Divine necessity. Einar Duenger Bohn. Abstract 1 INTRODUCTION 2 STRONG AND WEAK DIVINE NECESSITY ARTICLE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Divine necessity. Einar Duenger Bohn. Abstract 1 INTRODUCTION 2 STRONG AND WEAK DIVINE NECESSITY ARTICLE"

Transcription

1 Received: 28 April 2017 Revised: 1 August 2017 Accepted: 7 August 2017 DOI: /phc ARTICLE Divine necessity Einar Duenger Bohn University of Agder Correspondence Einar Duenger Bohn, Department of Religion, Philosophy and History, University of Agder Postboks 422, 4604 Kristiansand, Norway. einar.d.bohn@uia.no Abstract Divine necessity is the thesis that God must exist. In this paper, I give a brief survey of what the thesis is more exactly, the main arguments for it, and the main arguments against it. 1 INTRODUCTION From the claim that God must exist, it follows that God actually exists, but from the claim that God actually exists, it doesn't follow that God must exist. So even if God were to actually exist, we should still ask: must God exist? The thesis of what I call strong divine necessity is the claim that God must exist, from which it follows that God actually exists. The thesis of what I call weak divine necessity is the claim that if God actually exists, then God must exist, from which it obviously does not follow that God actually exists. But if we for independent reasons add the claim that God actually exists, it follows by weak divine necessity that God must exist; on the flip side, if we for independent reasons add the claim that it is not the case that God must exist, it follows from weak divine necessity that God actually doesn't exist. 1 On the other hand, if we for independent reasons discover that God actually exists, but didn't have to exist, it follows that both strong and weak divine necessity are false. 2 Strong and weak divine necessity are often not clearly separated, but they should be: They are logically different theses. Strong divine necessity entails weak divine necessity, but weak divine necessity does not entail strong divine necessity, hence the labels strong and weak. In this paper, I first clarify both strong and weak divine necessity (Section 2). Then I present and discuss a version of each of what I take to be the three main kinds of arguments for strong divine necessity (Section 3). Then I present and discuss a version of each of what I take to be the two main kinds of arguments against strong divine necessity (Section 4). Throughout, I also consider some interesting retreats to weak divine necessity. In the last section, I consider an alternative to divine necessity, what we might call divine absoluteness (Section 5). 2 STRONG AND WEAK DIVINE NECESSITY Again, the thesis of strong divine necessity is the claim that God must exist, i.e. God could not have failed to exist, and the thesis of weak divine necessity is the claim that if God actually exists, then God must exist, i.e. if God exists, then God could not have failed to exist. Unless noted otherwise, by God I mean the intentional being that is the ultimate ground of reality and worthy of worship. Hopefully, that is neutral enough to capture sufficiently many interesting notions of God. The question then is whether such an ultimate ground must exist, or could have failed to exist. By must and necessarily I mean metaphysical necessity in the sense of truth in any possible world, where a possible world is (circularly) explained as Philosophy Compass. 2017;e wileyonlinelibrary.com/journal/phc3 1of10

2 2of10 BOHN a complete way the world could have been. I define metaphysical possibility and impossibility as usual: possibly p if and only if not necessarily not p and impossibly p if and only if necessarily not p. I separate metaphysical necessity, which is truth in any possible world, from logical necessity, which is truth in any model. Arguably, there is a model for any possible world, but there is not a possible world for any model. So logical necessity entails metaphysical necessity, but metaphysical necessity does not entail logical necessity. Deducing a logical contradiction from a claim, and thus showing that it is logically impossible (i.e., has no model), is sufficient to show that it is metaphysically impossible (i.e., false in any possible world), but providing a model, and thus showing that it is logically possible, is not sufficient to show that there is a possible world like that, i.e., that it is metaphysically possible; there are logical possibilities that are not metaphysical possibilities. In short, I distinguish between metaphysics, which employs talk of truth in a possible world, and model theory, or pure logic, which employs talk of truth in a model; the latter is necessary but not sufficient for the former. 3 I take it the theses of divine necessity are theses of de re necessity, not de dicto necessity. Roughly, de re necessity is necessity ascribed to an object, while de dicto necessity is necessity ascribed to a claim, or a proposition. So, for example, the thesis of strong divine necessity claims that God necessarily exists, not merely that necessarily God exists. There is a substantial difference here. The de dicto claim requires only that the claim God exists is true in any possible world, independently of what makes it true from world to world; it might be one God in one world but another God in another world. The de re claim on the other hand requires that one and the same object has the property of existing in any possible world; it cannot be one God in one world and another God in another world but must be one and the same God in any possible world. 4 Note that this might involve a non deflationary notion of modality, i.e., a notion according to which modal properties of objects are real properties of those objects. In fact, until noted otherwise, I henceforth ignore all deflationary notions of modality. 5 This de re understanding of divine necessity might be a bit stronger than some prefer. 6 But note again that if divine necessity is formulated merely as the de dicto necessity of the claim that God exists, then it might be that no particular being necessarily exists, in which case any possible God lacks necessary existence. But I'm interested in divine necessity, not the necessity of divinity. One might alternatively try to formulate divine necessity as the claim that there is something that is necessarily God, but note that even that is too weak because it does not entail that that something necessarily exists. Compare: there is something that is necessarily me; that does not entail that that something necessarily exists. I am necessarily me, but, unfortunately, I don't necessarily exist. The theses of divine necessity that I will be interested in don't merely say of a thing that it is necessarily God, but they say of God that it necessarily exists. 7 3 THE ARGUMENTS FOR DIVINE NECESSITY In this section, I will present and discuss a version of each of what I take to be three main kinds of arguments for the thesis of strong divine necessity, namely, the ontological argument, the cosmological argument, and the argument from abstracta. I also consider some retreats to weak divine necessity. 8 It goes without saying that I can here only present and all too briefly discuss one particular rough version of each kind of argument. There is of course much, much more to be said on all points considered. Consider it a mere taste of the meal intended to make you want more, rather than a substantial portion of it intended to fill you up. 3.1 The ontological argument There are many versions of the ontological argument, most of which are well discussed in the literature. 9 Here is a taste of just one version, for purposes of strong divine necessity. The idea is that we can, upon conceptual reflections, come to see that God necessarily exists, because, at least according to this kind of argument, God is the greatest being

