Porphyry and Plotinus Metaphysics Steven K. Strange Emory University

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Porphyry and Plotinus Metaphysics Steven K. Strange Emory University"

Transcription

1 forthcoming in G. Karamanolis and A. Sheppard, eds. Studies in Porphyry Porphyry and Plotinus Metaphysics Steven K. Strange Emory University As editor and popularizer of his teacher Plotinus, as a founding figure of Neoplatonism, and as an important commentator on Plato and Aristotle, Porphyry deserves to be considered a major figure in the history of philosophy. But though a first-rate scholar of philosophy as well as of other fields and as such a worthy successor to his first tutor in Platonic philosophy, the learned Longinus it is much less clear to what extent Porphyry can be considered an original contributor to the development of ancient philosophy. 1 Indeed, much of Porphyry s extant work consists of excerpts, often extensive verbatim excerpts, from earlier writers: this is true of his De abstinentia, of his Pythagoras biography, 2 and of his philosophical epistle to his wife, the Ad Marcellam, and it seems to hold as well of his extant commentaries on Aristotle s Categories and on Ptolemy s Harmonics, neither of which make any claim to originality and both of which seem only to wish to present older material in readily accessible form. Porphyry s principal extant metaphysical work, the so-called Sententiae ad intelligibilia ducentes, in Greek!"#$%!& '$#( )! *#+)! (which might more precisely be rendered as resources for approaching the intelligible world ) appears to be an attempt at a sketch of the main points of Plotinian Neoplatonism, and might usefully be compared with the Encheiridion, the collection of excerpts made by Arrian of Nicomedia from his Discourses of Epictetus. Certainly, as A. C. Lloyd once remarked, the notion that a student looking to Porphyry s Sententiae will find in it an easy introduction to the philosophy of Plotinus will not survive experiment, 3 but the chapters of the work do present well-defined discussions of crucial points upon which one who wished to make progress in Plotinus thought might do well to meditate. The material of the Sententiae is for the most part purely Plotinian and often taken verbatim or nearly so from the Enneads, as can be seen from the excellent apparatus fontium in Lamberz s Teubner edition: 4 what is supplied by Porphyry himself seems intended to help clarify and only occasionally to expand upon his Plotinian basis. 5 If this picture of the Sententiae as a sort of handbook, like the Encheiridion of Epictetus, intended for Plotinian progressors, is correct, then any originality or innovation to be found in the work will have been unintentional on the part of its author, and it is therefore not surprising to find the work cited somewhat rarely in discussions of Porphyry s own thought. A.C. Lloyd in his important article in the Cambridge history of later Greek and early medieval philosophy 6 did claim to find in the Sententiae a new conception of the soul s return to the intelligible realm (by abstracting in thought from all logical particularity), 7 but he admits that this conception seems to have been suggested to Porphyry by the final chapter of Ennead VI.4-5, Plotinus treatise on the omnipresence of Being in the sensible world (VI.5.12). We should thus not look to the Sententiae for any specifically Porphyrian as opposed to Plotinian metaphysics. 8 Porphyry s originality vis-à-vis Plotinus, if any, must be found in other works. But is it in fact to be found? I wish to approach this question by examining some of Porphyry s apparent disagreements with Plotinus in metaphysics, to see whether they really are disagreements or merely further cases where, as in the Sententiae, Porphyry is merely expanding upon or trying to explicate Plotinus. It is of course possible that where Porphyry thinks he is explicating Plotinus he is really disagreeing with him, but before we decide that this is so, we should first make sure we understand Porphyry s point of view on the supposed disagreement in question. Thus I will first try to define somewhat more precisely how I think we should see Porphyry s attitude toward agreement with Plotinus. Following that, I will focus specifically on what Porphyry has to say about the Plotinian Hypostases in some of his attested fragments. 9 Here he will reveal himself as -2-

2 exegete of his master to a greater degree than has heretofore been recognized. I will close with a few rather sketchy remarks about the relevance of this material to the fragments of the Anonymous Commentary on Plato s Parmenides that has been attributed to Porphyry by Pierre Hadot. Various features of this text turn out to reflect Porphyry s discussion of the Plotinian Hypostases, and this appears to buttress Hadot s controversial attribution of it to Porphyry. We certainly do find areas of metaphysics where Porphyry is an innovator at least in the sense that he rejects views that were held by his teacher Plotinus. One such area, as was pointed out by P. Hadot in his classic article La métaphysique de Porphyre, 10 concerns the very notion of metaphysics itself as a special field of inquiry, that is, metaphysics conceived on analogy with Aristotle s theology or first philosophy, as the science that deals with supersensible reality, literally beyond physics or the science of nature. It is apparent from Plotinus treatise On dialectic (Ennead I.3) that Plotinus did not accept this Aristotelian/Peripatetic view of the status of metaphysics. For Plotinus, what deals with intelligible reality is rather Dialectic, conceived on the model of the dialectical method of Plato s late dialogues, the Sophist, Statesman and Philebus, which employs collection, division and definition in order to induce contemplation of the Ideas as the contents of Nous or the Divine Intelligence. 11 Dialectic, that is, the method of Collection and Division, is for Plotinus the genuine method of inquiry of the philosopher: an excellent example of his application of it is his official treatment of the overall structure of the intelligible world in the second book of his treatise On the kinds of Being, Ennead VI.2. Dialectic is opposed for Plotinus to Aristotelian metaphysics because he sees that Aristotle conceives them as opposed as well: Aristotle s science of being qua being or first philosophy is explicitly a replacement and rejection of Plato s conception of dialectic as the method of the true philosopher for Aristotle thinks Platonic dialectic can only yield probabilities and opinion, not genuine apodeictic knowledge. Plotinus on the other hand asserts that dialectic, the developed ability or power to properly employ collection and division, just is what philosophical knowledge or epistêmê is (Enn. I.3.5,1). This is an example of Plotinus rather deep understanding of differences between Plato and Aristotle, a rather important point, since Porphyry s disagreements with his master are often seen in terms of Porphyry s harmonizing tendency to defend Aristotelian views and attempt to fit them with Platonist ones, while Plotinus tends to reject them. Porphyry, as Hadot points out, adopts from pre-existing Platonist speculation a conception of the parts of philosophical inquiry that classifies them in the order ethics physics theology or metaphysics, that is, the study of the divine, which is also sometimes called epoptic after the visionary aspect of the mysteries. 12 This conception of the structure of philosophy is consistent with Porphyry s greater continuity with Middle Platonist traditions, in contrast to Plotinus more pronounced radicalism, though of course Porphyry was often willing to follow Plotinus more radical innovations as well, as in the case of the theory of Hypostases and the transcendence of the first One, or the placement of the Platonic Ideas within Nous, where he was first induced by Plotinus to break with the views of his earlier, more traditional teacher Longinus (Vita Plotini 18). 13 Porphyry employs the threefold division of philosophy into ethics, physics, and metaphysics to order the treatises of Plotinus in his edition of them, the Enneads: the first Ennead concerns ethics, the second and third physics, and the fourth through sixth the divine hypostases: 14 the fourth Ennead soul, the fifth nous, and the sixth (although Porphyry does not explicitly say so in the Life of Plotinus) more advanced topics in metaphysics, category theory and number and the One (VP 24-26). 15 Through the very arrangement of the treatises of the Enneads, therefore, Porphyry has imposed upon the reading of Plotinus a not wholly appropriate

