explain why it is there. Peter M. Sullivan 0. Introduction In Intention (1957),

More information

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity In these past few days I have become used to keeping my mind away from the senses; and I have become strongly aware that very little is truly known about bodies, whereas

More information

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS

CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN S PHILOSOPHICAL INVESTIGATIONS 42 Philosophy and Progress Philosophy and Progress: Vols. LVII-LVIII, January-June, July-December, 2015 ISSN 1607-2278 (Print), DOI : http://dx.doi.org/10.3329/pp.v57il-2.31203 CONCEPT OF WILLING IN WITTGENSTEIN

More information

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5)

SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) SUPPORT MATERIAL FOR 'DETERMINISM AND FREE WILL ' (UNIT 2 TOPIC 5) Introduction We often say things like 'I couldn't resist buying those trainers'. In saying this, we presumably mean that the desire to

More information

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith

DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN. Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith Draft only. Please do not copy or cite without permission. DESIRES AND BELIEFS OF ONE S OWN Geoffrey Sayre-McCord and Michael Smith Much work in recent moral psychology attempts to spell out what it is

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Let me state at the outset a basic point that will reappear again below with its justification. The title of this chapter (and many other discussions too) make it appear

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness

On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness On Dispositional HOT Theories of Consciousness Higher Order Thought (HOT) theories of consciousness contend that consciousness can be explicated in terms of a relation between mental states of different

More information

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no

Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws. blurring the distinction between two of these ways. Indeed, it will be argued here that no Belief, Rationality and Psychophysical Laws Davidson has argued 1 that the connection between belief and the constitutive ideal of rationality 2 precludes the possibility of their being any type-type identities

More information

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000).

Examining the nature of mind. Michael Daniels. A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Examining the nature of mind Michael Daniels A review of Understanding Consciousness by Max Velmans (Routledge, 2000). Max Velmans is Reader in Psychology at Goldsmiths College, University of London. Over

More information

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism

Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism; Naturalist Cognitivism Felix Pinkert 103 Ethics: Metaethics, University of Oxford, Hilary Term 2015 Cognitivism, Non-cognitivism, and the Humean Argument

More information

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Some proposals for understanding narrow content Some proposals for understanding narrow content February 3, 2004 1 What should we require of explanations of narrow content?......... 1 2 Narrow psychology as whatever is shared by intrinsic duplicates......

More information