3 BOHN 3of10 that can be, and it's greater to necessarily exist than to merely contingently exist. Here is one way of putting the argument: 1. God = the greatest being that can be Definition 2. God does not actually necessarily exist For reductio 3. God possibly necessarily exists Premise 4. If 2 and 3, God is possibly greater than God actually is Premise 5. But God is not possibly greater than God actually is 1 6. So not 2 or not 3 4,5 7. So God necessarily exists 2,3,6, RAA 10 Let me here only mention two good ways to block this particular argument. First, as I have argued elsewhere (Bohn, 2012), definition 1 is arguably incoherent: Greatness has no top level but is indefinitely extensible. For any possible great being, there is a possibly greater one, which entails that premises 1 and 3 are false. Second, premise 4 is deeply problematic because it's unclear how we can compare a possible God with an actual God given that for all assumption 2 says there might not be any God at all. (This same criticism holds of the strategy of using the ontological argument to first establish the existence of God, only to then try to establish its necessary existence.) It must be that we have a concept of God that might or might not have an extension in the actual world but has an extension in some possible world. Now, it is not the concept of God that is more or less great depending on whether it holds of some possible necessary thing or some actual non necessary thing, but it is its possible necessary extension that is greater than its actual non necessary extension. But the problem is that it might not have an actual extension at all! So instead, we must somehow compare a conceivable actual non necessary extension with a conceivable possible necessary extension, and somehow, the latter is greater than the former. But even then, how do we get from that to the conceivable actual extension actually existing? It's just unclear how there could be a sound way from merely considering a concept with a conceivable extension to that conceivable extension actually existing and equally unclear how there could be a sound way to it necessarily existing. For purposes of weak divine necessity, the idea behind the ontological argument is that it somehow follows from the concept of God that God must exist, if God actually exists. So for such purposes, we don't have to worry about whether God exists as we did in 2 above; we can simply assume it, which means that we have an argument for weak divine necessity that avoids at least the second of the above two criticisms: 1. God = the greatest being that can be Definition 2. God actually exists Assumption 3. God does not actually necessarily exist For reductio 4. God possibly necessarily exists Premise 5. If 2, 3 and 4, God is possibly greater than God actually is Premise 6. But God is not possibly greater than God actually is 1 7. So not 2 or not 3 or not 4 5,6 8. So if God exists, then God necessarily exists 2,3,4,7, RAA 11 This argument for weak divine necessity is stronger than the earlier argument for strong divine necessity, but it nonetheless has serious problems, even ignoring the previously mentioned problem with definition 1. The argument hinges on assumption 3 and premises 4 and 5. Unlike in the earlier argument 1 7 for strong divine necessity, given the assumption 2 that God exists, we can here reasonably compare God with a possible God, and in so comparing it across worlds, it even seems God is greater if it necessarily exists than if it merely contingently exists. But the problem is that when we so compare it across worlds, it seems we have equally clearly in mind a contingently existing God and a necessarily existing God, but the two are logically incompatible, so one of them is in fact impossible. That means, at best, that one of them must be merely epistemically possible, i.e., possible for (i.e., compatible with) all we know, but not in fact metaphysically possible. But which one is it: the actually contingent God of assumptions 2 and 3 or the possibly necessary God of premise 4? The argument doesn't tell. We need independent reasons to choose between 3 and 4, in order to move from 7 to 8.

4 4of10 BOHN It thus seems that neither strong nor weak divine necessity is very well supported by the above versions of the ontological argument. Of course, I have not surveyed all pros and cons here, and I must leave it to the reader to consider other versions of the ontological argument, but I dare claim that my conclusion is representative: The ontological argument does not establish divine necessity without much further ado. There is another related but independently interesting argument for strong divine necessity worth considering before we move on; let's call it the Plantinga argument (see, e.g., Plantinga, 1974). It is based on a similar idea as that in premises 3 and 4 in the previous two arguments (respectively): 1. God possibly necessarily exists Premise 2. So God necessarily exists 1, Modal Logic The argument is valid in any modal logic (e.g., S5) with the theorem that whatever is possibly necessary is necessary. In realist metaphysics, where all possible worlds can see each other, this theorem is very compelling. If all possible worlds can see each other, if something is necessarily the case in one world, it is the case in any world. But the Plantinga argument seems too good to be true. Why believe it is possible of God that it necessarily exists (see Section 4 below)? One might think that either it is possible of God that it must exist, in which case the conclusion 2 follows, or it is impossible of God that it must exist, in which case premise 1 is false. Again, which one is it? 12 One might grant that it is epistemically possible of God that it metaphysically must exist, but that does not entail that God metaphysically must exist; that is, the theorem that whatever is possibly necessary is necessary is not true if possibly is read epistemically and necessary is read metaphysically. So, of course, it all hinges on the kind of support that is given for premise 1. There are also parodies of the Plantinga argument. Here is one 13 : 1. God possibly doesn't necessarily exist Premise 2. So God doesn't necessarily exist 1, Modal Logic The argument is valid in the same modal logic as the Plantinga argument. Also, on its face, premise 1 of the parody argument seems as plausible as premise 1 of the Plantinga argument (see Section 4 below). So the next move should be to try to break the symmetry between the Plantinga argument and its parodies. I must here leave that to the reader. 3.2 The cosmological argument There are many versions of the cosmological argument, most of which are well discussed in the literature. 14 Here is a taste of just one version, for purposes of strong divine necessity. The idea is that all contingently existing things, including our universe, need a necessarily existing ground, which is God. Roughly, 1. Any contingent thing has a necessary ground Premise 2. The universe is a contingent thing Premise 3. So the universe has a necessary ground 1,2 4. That necessary ground is God 3, IBE So God necessarily exists 4 Note that we might here use ground as a generic term for any relevant explanatory relation; it might be causal (and diachronic) or non causal (and synchronic). 16 I can here only mention what I take to be the main problem with this kind of argument, namely, premise 1. Why cannot all contingent things have merely contingent grounds, i.e., why can there not be contingency all the way down, indefinitely? 17 Why believe premise 1? One kind of argument for premise 1 is that if all contingent things have merely contingent grounds, then, by subtraction of contingent things, there could have been absolutely nothing whatsoever. 18 But, or so the argument goes, there couldn't have been absolutely nothing whatsoever, so it cannot be that all contingent things have merely contingent grounds; so contingent things must have necessary grounds. But the first problem with this kind of argument is the first step from all things having contingent grounds to the possibility of absolutely nothing, because, contra this step, it might be that even though nothing must be, there must