3 Aristotelian element for Platonic/Plotinian dialectic is not merely another term for Aristotelian metaphysics, nor in fact does Plotinus in fact anywhere directly address the question of the division of the parts of philosophy. 16 Porphyry s ordering of the Enneads also introduces the somewhat misleading suggestion which is also the generally accepted view that the real goal of Plotinian philosophy is contemplation of and union with the One, the principal topic of the last three treatises of Ennead VI, whereas it is clear from Plotinus treatise on eudaimonia, Ennead I.4, that he instead conceives of the telos or goal of life as the sage s identification with the Divine Intelligence or Nous. 17 The effect on our reading of the Enneads by Porphyry s arrangement of the treatises deserves, I think, more attention than it has received. This raises again the issue of Porphyry s alleged Aristotelianism and his tendency to harmonize Aristotle with Platonism, points on which he is usually thought to have differed significantly from his master. In my view, however, it is easy to make too much of this. I have argued previously, 18 following fundamental work of A. C. Lloyd, 19 that at least in the area of logic and metaphysics, it is Plotinus rather than Porphyry who should be seen as originating this Aristotelianizing tendency within Neoplatonism. For Porphyry treats the criticisms that Plotinus directs against the text of Aristotle s Categories in Ennead VI.1 as aporiai to be solved, 20 and solves them in such a way that the Categories is seen precisely to be a work of logic and not of metaphysics, a work whose untoward metaphysical implications concerning the diminished reality of Platonic genera and species, for example can be defused and the text and the Organon as a whole made safe for use by Platonists. This has usually been construed as Porphyry s response to an attack by Plotinus on Aristotle s Categories, but in pursuing this project Porphyry was not necessarily being untrue to Plotinus intentions. No doubt many of the criticisms of the Categories that Plotinus retails in the first book of On the kinds of Being were intended by their originators, such as the 2 nd century CE (?) figures Lucius and Nicostratus, as hostile critiques of Aristotle. But in Plotinus that they can be seen as directed not against Aristotle himself, but rather against the standard interpretation of Aristotle s Categories as found in Peripatetic commentators: one could mention Alexander of Aphrodisias lost commentary on the work as among Plotinus possible or even likely targets. 21 For example, many of the arguments in Ennead VI.1 are directed against the assumption that the ten categories are to be construed as metaphysical summa genera. But it is very far from clear that Aristotle could have intended this interpretation, since for example he states in the Categories itself that quality is a homonym ( 8 init., 8b25-26), which would be impossible if the category of quality were a genuine genus, which by definition is predicated synonymously of its species. I think that we should assume that Plotinus is suggesting that this standard interpretation of the Categories is wrong, and not that it is Aristotle who is wrong on this point. 22 Porphyry responds to this critique by assuming that Aristotle s categories are intended to be a classification of sensible items and properties only, i.e., he accepts the main point of Plotinus critique, that the categories cannot be a complete classification of everything that exists. Porphyry certainly does disagree with Plotinus about whether the ten categories of Aristotle are actually applicable to sensible reality: Plotinus denies that they are, but Porphyry accepts them. 23 So on this point at least Porphyry thinks Aristotle can be harmonized with Platonist metaphysical truth, whereas Plotinus doubts that complete harmony is achievable, but still sees the disagreement as not being the flat-out opposition that it has often been taken to be. In another essay, P. Hadot has shown how Porphyry (via Dexippus) argued that Plotinus critiques of the Aristotelian category of substance (ousia) in On the kinds of Being can be read in a way that brought out the fundamental harmony of the philosophies of Plotinus and Aristotle. 24 Again, I would want to argue that what

4 this shows is not so much Porphyry s harmonizing tendency in opposition to Plotinus more hardline attitude, but Porphyry s understanding of some of Plotinus deeper motivations. Nevertheless, Porphyry is surely fully aware that Plotinus does have metaphysical disagreements with Aristotle, some of them rather fundamental, such as over Aristotle s view in Metaphysics, that the divine Nous is the highest God, rather than the One or Good, with Nous relegated to the status of the second Hypostasis (cf., very explicitly on this point, Ennead V.1.9,16ff.). Porphyry probably himself held that Aristotle s philosophy could not completely be reconciled with Platonism, since we are told that he wrote a work with the title On the dissension of Plato and Aristotle (P29 Smith) 25, but he must have thought that this disagreement was not fundamental, since he apparently also wrote a work in three books On the unity of the sect of Plato and Aristotle (P30 Smith) if this indeed is not just an alternate title for the same work, which would not substantially affect the point I am trying to make. 26 But this reflects the attitude toward Aristotle that we saw in Plotinus, and that as we saw Porphyry too recognized in him. We also know that Porphyry wrote a work against the earlier Peripatetic Boethus defending the immortality of the human soul against Boethus version of the entelechy-theory of Aristotle s De Anima (P32 Smith: extensive fragments). Plotinus also criticizes Boethus view in his early treatise on the soul s immortality (Ennead IV.7), but we cannot be certain whether Porphyry thought that Boethus interpretation of Aristotle was the correct one. 27 Certainly there were later Platonists who thought that Aristotle could be read as not attacking the immortality of the rational soul essentially, by identifying Aristotle s passive intelligence with rational soul, and defending its imperishability though there is no sign that Plotinus read Aristotle in this fashion, or that Porphyry thought that he did (the harmonizing interpretation of Aristotle on this point could descend from Porphyry, though I think that Iamblichus is more likely as its source). What I would suggest, then, is that Porphyry sees himself as a fairly faithful but not wholly uncritical follower of Plotinus and an adherent of Plotinus new or revived brand of Platonism, in rather the same way as (in his view) Aristotle was a not uncritical follower of Plato himself. 28 In any case Porphyry seems to have been a far more orthodox Plotinian than his rival Amelius Gentilianus, Plotinus other main student, whom Porphyry seems to portray himself in the Life as supplanting as Plotinus designated successor. We know that Amelius disagreed with Plotinus on a number of important points and we may sometimes see Plotinus criticizing in the Enneads, for instance on the topic of the unity of soul (Enn. IV.3.1-8). 29 This impression of Porphyry as selfconsciously the philosophical heir of Plotinus is reinforced by the evidence of Porphyry s treatise De abstinentia, the longest of his surviving philosophical works. 30 This defense of vegetarianism and animal rights (i.e., that brutes can rightly be considered subjects of justice) is addressed to Castricius Firmus, a former student of Plotinus whom Porphyry indeed seems to have inherited as an object of professorial concern. Castricius had abandoned the (Pythagorean) practice of vegetarianism that had also been followed by Plotinus (VP 2), and Porphyry is in this work attempting to recall him to the true path. There are a number of appeals to Castricius loyalty to and piety towards the teachings of the school which Porphyry even refers to as ancestral laws of the philosophy to which you were committed (I.2.3: trans. G. Clark). 31 This seems principally to mean the Pythagorean variety of Platonism that Plotinus had taught, but also may involve personal loyalty or commitment to the figure of Plotinus himself. Certainly the ascetic ethics and the moral psychology upon which it is based that is laid out in chs of Book I of the De abstinentia and elaborated in various passages later in the work seems essentially to be that of Plotinus, and especially of his great treatise on happiness, Ennead I.4. The goal of this ethics is to rejoin or become fully identified with one s personal nous or true self in the