5 BOHN 5of10 be something. In such a case, everything is contingent, but nonetheless, there couldn't have been absolutely nothing. So the problem is that the argument needs something like a last subtraction step from something contingent to nothing, which can be denied without accepting either the possibility of absolutely nothing or necessary grounds. The second problem with the argument is that even accepting something like that last subtraction step from something contingent to nothing, why is there being absolutely nothing whatsoever supposed to be impossible in the first place? To the contrary, as will be discussed in Section 4.1 below, on its face it seems possible. So the question remains: why believe premise 1? 19 Another argument in its favor might be in the form of IBE, an inference to the best explanation. 20 One might argue that, all else being equal, a theory that explains the contingent things in terms of a necessary ground is preferable to a theory that has no explanation of the contingent things. But the problem with this kind of argument for premise 1 is how to establish that the best explanation is in terms of a necessary ground. For example, I for one (Bohn, forthcoming1; see also Hume, 1776) find a theory according to which each contingent thing individually has an explanation in terms of other contingent things, with all contingent things collectively having no explanation whatsoever, 21 just as good, if not better than a theory according to which all contingent things have an explanation in terms of a necessary ground, a necessary ground which in turn itself has no further explanation in terms of anything else. 22 But, also, even if we believe that the universe has a necessary ground as per 3, why believe that ground is God as per 4? Is God really the best explanation for what that ground is? 23 Why can't some necessary natural law (or principle, or field, or whatever) be an equally good explanation? After all, that is a dream of physics: a necessary natural law (or principle, or field, or whatever) that necessitates the universe. The problem is of course that no one knows what that natural necessitator is supposed to be nor how physics is supposed to give us metaphysical as opposed to nomological necessity, but some believe they know what God is supposed to be and how it is supposed to give us metaphysical necessity. That might give the theist an upper hand as per The argument from abstracta The argument from abstracta is that God is the ground of all things outside of God, including some necessarily existing abstract things, but a contingently existing thing cannot ground necessarily existing things, so God must itself be a necessarily existing thing. Roughly, 1. Anything outside of God is grounded in God Premise 2. Any ground of necessary things is itself necessary Premise 3. Numbers are necessary and outside of God Premise 4. Numbers are grounded in God 1,3 5. God necessarily exists 2,3,4 Note that first, the notion of being outside of God is metaphorical and needs to be spelled out somehow. Let's here assume that can be done. Second, I here use numbers as examples of necessarily existing abstract objects outside of God, but any necessarily existing abstract objects outside of God would do the same job. So pick your favorite example. I find this argument to be one of the more interesting arguments for weak divine necessity. Of course, the argument is a non starter for a nominalist who believes that there are no necessarily existing abstract objects (e.g., Craig, 2014; Swinburne, 2015). But, contra nominalism, given that there are some necessarily existing abstract objects, e.g., numbers (or pure sets), the crux is premise 1, or the thesis of what I call divine foundationalism (Bohn, forthcoming2, forthcoming3). The thesis of divine foundationalism must be premised on the actual existence of God, which makes the argument from abstracta an argument for weak divine necessity: if God actually exists, then God is the ground of all things outside of God, which in turn entails that God necessarily exists as per 1 5 above. 25

6 6of10 BOHN 4 THE ARGUMENTS AGAINST DIVINE NECESSITY In this section, I present and discuss what I take to be two main kinds of arguments against the theses of divine necessity, namely, the argument from the possibility of absolutely nothing and the argument from the contingency of existence. 26 Again, consider the arguments a mere taste rather than a substantial meal. 4.1 The argument from the possibility of absolutely nothing If there could have been absolutely nothing whatsoever, nothing necessarily exists, and ipso facto God does not necessarily exist. So if there could have been absolutely nothing whatsoever, strong and weak divine necessity are both false. God is then at best a contingent being. Alternatively, if weak divine necessity is true, it follows by modus tollens there is actually no God. So could there have been absolutely nothing whatsoever? The most famous argument for the possibility of absolutely nothing is the subtraction argument (Baldwin, 1996; see also Coggins, 2010). Premise 1: there is a possible world w with only finitely many concrete objects. Premise 2: for any concrete object x in w, there is another possible world w 1 just like w except it is lacking x. Premise 3: no concrete object x in w is such that the non existence of any other concrete object y in w necessitates the existence of x. From premises 1 3, it follows by a series of n steps that there is a possible world w n in which there are no concrete objects. But the subtraction argument faces many problems. First, if the subtraction argument works, it only works to the effect that there could have been no concrete objects; it remains silent on whether there must be something beyond the concrete objects. Now, this is not too important for present purposes since presumably God is a concrete object, but if God is non concrete, the subtraction argument must be generalized beyond the concrete objects. 27 But it is not clear how that is to be done, since it would considerably weaken, if not simply refute, each one of the premises 1 3. Second, even sticking to only concrete objects, premise 2 might be true with respect to more or less ordinary objects like tables and chairs, but why think it is true with respect to the supposed ultimate ground of reality, namely, God? A theist might perfectly well accept that more or less ordinary concrete objects like tables and chairs might be metaphysically subtractable but not accept that God itself might be subtractable. There is nothing ad hoc in such a response, at least not for a theist; after all, God is supposed to be something special, unlike any other thing. It seems the subtraction argument is really a non starter for a theist who believes in divine necessity. But there is also what might be called an accumulative argument for the possibility of absolutely nothing whatsoever. Premise 1: the possibility of there being absolutely nothing whatsoever has a model and hence is logically consistent and hence is logically possible. 28 Premise 2: the possibility of there being absolutely nothing whatsoever is conceivable. Premise 3: anything that is logically possible and conceivable is by default metaphysically possible. 29 From premises 1 3, it follows that there being absolutely nothing whatsoever is by default metaphysically possible. The burden of proof is thus on anyone who claims it is metaphysically impossible. The problem with this kind of argument is that it has parodies. Here is one. 30 Premise 1: the possibility of a necessary being has a model (in modal logics) and hence is logically consistent and hence is logically possible. Premise 2: the possibility of a necessary being is conceivable. Premise 3: anything that is logically possible and conceivable is by default metaphysically possible. From premises 1 3, it follows that a necessary being is by default metaphysically possible. The burden of proof is thus on anyone who claims it is metaphysically impossible. So the question becomes which if any is the default position: the metaphysical possibility of absolutely nothing or the metaphysical possibility of a necessary being?