5 intelligible world, from which one s soul has descended into Becoming and embodiment, to reverse the process of descent by detaching oneself mentally from material conditions and from the emotions they provoke. Strict simplicity of diet, including vegetarianism, is one of the main elements in the ascetic regimen advocated by Porphyry: this is something that Plotinus never argues for (though according to Porphyry he did practice it), but the metaphysical and psychological assumptions upon which Porphyry builds his case for it are throughout recognizably Plotinian, especially the notion that one reverts to one s true intelligible self via uninterrupted contemplation of the spiritual realm. 32 Along with the Sententiae, we can take the De abstinentia as an example of Porphyry s Plotinian work, where he is concerned to present, not to criticize, Plotinian thought. Let us move on to the central question of Plotinus theory of hypostases. The extent to which Porphyry accepted the Plotinian metaphysical hierarchy of hypostases, One, Nous and Soul, and in particular the Plotinian distinction between One and Nous, is somewhat controversial and hard to determine. If we look only at the fragments of the fourth book of Porphyry s Philosophical history (220F-223F Smith, all cited by Cyril of Alexandria in his tract against Julian) it seems that Porphyry does accept Plotinus theory. Some apparent differences do arise, but I shall suggest that what we see occurring is once more Porphyry attempting to explicate and expanding upon Plotinus. The four fragments in question all come from Porphyry s discussion of Plato s doctrine of principles, 33 and they reveal, as we will see, that Porphyry wishes to accept Plotinus hypostases in this work (the Philosophical history) as an interpretation of Plato s doctrine. This indeed is what Plotinus intended them to be, as he declares explicitly in the first treatise introducing his theory of the Hypostases, On the three hypostases that are principles (Ennead V.1.8,1-14). Porphyry s endorsement of Plotinus theory is particularly evident from fragment 221F, which is connected closely with this particular passage of the Enneads: indeed, I shall argue that all four of the Porphyrian fragments on metaphysics from Book IV of the Philosophical history are very closely connected with Ennead V.1. Fragment 221F opens with Porphyry s statement that Plato claims that the substance of the divine extends to three hypostases (ll. 2-3), 34 which is a paraphrase of the last clause of Ennead V.1.7, which closes Plotinus extensive discussion of the Hypostases that occupies the first seven chapters of this treatise: And as far as [!"#$% in place of Porphyry s &#$%] these [= One, Nous, Soul] the divine things extend (V.1.7,49). 35 Plotinus here calls his Hypostases the divinities or divine things (ta theia), whereas Porphyry has instead the apparently by now standard term hupostaseis, which Plotinus nowhere uses in this technical sense and which Porphyry perhaps was responsible for introducing. It occurs in the well-known title of Ennead V.1 already cited, On the three hypostases that are principles ('($) *+, *$%+, -$#%.+, /012*32(4,). There is another reminiscence of the same Plotinian phrase a few lines below in Porphyry s fragment 221: [Plato says that] divinity (theôtês) reaches to the [level of] Soul (ll. 5-6). 36 Porphyry s immediately following statement that Plato says that the rest is the un-divine (atheon), starting with corporeal differentiation (ll. 6-7), 37 which has puzzled commentators, is just an amplification of and expansion through contrast and contrariety upon the Plotinian claim that the Hypostases are the divine things that Porphyry is glossing. While Porphyry here identifies the Second Hypostasis with the Demiurge (line 5) rather than with Nous, this is an echo of Plotinus own phrase Nous is the Demiurge for Plato 38 (Enn. V.1.8,6). The only obvious disagreement in this fragment with Plotinus strict doctrine lies in Porphyry s identification of the Cosmic Soul (5 *16.72!18 98#:), that is, the World-Soul of the Timaeus, with the Plotinian Third Hypostasis, since in Plotinus mature doctrine anyway, the Hypostasis

6 Soul is definitely to be distinguished from the soul of the universe, as is explicit for instance in Ennead IV.3, where Plotinus argues for just this claim against his pupil Amelius. 39 As nothing in Plotinus early treatise Ennead V.1 requires us to take the Hypostasis Soul to be the World-Soul, Porphyry would seem to have either over-interpreted or misinterpreted Plotinus on this point, or else he has deliberately introduced a subtle variation into the doctrine here. 40 But in any case, the doctrine of this fragment as a whole is Plotinian and taken from a central Plotinian text, and it endorses Plotinus theory of Hypostases as a reading of Plato s metaphysics. 41 Given the close connection of fragment 221F with the beginning of Ennead V.1.8, we may suspect that fragment 222F too is connected with the same Ennead chapter, where Plotinus cites (Enn. V. 1.8,1-4) the same passage of the Pseudo-Platonic Epistle II concerning the Three Kings (312e) that Porphyry quotes in 222F. However, Porphyry unlike Plotinus quotes Plato s text directly rather than paraphrasing (and does so fairly accurately, with only minor variation from our received text of the Epistle) and makes clear what Plotinus does not, that the three kings are the same as the three gods of Numenius of Apamea 42, whereas Plotinus picks out only a few key phrases from the Epistle. Cyril s remark following the direct quotation of Porphyry s citation of the Epistle in fragment 222 is his gloss on what Porphyry is saying: He [i.e., Porphyry] shows that Plato also indicates their coming into existence (hupostasis!) from one another, and the descent and diminution of those that follow upon the First, by saying primarily, secondarily and thirdly, and that all things come from One and are preserved by it (ll. 8-12). 43 If this remark by Cyril is correct, as seems plausible, then Porphyry is endorsing Plotinus idea of the procession of the Second and Third Hypostases from the First (as well as, presumably, the Third from the Second), what is usually and somewhat misleadingly called emanation. This procession is of course not to be found explicitly anywhere in Plato s dialogues, which is why Plotinus and Porphyry, following Numenius, from whom Plotinus seems to have gotten the idea, are obliged to cite Epistle II, as here, as textual support of it. 44 The Timaeus, however, does present Cosmic Soul as produced by the Demiurge (= Nous), which may help account for Porphyry s insistence, noted above, against Plotinus that the Third Hypostasis is to be taken as Cosmic Soul and not Universal Soul. An earlier chapter of Ennead V.1, chapter 5, cites the reports of Plato s so-called Unwritten Doctrines concerning the derivation of the Dyad from the One in support of the procession of Nous (identified with the Definite Dyad) from the First Principle. My suspicion is that Plotinus has taken this too from Numenius perhaps from his best-known work, On the Good and we know from Porphyry s notorious citation of Dercyllides On Plato s philosophy in Simplicius (fr.146f Smith) that Porphyry too was interested in Plato s Unwritten Doctrines. In the earlier passage, Plotinus notes (Enn. V.1.5,6-9) that Plato s Dyad has the One as its definer (horistês, 8), which agrees with Aristotle s report of the Unwritten Doctrines in Metaphysics A, but Plotinus adds that the Dyad first proceeds, in its indefinite form, from the One, by which it is then informed and transformed into Number (= the realm of the Ideas). That the Indefinite Dyad itself proceeds from the One is a feature of the account that is not found in the reports of Plato s Unwritten Doctrines we should recall that the 1 st century BCE Academic Pythagorean- Platonist Eudorus of Alexandria wished to add it to the report of Plato s views in Aristotle s Metaphysics A6 (988a10-11) but it is ubiquitous in the versions passed down in the Neopythagorean tradition, 45 of which Numenius was an adherent and from which Plotinus has inherited it as the basis for attributing the procession to Plato. In the first fragment of Philosophical history IV cited by Cyril, fr.220f, which comes a little before fr.222 in Cyril s text, Porphyry discusses Plato s view on the First Principle itself,

7 and attributes to him a sophisticated version of apophatic or negative theology, very much along the lines of that found in Plotinus. 46 Cyril here represents Porphyry as claiming for Plato a belief in the One God (= the One as highest god), who can (following Parmenides 142a) neither be fittingly named or known by humans, so that the designations that we do use for God can only be predicated improperly or katakhrêstikôs of him. That being said, the names that are most properly (or least improperly) used of God are One and Good, i.e., the terms that Plato himself uses of the First Principle in Republic VI and in the Parmenides respectively. One indicates the divine simplicity and self-sufficiency, while Good communicates insofar as is possible that God is the source of all good things, in that all things strive for the good by imitating God (or his so-to-speak characteristic, 47 as Porphyry puts it in line 14) and are a proper understanding of this passage in its Plotinian context may call this assumption into question. Fr.223 again concerns Plato s conception of the procession of Nous (here given its proper Plotinian name for the Second Hypostasis) from the Good as First Principle. It begins as follows: From this [= the Good, as can be gathered from Cyril s opening remarks], in a way inconceivable to humans, there comes to be Nous whole and on its own, in which are contained the really real beings [= the Ideas] and the whole essence (ousia) of beings. This is also primary Beauty and Beauty-Itself, having the form of Beautifulness from itself (ll. 3-7) 48 preserved by God. Of the two designations, therefore, Good reveals the most about the (strictly inexpressible and unknowable) divine nature, its as-it-were proper characteristic (idiôtês). This is because things are made good by imitating God, who must therefore be good in some sense, at least paradigmatically so. If we could assume that Porphyry, like some later Neoplatonists, associated the goodness of things with their existence or being, this would also help explicate the notion that all things derive from the Good as first principle. Finally, let us turn to the fourth report of Porphyry s Philosophical history on Plato s doctrine that Cyril cites, fr.223f Smith (which is actually cited third by Cyril, a little after 222F). This is in several ways the most interesting and puzzling of the four Cyril fragments. I think that it too is connected with a particular passage from Plotinus early treatise on the Hypostases, So far this looks to be standard Plotinian doctrine, including the notion that Nous is the primary Beauty, 49 save for the claim that the manner of the procession is inconceivable to humans. Now Plotinus himself clearly does not think that it is wholly inconceivable to humans, since he tries to explain it in Ennead V.1 chapters 6 and 7, though not, it must be said, very successfully. In fact much scholarly ink has been spilled over the details of his attempted explanation. 50 Porphyry may have had trouble making sense of Plotinus explanation as well, and this may account for his characterization of it as inconceivable to humans. It also seems that the details of Plotinus explanation are what Porphyry has in mind in the difficult passage concerning pre-eternity and eternity that follows next (ll. 7-20): Ennead V.1, though it has so far as I am aware not previously been discussed in this regard. Discussion of the fragment has focussed rather on its strange distinction between eternity and pre-eternity, which looks to be a definite innovation by Porphyry over Plotinus. However, I think -13- [Nous] has proceeded pre-eternally, 51 starting from God as its cause, being self-generated (autogennêtos) and Father of itself (autopatôr). For it is not the case that the generation has taken -14-

8 place when the former (ekeinos = the Good) moved toward the generation of this one (toutos = Nous), but rather this one has come forth self-generated from God. And it (Nous) has not come forth from any temporal beginning. 52 For time did not yet exist, nor yet when time has come to be is time at all related to it. 53 For Nous is always 54 timeless and solely eternal. Just as the First God is always one alone 55 even if all things come from him, in virtue of the fact that he is not counted in with them nor is their value (axia) able to be compared with [literally: is not at the same level as] his existence (huparxis), 56 so too Intelligence has come to be solely eternal and timelessly, and is itself time for the things that are in time, remaining in the sameness of its own eternal existence [hupostasis: cf. Timaeus 37d6 on eternity remaining in unity ] (ll. 7-20). 57 It seems clear that Porphyry has in mind here, and is in fact glossing, the controversial and extremely obscure passage Enn. V.1.6,15-27, where Plotinus attempts to explain the generation of Nous from the One. 58 The allusion in Porphyry s phrase 1; <=$ >.(?,18.%,18!",18 0$@A <",(2%, *B, *1C*18 at lines 9-10 to Plotinus denials of motion (towards something) to the One at V.1.6,16-17 and 22-23, as well as the parallels between Plotinus explanation why time is irrelevant to his account and Porphyry s lines especially are sufficient to establish the existence of this allusion. If this be accepted, we can then ask how Porphyry is reading the disputed Plotinus passage. The central issue, notoriously, is a grammatical one: what is the subject of the participle epistraphentos at Plotinus line 18? 59 Is the subject of this participle Nous, or is it the One? In other words, is Plotinus saying that since it is impossible for the One to move towards Nous which at this point does not yet exist, so to speak in order to generate it, that it must revert upon itself to accomplish the generation of Nous (since, clearly, it can t move toward anything else), or is he saying that since the One is barred by its nature from doing anything at all in order for Nous to be generated, that Nous must in effect generate itself, by reverting (in its preliminary indefinite state of pre-intellect 60 ) toward the One? Once the question is posed, it becomes clear, I think, that Porphyry here is adopting the second reading of epistraphentos, with its subject being Nous. 61 Thus reversion (epistrophê) is being treated as a kind of motion towards something else: there is hence no notion here of any self-reversion of the One, in Porphyry s view. The idea is that Nous must first generate or constitute itself (again, in an indefinite state) so as to be able to revert upon the One and so become definite (the stage that Plotinus thinks of as corresponding to the One defining the Indefinite Dyad in Plato s Unwritten Doctrines). This line of thought leads naturally, in both the Plotinus and the Porphyry passages so interpreted, to the problem of when, so to speak, these stages of generation are supposed to be taking place, i.e., to the problem of the apparent essential temporality of the process. There is also an apparent contradiction lurking in that it would seem that Nous has first to generate itself in order to revert upon the One, i.e., in order to generate itself but apparently this is supposed to be resolved for Plotinus at least by distinguishing the two stages of Nous, indefinite and definite: neither Plotinus or Porphyry is explicit in dealing with this problem here, though Plotinus is more so elsewhere. 62 In fact, it may be the puzzling nature of this latter problem that led Porphyry to declare the whole process to be, strictly, incomprehensible to humans. In his response to the general issue about temporality, Porphyry is satisfied merely to deny that the process is temporal. Plotinus adds the somewhat helpful point that the stages in the temporal account are supposed to be analogues of (eternal) relations of causality and effect/product among the items in the account, that is, to reflect the fact that the One is the cause of the generation of

9 Nous (6,18-22). Plotinus seems to be thinking here of what might be called a process of eternal generation, but Porphryry goes farther and speaks of it as being pre-eternal. 63 If Porphyry s notion of pre-eternality is supposed to explain anything here, I think it must be that the process is supposed to account for the generation of eternity itself, so that talk of eternal generation is out of place. But if this is so, we see Porphyry attempting to clear up a difficult point in Plotinus account by expanding on it. How can the One be called the cause (aition, fr.223f7-8) of the generation of Nous, if Nous is self-generated? The answer to this must again lie in the two stages of generation: the One is the cause of the outflowing of the indefinite pre-nous (cf. Enn. V.2.1, the image of the fountain overflowing), which then generates itself or bootstraps itself into existence in reverting on the One. Our Porphyry fragment, however, appears innocent of all these complexities, perhaps because he thought them to be incomprehensible to the human mind. What Porphyry does add to the Plotinian picture is the distinction between pre-eternity and eternity, which seems intended to express the idea that the generation of Nous (identified with eternity) takes place, not only before time, but so to speak before eternity as well. 64 Now the concept of pre-eternity is also found in the unique fragment of Porphyry s On principles from Proclus Platonic theology (fr.232f Smith), which speaks of the pre-eternal element within the eternal Nous and connecting it with the One, rather than as here in fr.223f of its procession from the One or First Principle before eternity. This would seem to be linked to the notorious difficulty about Porphyry s having posited the One as Father of the so-called First Intelligible Triad Being/Existence-Life-Intelligence (Nous) (Damascius Prin. I.86 Ruelle, cf. also Proclus In Parm and Anon. In Parm fr.ix init.) 65 Note that in our fr.223 of the Philosophical history, Nous is said to be its own father, while in the On Principles fragment the pre-eternal element (presumably to be somehow identified with the One and perhaps also with pre-nous) is within the Hypostasis Nous, so that as it were Nous contains its father within itself. We also see in our fragment the important and seemingly opposed notion that the One is not to be counted in with (sunarithmeisthai) other things. This has already come up in the perhaps Porphyrian sequel to fr.221 (ll. 6-12), which I omitted to discuss above, where certain unnamed and mysterious 66 persons are said to object to the Plotinian account of the Hypostases that the First Principle should not be counted in with the other two Hypostases (line 9). This echoes known criticisms of Porphyry elsewhere for counting in the First Principle as the Father of the First Intelligible Triad (cf. the Damascius passage), and may represent Porphyry himself stating this objection against his own view, or against his own interpretation of Plotinus metaphysical view. This paradox, concerning the One in Porphyry s thought both being conceived as somehow a constituent of Nous and on the other hand as strictly transcending it as its source, has been connected by Hadot and Dillon with similar themes in the Anonymous Parmenides commentary (fr. XI-XII) concerning the dual status of the One of the Second Hypothesis, as both somehow being identical with the strictly transcendent One of the First Hypothesis and as also having its role as constituent of the One-Being of the Second Hypothesis, which on the Neoplatonic interpretation is to be identified with the Hypostasis Nous. 67 In my view, as in Hadot s, these parallels provide rather strong evidence in favor of his attribution of the Anonymous Commentary to Porphyry, and I do not think that they have been sufficiently appreciated in recent controversies over this attribution. Proper discussion of this issue, however, would take us far beyond what I have tried to do here. There are also rather striking resemblances in both language and doctrine between the Anonymous Commentary and the fragments from Book IV of