7 BOHN 7of The argument from the contingency of existence Some have argued that no true existence statement is necessarily true (most notably Hume, 1779), so everything that exists could have failed to exist, i.e., is contingent. If so, strong and weak divine necessity are both false; or, alternatively, if weak divine necessity is true, it follows by modus tollens that there is actually no God. The important difference between this case of the contingency of existence and the earlier case of the possibility of there being absolutely nothing whatsoever is that even if there being absolutely nothing whatsoever turns out to be impossible, it can still be possible that everything is contingent. It might simply be that even though nothing must be, there must be something. So even though the problem of nothingness and the problem of contingency both create the same problems for strong and weak divine necessity, the proponent of strong or weak divine necessity still faces the problem of the contingency of existence even if in the end she doesn't face the problem of absolute nothingness. So is every true existence statement metaphysically contingent? There is, as above, what we might call an accumulative argument for it. Premise 1: for any true existence statement of the form a exists, its negation a doesn't exist has a model and hence is logically consistent and hence is logically possible. Premise 2: for any true existence statement, its negation is conceivable. Premise 3: anything that is logically possible and conceivable is by default metaphysically possible. From premises 1 3, it follows that for any true existence statement, its negation is by default metaphysically possible. The burden of proof is thus on anyone who claims its negation is metaphysically impossible. So until shown otherwise, every true existence statement seems metaphysically contingent. A problem with this kind of argument is that the theist presumably believes that she has shown otherwise in the case of God. There are also parodies in the vicinity. Here is one. 31 Premise 1: for any true existence statement of the form a exists, its necessitation a necessarily exists has a model (in modal logics) and hence is logically consistent and hence is logically possible. Premise 2: for any true existence statement, its necessitation is conceivable. Premise 3: anything that is logically possible and conceivable is by default metaphysically possible. From premises 1 3, it follows that for any true existence statement, its necessitation is by default metaphysically possible. But, what's more, by the modal logics used in our discussion of the Plantinga argument in Section 3 above (e.g., S5), this entails that any existence is by default necessary existence, which (pace Williamson, 2013), is absurd. One might therefore question all arguments of the above accumulative form. But, of course, one might also instead question premise 2 of the last parody. Can we really conceive of the necessitation of any existence statement? So the question becomes: for any existence statement of the form a exists, is its necessitation as conceivable as its negation? Or, more generally, which if any possibility is the default position? 5 DIVINE ABSOLUTENESS Maybe the whole issue of whether God must exist in some metaphysical sense of must is simply misguided. Maybe we should instead move to a wholly different notion of must, where God must exist in some metaphysically non modal but rather fundamental and absolute sense of must ; let's call this the thesis of divine absoluteness. The idea is that metaphysical modality doesn't apply to God; perhaps God is the fundamental and absolute ground of all things outside of God, including all of metaphysical modality, including all its true talk of possible worlds, with God itself thus being fundamentally amodal. Then it ultimately makes no sense to claim that God could have failed to exist nor that God must exist, in some metaphysical sense of must, but it might still make sense to claim that God must exist in some sense of must according to which God's existence is a fundamental and absolute truth in the sense of being the ground of all things outside of God. Maybe that is all we should mean by the claim that God must exist. Is such divine absoluteness true? 32 There are at least three problems. First, it is very hard to understand exactly how God is supposed to be amodal; simply saying so doesn't make it so. The question Could God have failed to exist? seems a perfectly sensible question. For example, if the answer is yes, strong divine necessity is false; if the answer is no, strong divine necessity is true; either way there seems to be a truth about the metaphysical modal status of God. Second, relatedly, non deflationary metaphysical modality seems irreducible, including irreducible to God. Third, if God is the ground of all things outside

8 8of10 BOHN of itself, and some of those things are metaphysically necessary existents, it seems God must itself be at least a metaphysically necessary existent (cf. the argument from abstracta above), if not a logically necessary existent. 6 CONCLUDING REMARKS In this paper, I have briefly discussed strong and weak divine necessity, as well as all too briefly the alternative of divine absoluteness. The two theses of divine necessity seem hard to establish, and the thesis of divine absoluteness seems hard to make sense of. Maybe the theist is better off taking at least weak divine necessity as a metaphysical axiom to be justified holistically, by its theoretical fruits? Let me end by all too briefly mention two interesting alternative ways of trying to establish divine necessity. The first such alternative is based on Ted Sider's (2011) deflationary notion of metaphysical modality. According to Sider, the metaphysically necessary truths are, in a nutshell, simply some truths we put on a list and call metaphysically necessary. Mathematical truths are examples of such truths. Maybe, the existence of God too should be put on that list? Putting the existence of God on the list might perhaps be holistically and pragmatically justified. I believe such Siderian divine necessity is worth a serious discussion. The second alternative is based on Tim Williamson's (2013) necessitism, according to which it is necessary that all existing things are necessarily existing. 33 By such necessitism, it trivially follows that if God merely possibly exists, God necessarily exists. Note that according to the Plantinga argument discussed earlier, it follows from the possibility of God's necessary existence that God necessarily exists, but according to the Williamsonian argument I am giving here, it follows from the possibility of God's existence that God necessarily exists. 34 ENDNOTES 1 Cf. Findlay (1948), though Findlay operates with an outdated, pre Kripkean notion of necessity. 2 Cf. Swinburne (1994, 2015), though Swinburne operates with an arguably false conventional notion of necessity. Against conventionalism, see Quine (1935) and Sider (2011: section 6.5). 3 On possible worlds, see Divers (2002); on models, see Hodges (1997). What I call metaphysical necessity is sometimes called broad logical necessity, and what I call logical necessity is sometimes called narrow logical necessity; e.g., Swinburne (1994, 2015) and Leftow (2010). But I prefer speaking with the metaphysicians and logicians in terms of the metaphysicallogical distinction. Unless noted otherwise, by possible, necessary and impossible, I henceforth mean metaphysically possible, necessary and impossible. 4 Note that things are different if we employ counterpart theory, according to which nothing exists in two or more different possible worlds, but modal claims are made true or false in virtue of contextually determined counterpart relations to other things in other possible worlds. I have no space to discuss that option here. See Lewis (1968, 1986, especially ch.4). 5 The distinctions between deflationary/non deflationary and de re/de dicto might cut across each other, so there might be ways of formulating the above de re versions of divine necessity in a more deflationary manner, but I cannot and will not pursue that route here. But see Sections 5 and 6 below. 6 For example, Rasmussen (2016) discusses weak divine necessity in terms of de dicto necessity rather than de re necessity. 7 Alternatively, one might treat necessarily as a sentential operator, God as a rigid designator referring to one and the same thing in all possible worlds (assuming cross world identity) and then formulate divine necessity as follows: Necessarily, God exists. But I doubt that much is gained by this strategy for reasons I cannot go into here. On another note, I assume throughout that if God exists in a possible world, then God cannot fail to be God in any possible world. That is, I assume that it is essential to God that it is God and hence that God cannot be some other thing than God. 8 See also Pruss and Rasmussen (forthcoming) for a clear headed overview and discussion of various arguments for there being at least one necessarily existing concrete object. But note that it is an open question how to get from there to any of the two theses of divine necessity discussed in the present paper; though see Rasmussen (2010b, section 5) for some hints. See also Oppy (2014: ch.6). 9 See Oppy (1995, 2016) for an overview, discussion and references. 10 I m here assuming (among other things) that whatever is actually necessary is necessary (e.g., modal logic S5). RAA means reductio ad absurdum. 11 Assuming (among other things) that whatever is actually necessary is necessary (e.g., modal logic S5).

9 BOHN 9of10 12 See also Schrader (1991), though note that he talks about logical necessity. 13 Thanks to a referee for this journal for pointing to this particular version of the parody argument. 14 See Oppy, 2006, Chapter 3; Rasmussen, 2010b; and Reichenbach, 2016, for overview, discussion, and references. 15 IBE means inference to the best explanation. 16 Arguably, Rasmussen (2010b) puts too much emphasis on causality, though it is not clear to me what he means by causal. He does seem to use the term very broadly. For overview, discussion, and references on a non causal notion of grounding, see Bliss and Trogdon (2014) and Raven (2015). 17 Just like there can be grounding all the way down, indefinitely (Bohn, forthcoming1). 18 For an argument to this effect, see the subtraction argument in Section 4.1 below. In the diachronic case, the idea is that something would have to come from nothing. 19 One might also try to argue for it on the basis of a principle of sufficient reason. See Pruss (2006). 20 Thanks to a referee for this journal for pushing this point. 21 Or perhaps there simply is no contingent plurality of all contingent things; but rather, contingent plurality of contingent things is indefinitely extensible: for any contingent plurality of contingent things, there is a contingent thing not in that plurality. 22 For criticism of this kind of Humean idea, see, e.g., Pruss (2006:41 46). 23 See, e.g., Rasmussen (2010b, Section 5) for hints of some positive such arguments. 24 For a more general discussion of the Leibnizian Cosmological Arguments, see Pruss (2009). For another argument, see Rasmussen (2010a). 25 For more on this type of argument, see, e.g., Plantinga (1980, 1982); Leftow (1990); and Davidson (2013). 26 See also Pruss & Rasmussen (forthcoming, Chapter 9) for a clear headed overview and discussion of various arguments against there being a necessarily existing concrete object. See also Rasmussen (2016) and Adams (1971, 1983). 27 I intentionally leave concrete undefined here, but note that in any case, it is not equivalent with physical or material. Presumably, all physical things must be concrete, but not all concrete things must be physical. While being physical (or material) is opposed to being mental, being concrete is opposed to being abstract. Being concrete is more like violating the identity of indiscernibles, or being determinately either F or not F, for any property F. 28 Classical logic operates with no empty domain, but that is a mere formal convenience that is neither here nor there for our present purposes; for philosophical purposes, we can and should work with systems that include the empty domain. 29 Note that the accumulation of logical consistency and conceivability is not an infallible guide to metaphysical possibility. 30 See also Rasmussen (2016). 31 See also Rasmussen (2016). 32 Cf. Swinburne (1994, 2015) and Hick (1960); for criticism, see Leftow (2010). According to Leftow (2012), God is not fully metaphysically amodal but pretty close to it. 33 Note that according to Williamsonian necessitism, though that a thing exists is necessary, what it is need not be necessary. See Williamson (2013). 34 Thanks to Ben Caplan, Peter Forrest, Martin Jakobsen, Yujin Nagasawa, Atle Ottesen Søvik, and an anonymous referee for this journal for comments and discussions. ORCID Einar Duenger Bohn WORK CITED Adams, R. (1971). Has it been proved that all real existence is contingent? American Philosophical Quarterly, 8(3), Adams, R. (1983). Divine necessity. The Journal of Philosophy, 80(11), Baldwin, T. (1996). There might be nothing. Analysis, 56(4), Bliss, R. & Trogdon, K. (2014). Metaphysical grounding. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Bohn, E. D. (2012). Anselmian theism and indefinitely extensible perfection. Philosophical Quarterly, 62(249), Bohn, E. D. (forthcoming1). Indefinitely descending ground. In R. Bliss, & G. Priest (Eds.), Reality and its structure. Oxford University Press. Bohn, E. D. (forthcoming2). Divine foundationalism. Philosophy Compass. Bohn, E. D. (forthcoming3). God and abstract objects. Cambridge University Press.

10 10 of 10 BOHN Coggins, G. (2010). Could there have been nothing? Palgrave Macmillan. Craig, W. L. (2014). Anti platonism. In P. Gould (Ed.), Beyond the control of God? Six views on the problem of God and abstract objects (pp. 2014). Bloomsbury Academic. Davidson, M. (2013). God and other necessary beings. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Divers, J. (2002). Possible worlds. Routledge. Findlay, J. N. (1948). Can God's existence be disproved? Mind, 57(226), Hick, J. (1960). God as necessary being. Journal of Philosophy, 57(22/23), Hodges, W. (1997). A shorter model theory. Cambridge University Press. Hume, D. (1779). Dialogues concerning natural religion. As reprinted in. In Dialogues concerning natural religion and the natural history of religion (pp. 2008). Oxford University Press. Leftow, B. (1990). God and abstract objects. Faith and Philosophy, 7, Leftow, B. (2010). Swinburne on divine necessity. Religious Studies, 46(02), Leftow, B. (2012). God and necessity. Oxford University Press. Lewis, D. (1968). Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. The Journal of Philosophy., 65, Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Blackwell. Oppy, G. (1995). Ontological arguments and belief in God. Cambridge University Press. Oppy, G. (2006). Arguing about Gods. Cambridge University Press. Oppy, G. (2014). Describing Gods. Cambridge University Press. Oppy, G. (2016). Ontological arguments. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Plantinga, A. (1974). The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Plantinga, A. (1980). Does God have a nature? Milwaukee: Marquette University Press. Plantinga, A. (1982). How to be an anti realist. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 56, Pruss, A. R. (2006). The principle of sufficient reason. Cambridge University Press. Pruss, A.R. (2009). Leibnizian cosmological arguments. As in W.L. Craig & J.P. Moreland (eds.) Blackwell companion to natural theology. Oxford: Blackwell, Pruss, A. R., & Rasmussen, J. L. (forthcoming). Necessary existence. Oxford University Press. Quine, W.V.O. (1935). Truth by convention. As in W.V.O. Quine (1976). The ways of paradox and other essays. Harvard University Press. Rasmussen, J. L. (2010a). A new argument for a necessary being. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 89(2), Rasmussen, J. L. (2010b). Cosmological arguments from contingency. Philosophy Compass, 5(9), Rasmussen, J. L. (2016). Could God fail to exist? European Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 8(3), Raven, M. (2015). Ground. Philosophy Compass, 10(15), Reichenbach, B. (2016). Cosmological argument. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Schrader, D. (1991). The antinomy of divine necessity. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 30(1), Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford University Press. Swinburne, R. (1994). The Christian God. Oxford University Press. Swinburne, R. (2015). Could God be a necessary being? In Oxford studies in philosophy of religion. Volume 6. Oxford University Press. Williamson, T. (2013). Modal logic as metaphysics. Oxford University Press. Einar Duenger Bohn is a professor of philosophy at the University of Agder. He has a PhD from UMass Amherst (2009). His main research interests are in the philosophy of religion, metaphysics, and artificial intelligence, including the ethics of artificial intelligence. How to cite this article: Bohn ED. Divine necessity. Philosophy Compass. 2017;e /phc