10 Porphyry s Philosophical history that we have been discussing. Most or all of them were pointed out by Hadot in his monumental Porphyre et Victorinus, 68 but they also have not been made enough of in the recent controversies over the authorship of the Commentary. Let me just mention here two points from fragment 220F. First is the term prosegoriai for the designations or denominations of the First God, which though a common technical term of the period occurs in the same context in Anonymous fr. I The doctrinal point is similar there too, concerning the applicability of the name One to the First Principle. 70 Much of the text of the Commentary s fragments as we have them is concerned with negative theology, the difficulty of talking sensibly about the first God, identified with the One of the First Hypothesis of Plato s Parmenides. The main point of Anonymous fr.1 seems to be, as in Philosophical history fr. 220, main reading of the Ennead V.1.6 passage, according to which the One generates Nous by itself moving towards its generation. 74 This does not much affect his case for identifying the Anonymous Commentator with Porphyry, since he does call attention to the parallels between the account of the relationship between the First and Second Ones of the Parmenides in the Anonymous Commentary, frs. XI-XII 75 and Porphyry s account of the self-generation of Nous in Philosophical history fr.223f, as well as between the discussion of the relation of the One to the First Intelligible Triad in fr.ix,1-7 and fr.223f and the Damascius passage. Does my new reconstruction of Porphyry s interpretation of Plotinus account of the generation of Nous increase the probability that the Anonymous Commentator is Porphyry? This remains an open question, but certainly it seems to bring the Anonymous into closer proximity to Plotinus. 76 that One, though in some ways quite inadequate as a designation of the First, is nonetheless most appropriate among human names for this role: in particular it is the cause of the being of other things (fr.i.10-12, cfr. fr.ii ). Elsewhere the One is also said to be responsible for the preservation (sôteria, fr. V.6 72 ) of other things, recalling 220F15. Another striking parallel comes at the end of the first fragment of the Commentary, where it is denied that the One can be conceived in terms of activity, thought or simplicity, recalling the statement of fr.220f10-12 (which however affirms the One s simplicity and denies its need of parts). 73 There are other linguistic and doctrinal parallels noted by Hadot, but the general impression certainly seems to support Hadot s identification of the Anonymous with Porphyry. However Hadot, like other commentators, fails to note the close connection I have pointed to between Philosophical history fr.223f and Plotinus account of the generation of Nous from the One in Ennead V.1.6, where Porphyry seems to be identifying his own account of Nous s socalled self-generation with Plotinus account. Instead, Hadot is on record as advocating the other 1 See on this point Andrew Smith, Porphyry s place in the Neoplatonic tradition (The Hague 1974), Introduction xii ff. Part One of Smith s book, chapters 1-5, deals extensively with the question of Porphyry s originality vis-à-vis Plotinus in psychology, rather than in metaphysics in general, with which I will be concerned here. 2 The Life of Pythagoras originally formed part of the first book of Porphyry s Philosophical history, from which come the fragments on Platonic metaphysics which will be discussed in the last part of this paper. 3 The Later Neoplatonists, in A. H. Armstrong, ed., The Cambridge history of later Greek and early medieval philosophy (Cambridge 1967) Porphyry, Sententiae ad intelligibilia ducentes, ed. E. Lamberz (Leipzig 1975). 5 A good example is Sententiae ch.32 on the scale of types of virtues, which presents an interesting rational reconstruction of Plotinus discussion of the same topic in his tractate on the virtues, Ennead I.2. 6 Ibid Ibid M. Zambon, Porphyre et le Moyen-Platonisme (Paris 2002) mentions two supposed

11 differences between the metaphysics of the Sententiae and that of Plotinus: a stronger contrast between being and non-being, approaching a dualism, and a rigidifying of the differences between the various hierachical levels. But if these are indeed genuine disagreements with Plotinus (which I doubt) they amount at most to differences of emphasis, or would not have been seen as disagreements by Porphyry himself. 9 There is quite a bit about the Hypostases in the Sententiae as well, but I will not have anything more to say about this work. 10 Porphyre (Entretiens Hardt 12 [1965]) Contrast on this point A. C. Lloyd, The anatomy of Neoplatonism (Oxford 1990) , who in my view fails to distinguish Plotinus Platonic dialectic sufficiently from Aristotelian logic. 12 Cf. Hadot, op. cit Politics is presumably to be classified with ethics. This arrangement is Aristotelian only in that it distinguishes physics from metaphysics, which it places above physics: it does not, for instance, respect Aristotle s fundamental distinction between practical and theoretical philosophy (and much of ethics would perhaps count as theoretical). But it does seem to be connected with the idea that logic, as in Aristotle, is an instrument or organon of philosophy, not a part of philosophy, as it had been for the Stoics, a view that Plotinus certainly also accepts: cf. Enn. I.3.4-5, where formal logic is compared to learning grammar as a propaedeutic study. 13 Cf. Zambon, op. cit., on Porphyry s continuity with Middle Platonism. I do not wish to deny that Plotinus thought is generally continuous with Middle Platonism as well, but at least on the issues mentioned, Plotinus seems to exhibit a notable degree of innovation. On the transcendence of the Plotinian One as an innovation, see especially P. Meijer, Plotinus on the Good or the One (Enneads VI,9): an analytical commentary (Amsterdam 1992). 14 See below on Porphyry s interpretation of Enn. V.1.7 fin. 15 Hadot, op. cit An exception is Enn. I.3.5-6, where dialectic is connected with wisdom (sophia, 6,12-13) as the highest and most valuable part of philosophy and distinguished from physics and ethics, while logic of the Aristotelian sort is declared not to be a part of philosophy or a concern of the real philosopher probably, not even as an organon (cf. 5,10). 17 Porphyry actually asserts at Vita Plotini 23,15-16 that the telos for Plotinus was union with the -21- One. Insofar as Ennead I.4 can be taken as a definitive statement of Plotinus ethics, this does not seem to be the case. 18 Plotinus, Porphyry and the Neoplatonic interpretation of the Categories, Aufstieg und Niedergang der römischen Welt II.36.2 (1987) Neoplatonic logic and Aristotelian logic, Phronesis 1 ( ) 58-72, See also especially F. J. De Haas, Did Plotinus and Porphyry disagree about Aristotle s Categories?, Phronesis 46 (2001) and Context and strategy of Plotinus treatise On the genera of Being VI.1-3 in V. Celluprica and C. D Ancona, eds., Aristotele e i suoi esegeti neoplatonici (Naples 2004), pp I find myself in in general agreement with De Haas s view of the attitude of Plotinus and Porphyry to Aristotle: I only wish to emphasize here a few salient points. For a thorough defense of the more traditional view of Plotinus attitude to Aristotle, see most recently R. Chiaradonna, Sostanza movimento analogia: Plotino critico di Aristotele (Naples 2002). 20 As is also seen, more explicitly, in the slightly later Categories commentary by the Iamblichean Dexippus. 21 Again, see the above-cited works of De Haas. He notes the view of the Categories as being about the genera of being, which is attacked by Plotinus, as being Alexander s, but does not, I think, sufficiently stress this. De Haas also sees that Plotinus seems to be attributing to Aristotle the view which he thinks is correct that the category-classes of the Categories are what Plotinus calls katêgoriai and not genera of being. 22 A similar situation arises with respect to Plotinus critique of Aristotle s theory of time in his treatise on eternity and time, Ennead III.7. In chapter 9 and following of this treatise, Plotinus subjects Aristotle s proposed definition of time from Physics IV as the number of motion (kinêsis) to a devastating critique, but later explains that he does not actually think that Aristotle meant to propose this characterization as a definition, and that the tradition has misunderstood him on this point: he meant instead that time is what is measured by motion, not what measures it, and we misunderstand him because his text was intended to be esoteric, and only read by students who had been attending his lectures, who would have been able to comprehend what he was up to (III.7.13,10-18). On Plotinus critique here, see my essay Plotinus on the Nature of Eternity and Time, in Lawrence Schrenk, ed., Aristotle in Late Antiquity (Washington, DC -22-