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail

How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail How Gödelian Ontological Arguments Fail Matthew W. Parker Abstract. Ontological arguments like those of Gödel (1995) and Pruss (2009; 2012) rely on premises that initially seem plausible, but on closer

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

On A New Cosmological Argument

On A New Cosmological Argument On A New Cosmological Argument Richard Gale and Alexander Pruss A New Cosmological Argument, Religious Studies 35, 1999, pp.461 76 present a cosmological argument which they claim is an improvement over

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Time travel and the open future

Time travel and the open future Time travel and the open future University of Queensland Abstract I argue that the thesis that time travel is logically possible, is inconsistent with the necessary truth of any of the usual open future-objective

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction?

Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? Does Deduction really rest on a more secure epistemological footing than Induction? We argue that, if deduction is taken to at least include classical logic (CL, henceforth), justifying CL - and thus deduction

More information

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio

Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio Externalism and a priori knowledge of the world: Why privileged access is not the issue Maria Lasonen-Aarnio This is the pre-peer reviewed version of the following article: Lasonen-Aarnio, M. (2006), Externalism

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter

No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter Forthcoming in Philosophia Christi 13:1 (2011) http://www.epsociety.org/philchristi/ No Dilemma for the Proponent of the Transcendental Argument: A Response to David Reiter James N. Anderson David Reiter

More information

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW

AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW Jeffrey E. Brower AQUINAS S METAPHYSICS OF MODALITY: A REPLY TO LEFTOW Brian Leftow sets out to provide us with an account of Aquinas s metaphysics of modality. 1 Drawing on some important recent work,

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

The Recent Revival of Cosmological Arguments

The Recent Revival of Cosmological Arguments Philosophy Compass 3/3 (2008): 541 550, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2008.00134.x The Recent Revival of Cosmological Arguments David Alexander* Baylor University Abstract Cosmological arguments have received more

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?''

IS GOD SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' IS GOD "SIGNIFICANTLY FREE?'' Wesley Morriston In an impressive series of books and articles, Alvin Plantinga has developed challenging new versions of two much discussed pieces of philosophical theology:

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions

Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Comments on Truth at A World for Modal Propositions Christopher Menzel Texas A&M University March 16, 2008 Since Arthur Prior first made us aware of the issue, a lot of philosophical thought has gone into

More information

A CRITIQUE OF THE USE OF NONSTANDARD SEMANTICS IN THE ARBITRARINESS HORN OF DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

A CRITIQUE OF THE USE OF NONSTANDARD SEMANTICS IN THE ARBITRARINESS HORN OF DIVINE COMMAND THEORY A CRITIQUE OF THE USE OF NONSTANDARD SEMANTICS IN THE ARBITRARINESS HORN OF DIVINE COMMAND THEORY A PAPER PRESENTED TO DR. DAVID BAGGETT LIBERTY UNIVERSITY LYNCHBURG, VA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

A New Argument Against Compatibilism

A New Argument Against Compatibilism Norwegian University of Life Sciences School of Economics and Business A New Argument Against Compatibilism Stephen Mumford and Rani Lill Anjum Working Papers No. 2/ 2014 ISSN: 2464-1561 A New Argument

More information

Postmodal Metaphysics

Postmodal Metaphysics Postmodal Metaphysics Ted Sider Structuralism seminar 1. Conceptual tools in metaphysics Tools of metaphysics : concepts for framing metaphysical issues. They structure metaphysical discourse. Problem

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

The Cosmological Argument

The Cosmological Argument The Cosmological Argument Stage I 1. Causal Premise: Everything of type T has a cause. [note: cause purpose]. 2. Something of type T exists. 3. There is a reason X for thinking that there is a First Cause

More information

INDEFINITELY DESCENDING GROUND Einar Duenger Bohn University of Agder [Forthcoming in Reality and its Structure, edited by R.Bliss & G.Priest, OUP.

INDEFINITELY DESCENDING GROUND Einar Duenger Bohn University of Agder [Forthcoming in Reality and its Structure, edited by R.Bliss & G.Priest, OUP. INDEFINITELY DESCENDING GROUND Einar Duenger Bohn University of Agder [Forthcoming in Reality and its Structure, edited by R.Bliss & G.Priest, OUP.] We often say that some facts obtain in virtue of others,

More information

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn Philosophy Study, November 2017, Vol. 7, No. 11, 595-600 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2017.11.002 D DAVID PUBLISHING Defending Davidson s Anti-skepticism Argument: A Reply to Otavio Bueno Mohammad Reza Vaez

More information

The principle of sufficient reason and necessitarianism

The principle of sufficient reason and necessitarianism The principle of sufficient reason and necessitarianism KRIS MCDANIEL 1. Introduction Peter van Inwagen (1983: 202 4) presented a powerful argument against the Principle of Sufficient Reason, which I henceforth

More information

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD JASON MEGILL Carroll College Abstract. In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Hume (1779/1993) appeals to his account of causation (among other things)

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Free will and the necessity of the past

Free will and the necessity of the past free will and the necessity of the past 105 Free will and the necessity of the past Joseph Keim Campbell 1. Introduction In An Essay on Free Will (1983), Peter van Inwagen offers three arguments for incompatibilism,

More information

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized

Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Philosophy of Religion Aquinas' Third Way Modalized Robert E. Maydole Davidson College bomaydole@davidson.edu ABSTRACT: The Third Way is the most interesting and insightful of Aquinas' five arguments for

More information

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction

Philosophy Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction Philosophy 5340 - Epistemology Topic 5 The Justification of Induction 1. Hume s Skeptical Challenge to Induction In the section entitled Sceptical Doubts Concerning the Operations of the Understanding

More information

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will

The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will Stance Volume 3 April 2010 The Principle of Sufficient Reason and Free Will ABSTRACT: I examine Leibniz s version of the Principle of Sufficient Reason with respect to free will, paying particular attention

More information

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir

Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: A Reply to A. J. Cotnoir Thought ISSN 2161-2234 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Counterparts and Compositional Nihilism: University of Kentucky DOI:10.1002/tht3.92 1 A brief summary of Cotnoir s view One of the primary burdens of the mereological

More information

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity,

SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY. Jeffrey E. Brower. There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity, SIMPLICITY AND ASEITY Jeffrey E. Brower There is a traditional theistic doctrine, known as the doctrine of divine simplicity, according to which God is an absolutely simple being, completely devoid of

More information

Philosophy of Religion (PHIL11159)

Philosophy of Religion (PHIL11159) . Philosophy of Religion (PHIL11159) Course Organiser Dr. James Henry Collin University of Edinburgh COURSE AIMS AND OBJECTIVES This is a level 11 course for students seeking an advanced introduction to

More information

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum

BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE. Ruhr-Universität Bochum 264 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES BENEDIKT PAUL GÖCKE Ruhr-Universität Bochum István Aranyosi. God, Mind, and Logical Space: A Revisionary Approach to Divinity. Palgrave Frontiers in Philosophy of Religion.

More information

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice

Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Logic and Pragmatics: linear logic for inferential practice Daniele Porello danieleporello@gmail.com Institute for Logic, Language & Computation (ILLC) University of Amsterdam, Plantage Muidergracht 24

More information

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism

Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Res Cogitans Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 8 6-24-2016 Deflationary Nominalism s Commitment to Meinongianism Anthony Nguyen Reed College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-9016-5 ORIGINAL PAPER Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Michael Bergmann Published online: 7 March 2007 Ó Springer Science+Business

More information

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011

The Ontological Argument for the existence of God. Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The Ontological Argument for the existence of God Pedro M. Guimarães Ferreira S.J. PUC-Rio Boston College, July 13th. 2011 The ontological argument (henceforth, O.A.) for the existence of God has a long

More information

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Issue 4, Special Conference Proceedings 2017 Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society An Alternative Approach to Mathematical Ontology Amber Donovan (Durham University) Introduction

More information

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent. Author meets Critics: Nick Stang s Kant s Modal Metaphysics Kris McDaniel 11-5-17 1.Introduction It s customary to begin with praise for the author s book. And there is much to praise! Nick Stang has written

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

Abstract: In this paper, I propose a way to modify panpsychism in order to avoid its notorious combination problem.

Abstract: In this paper, I propose a way to modify panpsychism in order to avoid its notorious combination problem. PANPSYCHISM, THE COMBINATION PROBLEM, AND PLURAL COLLECTIVE PROPERTIES Einar Duenger Bohn University of Agder [Forthcoming in Australasian Journal of Philosophy] Abstract: In this paper, I propose a way

More information

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument

Broad on Theological Arguments. I. The Ontological Argument Broad on God Broad on Theological Arguments I. The Ontological Argument Sample Ontological Argument: Suppose that God is the most perfect or most excellent being. Consider two things: (1)An entity that

More information

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists

Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists Simplicity and Why the Universe Exists QUENTIN SMITH I If big bang cosmology is true, then the universe began to exist about 15 billion years ago with a 'big bang', an explosion of matter, energy and space

More information

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014

Exercise Sets. KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness. Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 Exercise Sets KS Philosophical Logic: Modality, Conditionals Vagueness Dirk Kindermann University of Graz July 2014 1 Exercise Set 1 Propositional and Predicate Logic 1. Use Definition 1.1 (Handout I Propositional

More information

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? 17 SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? SIMINI RAHIMI Heythrop College, University of London Abstract. Modern philosophers normally either reject the divine command theory of

More information

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages

Timothy Williamson: Modal Logic as Metaphysics Oxford University Press 2013, 464 pages 268 B OOK R EVIEWS R ECENZIE Acknowledgement (Grant ID #15637) This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation. The opinions expressed in this publication

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism

Abstract Abstraction Abundant ontology Abundant theory of universals (or properties) Actualism A-features Agent causal libertarianism Glossary Abstract: a classification of entities, examples include properties or mathematical objects. Abstraction: 1. a psychological process of considering an object while ignoring some of its features;

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense

The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense Quadrivium: A Journal of Multidisciplinary Scholarship Volume 6 Issue 1 Issue 6, Winter 2014 Article 7 2-1-2015 The Logical Problem of Evil and the Limited God Defense Darren Hibbs Nova Southeastern University,

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2

Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 1 Recap Perception and Mind-Dependence: Lecture 2 (Alex Moran, apm60@ cam.ac.uk) According to naïve realism: (1) the objects of perception are ordinary, mindindependent things, and (2) perceptual experience

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

Modal Truthmakers and Two Varieties of Actualism

Modal Truthmakers and Two Varieties of Actualism Forthcoming in Synthese DOI: 10.1007/s11229-008-9456-x Please quote only from the published version Modal Truthmakers and Two Varieties of Actualism Gabriele Contessa Department of Philosophy Carleton

More information

MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT. Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University

MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT. Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University MEGILL S MULTIVERSE META-ARGUMENT Klaas J. Kraay Ryerson University This paper appears in the International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 73: 235-241. The published version can be found online at:

More information

Action in Special Contexts

Action in Special Contexts Part III Action in Special Contexts c36.indd 283 c36.indd 284 36 Rationality john broome Rationality as a Property and Rationality as a Source of Requirements The word rationality often refers to a property

More information

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper

TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM. by Joseph Diekemper TEMPORAL NECESSITY AND LOGICAL FATALISM by Joseph Diekemper ABSTRACT I begin by briefly mentioning two different logical fatalistic argument types: one from temporal necessity, and one from antecedent

More information

Fundamentals of Metaphysics

Fundamentals of Metaphysics Fundamentals of Metaphysics Objective and Subjective One important component of the Common Western Metaphysic is the thesis that there is such a thing as objective truth. each of our beliefs and assertions

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2014). Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities. Metaphysica, 15 (1), 209 217. The final publication