12 1994) On all this, see now J. Barnes, Porphyry: Introduction (Oxford 2003), Additional Note G. 24 L harmonie des philosophies de Plotin et d Aristote selon Porphyre dans le commentaire de Déxippe sur les Catégories, in Plotino e il neoplatonismo in Oriente e in Occidente (Rome 1974), 31-47: English translation by V. Caston in R. Sorabji, ed., Aristotle transformed: the ancient commentators and their influence (London 1990) Porphyry s fragments will be cited in the edition of Andrew Smith, Porphyrii philosophi fragmenta (Stuttgart and Leipzig 1993). The title of the present work is reminiscent of Numenius of Apamea s polemic against the skeptical Academy, On the dissension [also D%32*E2%A] of the Academy with Plato. 26 George Karamanolis argues persuasively in his forthcoming book that they were indeed different works, but both upheld the essential agreement of Plato and Aristotle. I am grateful to Karamanolis for allowing me to see his unpublished work on this topic. 27 I say this even though I assume that title reported in the Suida lexicon Against Aristotle concerning whether the soul is an entelechy (P31 Smith) refers to the same work of Porphyry against Boethus, for the report could be confused about the work s contents (see Smith s apparatus to P31 for this possibility). See also A. Smith, A Porphyrian treatise against Aristotle?, in F. X. Martin and J. A. Richmond, eds., From Augustine to Eriugena : essays on Neoplatonism and Christianity in honor of John O'Meara (Washington, D. C. 1991) The principle issue regards whether frs.245f and 245F Smith are directed against Aristotle himself, or against members of the Peripatetic tradition (i.e., Boethus). 28 It should be noted that according to the fragments of On providence of the 5 th century Alexandrian Neoplatonist Hierocles (apud Photius codd. 214 and 251), the essential harmony of the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle was a basic tenet of the school of Ammonius the teacher of Plotinus. This testimony, though isolated, is perhaps not to be lightly dismissed, since it seems to come through the Academy of Plutarch of Athens and may derive from the above-mentioned work or works of Porphyry on the agreement or disagreement of Plato and Aristotle. See now on Hierocles work H. Schibli, Hierocles of Alexandria (Oxford 2002). 29 See the commentary on this text by W. Helleman-Elgersma, Soul sisters: a Commentary on Enneads IV 3 (27), 1-8 of Plotinus (Amsterdam 1980), who is convincing on this point I exclude Porphyry s commentary on the Harmonics of Ptolemy, which does however contain passages of considerable philosophical interest. Only the very end of Book IV of the De abstinentia is missing. The work is now conveniently accessible in an excellent English translation, with copious notes, by Gillian Clark: Porphyry, On abstinence from killing animals (London 2000). 31 Compare Amelius reference in his letter to Porphyry (Vita Plotini 17,39) to Plotinus philosophy as our spiritual home (5 1F.(GE H2*?E, trans. A. H. Armstrong). 32 There is a problem in that Porphyry seems to think of the full accomplishment of the ethical goal in terms of complete detachment from worldly concerns, and even from awareness of this world, whereas Plotinus appears to think that the sage will be able to be active in the world even while retaining his unbroken contemplation of the intelligible (and in fact Porphyry describes Plotinus in such terms in the Life). I am indebted to Kelly E. Arenson for calling this problem to my attention. The solution is perhaps that Porphyry in De abstinentia I is discussing the conditions under which the re-ascent and rejoining with the higher self can be accomplished, and not what would be possible for the ascended sage after he has reached the stage of eudaimonia described in Ennead I There are actually five fragments of Book IV preserved by Cyril, but the first one (219F Smith) concerns only details of Plato s biography, not metaphysics. 34 &#$% <=$ *$%+, /012*32(4, IJK 'L3*4, *B, *16 M(?18 0$1(LM(G, 1;2?E,. Translations of the fragments of the Philosophical History are my own. 35 NE)!"#$% *1C*4, *= M(GE, Enn. V.1.7, &#$% <=$ 98#OA *B, M(7*K*E 0$1(LM(G,. This second parallel, though not the earlier one, is noted by Smith in his apparatus. 37 L1%07, DP *@ &M(1, -0@ *OA 24!E*%.OA >,O$#ME% D%EJ1$QA. 38 DK!%18$<@A <=$ R,16A E;*S. 39 See n27 above. 40 This may be connected with Porphyry s claim elsewhere that the Demiurge for Plotinus (not Plato!) is the immanent nous of the World-Soul, which suggests that the alteration to Plotinus formulation in our fragment may be deliberate on Porphyry s part. See W. Deuse, Der Demiurg bei Porphyrios und Jamblich, in C. Zintzen, ed., Der Philosophie des Neuplatonismus -24-

7AAN2031 Greek Philosophy III: Special Topics Neoplatonism Syllabus Academic year 2014/5

7AAN2031 Greek Philosophy III: Special Topics Neoplatonism Syllabus Academic year 2014/5 7AAN2031 Greek Philosophy III: Special Topics Neoplatonism Syllabus Academic year 2014/5 Basic information Credits: 20 Module Tutor: Dr. Raphael Woolf Office: 712 Consultation time: TBA Semester: 2 Lecture

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres [ Loyola Book Comp., run.tex: 0 AQR Vol. W rev. 0, 17 Jun 2009 ] [The Aquinas Review Vol. W rev. 0: 1 The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic From at least the time of John of St. Thomas, scholastic

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95. REVIEW St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp. 172. $5.95. McInerny has succeeded at a demanding task: he has written a compact

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Edinburgh Research Explorer

Edinburgh Research Explorer Edinburgh Research Explorer Review of Remembering Socrates: Philosophical Essays Citation for published version: Mason, A 2007, 'Review of Remembering Socrates: Philosophical Essays' Notre Dame Philosophical

More information

1. By the Common Era, many ideas were held in common by the various schools of thought which originated from the Greek period of the 4 th c. BCE.