More information

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2 Intro to Ground Ted Sider Ground seminar 1. The idea of ground This essay is a plea for ideological toleration. Philosophers are right to be fussy about the words they use, especially in metaphysics where

More information

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction

SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1. Dominic Gregory. I. Introduction Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol. 79, No. 3, pp. 422 427; September 2001 SMITH ON TRUTHMAKERS 1 Dominic Gregory I. Introduction In [2], Smith seeks to show that some of the problems faced by existing

More information

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism One of Spinoza s clearest expressions of his monism is Ethics I P14, and its corollary 1. 1 The proposition reads: Except God, no substance can be or be

More information

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence

Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence M. Eddon Why Four-Dimensionalism Explains Coincidence Australasian Journal of Philosophy (2010) 88: 721-729 Abstract: In Does Four-Dimensionalism Explain Coincidence? Mark Moyer argues that there is no

More information

Monism, Emergence, and Plural Logic

Monism, Emergence, and Plural Logic Erkenn (2012) 76:211 223 DOI 10.1007/s10670-011-9280-4 ORIGINAL ARTICLE Monism, Emergence, and Plural Logic Einar Duenger Bohn Received: 22 January 2010 / Accepted: 30 April 2011 / Published online: 23

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University

PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University PLANTINGA ON THE FREE WILL DEFENSE Hugh LAFoLLETTE East Tennessee State University I In his recent book God, Freedom, and Evil, Alvin Plantinga formulates an updated version of the Free Will Defense which,

More information

Could There Have Been Nothing?

Could There Have Been Nothing? Could There Have Been Nothing? This page intentionally left blank Could There Have Been Nothing? Against Metaphysical Nihilism Geraldine Coggins Keele University, UK Geraldine Coggins 2010 Softcover reprint

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

NOTHING NAOMI THOMPSON. A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY (B)

NOTHING NAOMI THOMPSON. A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY (B) NOTHING By NAOMI THOMPSON A thesis submitted to the University of Birmingham for the degree of MASTER OF PHILOSOPHY (B) Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Law The University of Birmingham September

More information

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason

Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason Chance, Chaos and the Principle of Sufficient Reason Alexander R. Pruss Department of Philosophy Baylor University October 8, 2015 Contents The Principle of Sufficient Reason Against the PSR Chance Fundamental

More information

Curriculum Vitae GEORGE FREDERICK SCHUELER Web Page:

Curriculum Vitae GEORGE FREDERICK SCHUELER   Web Page: Curriculum Vitae GEORGE FREDERICK SCHUELER E-Mail: SCHUELER@UDEL.EDU, Web Page: www.unm.edu/~schueler/ 35 Darien Rd., Newark, Delaware 19711 Phone: (302) 294-1589 Philosophy Dept., University of Delaware,

More information

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion

Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion 398 Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic Volume 38, Number 3, Summer 1997 Situations in Which Disjunctive Syllogism Can Lead from True Premises to a False Conclusion S. V. BHAVE Abstract Disjunctive Syllogism,

More information

The modal status of materialism

The modal status of materialism Philos Stud (2009) 145:351 362 DOI 10.1007/s11098-008-9235-z The modal status of materialism Joseph Levine Æ Kelly Trogdon Published online: 10 May 2008 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008 Abstract

More information

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on

Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons. Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on Version 3.0, 10/26/11. Brief Remarks on Putnam and Realism in Mathematics * Charles Parsons Hilary Putnam has through much of his philosophical life meditated on the notion of realism, what it is, what

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God, by John Howard Sobel.

Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God, by John Howard Sobel. 1 Logic and Theism: Arguments For and Against Beliefs in God, by John Howard Sobel. Cambridge University Press, 2003. 672 pages. $95. ROBERT C. KOONS, University of Texas This is a terrific book. I'm often

More information

Can logical consequence be deflated?

Can logical consequence be deflated? Can logical consequence be deflated? Michael De University of Utrecht Department of Philosophy Utrecht, Netherlands mikejde@gmail.com in Insolubles and Consequences : essays in honour of Stephen Read,

More information

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis

A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis A Priori Skepticism and the KK Thesis James R. Beebe (University at Buffalo) International Journal for the Study of Skepticism (forthcoming) In Beebe (2011), I argued against the widespread reluctance

More information

DAVID VANDER LAAN. Curriculum Vitae updated Sept 2017

DAVID VANDER LAAN. Curriculum Vitae updated Sept 2017 DAVID VANDER LAAN Curriculum Vitae updated Sept 2017 Office Department of Philosophy Westmont College 955 La Paz Road Santa Barbara, CA 93108 (805) 565-7041 Professional Appointments Westmont College,

More information

The ground of ground, essence, and explanation

The ground of ground, essence, and explanation https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-018-1856-y S.I.: GROUND, ESSENCE, MODALITY The ground of ground, essence, and explanation Michael Wallner 1 Received: 31 May 2017 / Accepted: 15 June 2018 The Author(s) 2018

More information

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Author(s): Christopher Belanger Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science,

More information

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism

How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism How Do We Know Anything about Mathematics? - A Defence of Platonism Majda Trobok University of Rijeka original scientific paper UDK: 141.131 1:51 510.21 ABSTRACT In this paper I will try to say something

More information

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article:

Lawrence Brian Lombard a a Wayne State University. To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [Wayne State University] On: 29 August 2011, At: 05:20 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? by Eileen Walker 1) The central question What makes modal statements statements about what might be or what might have been the case true or false? Normally

More information

Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp , 2008.

Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp , 2008. The Metaphysical Status of Logic TUOMAS E. TAHKO (www.ttahko.net) Published in Michal Peliš (ed.) The Logica Yearbook 2007 (Prague: Filosofia), pp. 225-235, 2008. ABSTRACT The purpose of this paper is

More information

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2

Retrospective Remarks on Events (Kim, Davidson, Quine) Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview. The Possible & The Actual I: Intensionality of Modality 2 Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 20: Overview 1st Papers/SQ s to be returned next week (a bit later than expected) Jim Prior Colloquium Today (4pm Howison, 3rd Floor Moses)

More information

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence

The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Filo Sofija Nr 30 (2015/3), s. 239-246 ISSN 1642-3267 Jacek Wojtysiak John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin The Paradox of the stone and two concepts of omnipotence Introduction The history of science

More information

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD

THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD THE POSSIBILITY OF AN ALL-KNOWING GOD The Possibility of an All-Knowing God Jonathan L. Kvanvig Assistant Professor of Philosophy Texas A & M University Palgrave Macmillan Jonathan L. Kvanvig, 1986 Softcover

More information