1. By the Common Era, many ideas were held in common by the various schools of thought which originated from the Greek period of the 4 th c. BCE. Theo 424 Early Christianity Session 7: The Influence of Intellectual Thought Page 1 Reading assignment: Meeks, The Moral World of the First Christians 40-64; Course Reader 86-91 (Kelly 14-22; Ferguson

More information

Reviewed by Sean Michael Pead Coughlin University of Western Ontario

Reviewed by Sean Michael Pead Coughlin University of Western Ontario Simplicius: On Aristotle, On the Heavens 3.1--7 translated by Ian Mueller London: Duckworth, 2009. Pp. viii + 182. ISBN 978--0--7156--3843--9. Cloth 60.00 Reviewed by Sean Michael Pead Coughlin University

More information

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau Volume 12, No 2, Fall 2017 ISSN 1932-1066 Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau edmond_eh@usj.edu.mo Abstract: This essay contains an

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle

The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle The Sea-Fight Tomorrow by Aristotle Aristotle, Antiquities Project About the author.... Aristotle (384-322) studied for twenty years at Plato s Academy in Athens. Following Plato s death, Aristotle left

More information

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation Reply to Cover Dennis Plaisted, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation ofleibniz's views on relations is surely to

More information

D. The Truth as a Surd

D. The Truth as a Surd D. The Truth as a Surd 1] The saying God is an inexpressible number (αριθμοσ αρρητοσ θεοσ ) is attributed to a thinker named Lysis, (c. 425 B.C.). Assuming that this refers to the work being done in incommensurable

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Collection and Division in the Philebus

Collection and Division in the Philebus Collection and Division in the Philebus 1 Collection and Division in the Philebus Hugh H. Benson Readers of Aristotle s Posterior Analytics will be familiar with the idea that Aristotle distinguished roughly

More information

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. Ordinatio prologue, q. 5, nn. 270 313 A. The views of others 270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. 217]. There are five ways to answer in the negative. [The

More information

CURRICULUM VITAE. George Karamanolis

CURRICULUM VITAE. George Karamanolis 1 CURRICULUM VITAE George Karamanolis Research Interests Ancient Philosophy (especially Plato and History of Platonism, Hellenistic Philosophy, Philosophy of Late Antiquity), Medieval Philosophy Education

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation

Plato's Parmenides and the Dilemma of Participation 1 di 5 27/12/2018, 18:22 Theory and History of Ontology by Raul Corazzon e-mail: rc@ontology.co INTRODUCTION: THE ANCIENT INTERPRETATIONS OF PLATOS' PARMENIDES "Plato's Parmenides was probably written

More information

Plotinus and Aquinas on God. A thesis presented to. the faculty of. the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University. In partial fulfillment

Plotinus and Aquinas on God. A thesis presented to. the faculty of. the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University. In partial fulfillment Plotinus and Aquinas on God A thesis presented to the faculty of the College of Arts and Sciences of Ohio University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Master of Arts Steven L. Kimbler

More information

Development of Thought. The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which

Development of Thought. The word philosophy comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which Development of Thought The word "philosophy" comes from the Ancient Greek philosophia, which literally means "love of wisdom". The pre-socratics were 6 th and 5 th century BCE Greek thinkers who introduced

More information

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB 1 1Aristotle s Categories in St. Augustine by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Because St. Augustine begins to talk about substance early in the De Trinitate (1, 1, 1), a notion which he later equates with essence

More information

Ancient perspectives on Aristotle s theory of the soul as a hylomorphic form from Aristotle to Plotinus: Epiphenomenalism, Emergentism and Dualism

Ancient perspectives on Aristotle s theory of the soul as a hylomorphic form from Aristotle to Plotinus: Epiphenomenalism, Emergentism and Dualism Ancient perspectives on Aristotle s theory of the soul as a hylomorphic form from Aristotle to Plotinus: Epiphenomenalism, Emergentism and Dualism Abstract Riccardo Chiaradonna Rome, Nov. 28, 2016 The

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy

Shanghai Jiao Tong University. PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy Shanghai Jiao Tong University PI913 History of Ancient Greek Philosophy Instructor: Juan De Pascuale Email: depascualej@kenyon.edu Home Institution: Office Hours: Kenyon College Office: 505 Main Bldg Term:

More information

Contents. Introduction 8

Contents. Introduction 8 Contents Introduction 8 Chapter 1: Early Greek Philosophy: The Pre-Socratics 17 Cosmology, Metaphysics, and Epistemology 18 The Early Cosmologists 18 Being and Becoming 24 Appearance and Reality 26 Pythagoras

More information

Reply to Florio and Shapiro

Reply to Florio and Shapiro Reply to Florio and Shapiro Abstract Florio and Shapiro take issue with an argument in Hierarchies for the conclusion that the set theoretic hierarchy is open-ended. Here we clarify and reinforce the argument

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome In Works of Love, Søren Kierkegaard professes that (Christian) love is the bridge between the temporal and the eternal. 1 More specifically, he asserts that undertaking to unconditionally obey the Christian

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION?

DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? 221 DO TROPES RESOLVE THE PROBLEM OF MENTAL CAUSATION? BY PAUL NOORDHOF One of the reasons why the problem of mental causation appears so intractable

More information

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms?

Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Does the Third Man Argument refute the theory of forms? Fine [1993] recognises four versions of the Third Man Argument (TMA). However, she argues persuasively that these are similar arguments with similar

More information

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY Science and the Future of Mankind Pontifical Academy of Sciences, Scripta Varia 99, Vatican City 2001 www.pas.va/content/dam/accademia/pdf/sv99/sv99-berti.pdf THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION

More information

Plato's Introduction of Forms (review)

Plato's Introduction of Forms (review) Plato's Introduction of Forms (review) Lloyd P. Gerson Mouseion: Journal of the Classical Association of Canada, Volume 7, Number 1, 2007, LI Series III, pp. 83-87 (Review) Published by University of Toronto

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and

BOOK REVIEWS. The arguments of the Parmenides, though they do not refute the Theory of Forms, do expose certain problems, ambiguities and BOOK REVIEWS Unity and Development in Plato's Metaphysics. By William J. Prior. London & Sydney, Croom Helm, 1986. pp201. Reviewed by J. Angelo Corlett, University of California Santa Barbara. Prior argues

More information

NEOPLATONISM, THEN AND NOW. Date:

NEOPLATONISM, THEN AND NOW. Date: NEOPLATONISM, THEN AND NOW Date: 2-11-2014 OPENING WORDS Earlier this year, I undertook a twelve-week philosophy course at Sydney Community College, in Rozelle. It was a fairly easygoing, yet exhaustive

More information

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications Julia Lei Western University ABSTRACT An account of our metaphysical nature provides an answer to the question of what are we? One such account

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

X/$ c Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, 2004 AQUINAS S VIEWS ON MIND AND SOUL: ECHOES OF PLATONISM. Patrick Quinn

X/$ c Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, 2004 AQUINAS S VIEWS ON MIND AND SOUL: ECHOES OF PLATONISM. Patrick Quinn Verbum VI/1, pp. 85 93 1585-079X/$ 20.00 c Akadémiai Kiadó, Budapest, 2004 AQUINAS S VIEWS ON MIND AND SOUL: ECHOES OF PLATONISM Patrick Quinn All Hallows College Department of Philosophy Grace Park Road,

More information

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3

OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor OSSA Conference Archive OSSA 3 May 15th, 9:00 AM - May 17th, 5:00 PM Commentary on Schwed Lawrence Powers Follow this and additional works at: https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 16 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. At

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms

* I am indebted to Jay Atlas and Robert Schwartz for their helpful criticisms HEMPEL, SCHEFFLER, AND THE RAVENS 1 7 HEMPEL, SCHEFFLER, AND THE RAVENS * EMPEL has provided cogent reasons in support of the equivalence condition as a condition of adequacy for any definition of confirmation.?

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak.

Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. On Interpretation By Aristotle Based on the translation by E. M. Edghill, with minor emendations by Daniel Kolak. First we must define the terms 'noun' and 'verb', then the terms 'denial' and 'affirmation',

More information

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) The Names of God from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) For with respect to God, it is more apparent to us what God is not, rather

More information

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein

Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David Bronstein Marquette University e-publications@marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 4-1-2017 Review of Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics by David

More information

Categories and On Interpretation. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey

Categories and On Interpretation. Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Categories and On Interpretation Philosophy 21 Fall, 2004 G. J. Mattey Aristotle Born 384 BC From Stagira, ancient Macedonia Student and lecturer in Plato s Academy Teacher of Alexander the Great Founder

More information

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT Aristotle was, perhaps, the greatest original thinker who ever lived. Historian H J A Sire has put the issue well: All other thinkers have begun with a theory and sought to fit reality

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 2 - Methods of knowledge - Inference, dialectic and Plato. justification Platonic Model Divided Line -

Introduction to Philosophy Lecture 2 - Methods of knowledge - Inference, dialectic and Plato. justification Platonic Model Divided Line - Introduction to Philosophy - 2 nd and 3 rd terms. Greenwich University, PHIL1005 Tutor: Matt Lee - lm57@gre.ac.uk Course website: http://notebookeleven.com Lecture 2 - Methods of knowledge - Inference,

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 35 The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper, I will critically examine Christine Korsgaard s claim

More information

The Interpretative Differences between Philo and The Secret Revelation of John

The Interpretative Differences between Philo and The Secret Revelation of John 1 William L&S 20C The Bible in Western Culture Professor Ronald Hendel The Interpretative Differences between Philo and The Secret Revelation of John Comparing Philo s biblical interpretations with those

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions

Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions Reviews Andrei Marmor: Social Conventions Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2009, xii + 186 pp. A few decades ago, only isolated groups of philosophers counted the phenomenon of normativity as one

More information

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents ERWIN TEGTMEIER, MANNHEIM There was a vivid and influential dialogue of Western philosophy with Ibn Sina in the Middle Ages; but there can be also a fruitful dialogue

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms

The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms MP_C06.qxd 11/17/06 5:28 PM Page 66 6 The Summa Lamberti on the Properties of Terms [1. General Introduction] (205) Because the logician considers terms, it is appropriate for him to give an account of

More information

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia

The Trinity and the Enhypostasia 0 The Trinity and the Enhypostasia CYRIL C. RICHARDSON NE learns from one's critics; and I should like in this article to address myself to a fundamental point which has been raised by critics (both the

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree.

McKenzie Study Center, an Institute of Gutenberg College. Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree. , an Institute of Gutenberg College Handout 5 The Bible and the History of Ideas Teacher: John A. Jack Crabtree Aristotle A. Aristotle (384 321 BC) was the tutor of Alexander the Great. 1. Socrates taught

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

Resurrection: The Hope of Worms Enrica Ruaro Iamblichus and the Intermediate Nature of the Human Soul John F.

Resurrection: The Hope of Worms Enrica Ruaro Iamblichus and the Intermediate Nature of the Human Soul John F. Table des matières Préface... 1 Jean-Marc Narbonne The Unity of the Tripartite Soul in Plato s Republic 4... 3 Aristotle to Plotinus on the Status of Nous: The Passage from Dualism to Monism... 15 Mark

More information

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views by Philip Sherrard Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Spring 1973) World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com ONE of the

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT

Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT 74 Between the Species Korsgaard and Non-Sentient Life ABSTRACT Christine Korsgaard argues for the moral status of animals and our obligations to them. She grounds this obligation on the notion that we

More information

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY

404 Ethics January 2019 I. TOPICS II. METHODOLOGY 404 Ethics January 2019 Kamtekar, Rachana. Plato s Moral Psychology: Intellectualism, the Divided Soul, and the Desire for the Good. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018. Pp. 240. $55.00 (cloth). I. TOPICS

More information

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski J Agric Environ Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10806-016-9627-6 REVIEW PAPER Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski Mark Coeckelbergh 1 David J. Gunkel 2 Accepted: 4 July

More information

"Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages

Can We Have a Word in Private?: Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Macalester Journal of Philosophy Volume 14 Issue 1 Spring 2005 Article 11 5-1-2005 "Can We Have a Word in Private?": Wittgenstein on the Impossibility of Private Languages Dan Walz-Chojnacki Follow this

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

Aristotle and the Soul

Aristotle and the Soul Aristotle and the Soul (Please note: These are rough notes for a lecture, mostly taken from the relevant sections of Philosophy and Ethics and other publications and should not be reproduced or otherwise

More information

Pythagoras, b. Samos 586 B.C.E. first coined the word philosophia (Love of Wisdom). Called the Yavancharya (Ionian Teacher) in India

Pythagoras, b. Samos 586 B.C.E. first coined the word philosophia (Love of Wisdom). Called the Yavancharya (Ionian Teacher) in India PORPHYRY S VIEW OF THE ASCENT OF THE SOUL Institute of World Culture December 1, 2007 Judy D. Saltzman IMPORTANT PHILOSOPHERS AND SCHOLARS Pythagoras, b. Samos 586 B.C.E. first coined the word philosophia

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

Boethius, logic, and time: The story thus far

Boethius, logic, and time: The story thus far Boethius, logic, and time: The story thus far The 5 th century philosopher and theologian, Boethius, has attracted much study over the last fifty years. I will examine some studies on Boethius's logic,

More information

Is Plotinus a Platonist?

Is Plotinus a Platonist? Is Plotinus a Platonist? Professor John P. Anton, University of South Florida I I t has been noted that Plotinus has repeatedly, as we shall see, acknowledged his indebtedness to Plato. A question still

More information

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1

On Interpretation. Section 1. Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill. Part 1 On Interpretation Aristotle Translated by E. M. Edghill Section 1 Part 1 First we must define the terms noun and verb, then the terms denial and affirmation, then proposition and sentence. Spoken words

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism

Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism Spinoza s Modal-Ontological Argument for Monism One of Spinoza s clearest expressions of his monism is Ethics I P14, and its corollary 1. 1 The proposition reads: Except God, no substance can be or be

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria

PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT. Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE LET THOMAS AQUINAS TEACH IT by Joseph Kenny, O.P. St. Thomas Aquinas Priory Ibadan, Nigeria 2012 PREFACE Philosophy of nature is in a way the most important course in Philosophy. Metaphysics

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths

Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Molnar on Truthmakers for Negative Truths Nils Kürbis Dept of Philosophy, King s College London Penultimate draft, forthcoming in Metaphysica. The final publication is available at www.reference-global.com

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles

Aquinas on Spiritual Change. In Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft), Myles Aquinas on Spiritual Change In "Is an Aristotelian Philosophy of Mind Still Credible? (A draft)," Myles Burnyeat challenged the functionalist interpretation of Aristotle by defending Aquinas's understanding

More information

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle

The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle This paper is dedicated to my unforgettable friend Boris Isaevich Lamdon. The Development of Laws of Formal Logic of Aristotle The essence of formal logic The aim of every science is to discover the laws

More information

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven:

ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven: ON EFFICIENT CAUSALITY: METAPHYSICAL DISPUTATIONS 17,18, AND 19. By FRANCISCO SUAREZ. Translated By ALFRED J. FREDDOSO. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994. Pp. xx, 428. A quick scan of the leading

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING

Richard L. W. Clarke, Notes REASONING 1 REASONING Reasoning is, broadly speaking, the cognitive process of establishing reasons to justify beliefs, conclusions, actions or feelings. It also refers, more specifically, to the act or process

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Spinoza s Metaphysics: Substance and Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, xxii + 232 p. Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington I n his important new study of

More information

Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo *

Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo * Journal of Pentecostal Theology 20 (2011) 184 190 brill.nl/pent Pentecostals and Divine Impassibility: A Response to Daniel Castelo * Andrew K. Gabriel ** Horizon College and Seminary, 1303 Jackson Ave.,

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY *

Dartmouth College THE DIVINE SIMPLICITY * 628 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY I do not deny that violence is sometimes even required by public reason and that considerably more violence is allowed by public reason, but I think there can be no doubt

More information