Measuring the burden of disease by measuring wellbeing John Broome For the WHO s volume on summary measures of population health

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Measuring the burden of disease by measuring wellbeing John Broome For the WHO s volume on summary measures of population health"

Transcription

1 Measuring the burden of disease by measuring wellbeing John Broome For the WHO s volume on summary measures of population health 1. Distributions of wellbeing We are interested in measuring the harm that is done by disease. To look at the question practically and positively, we are interested in measuring the good that will be done by reducing disease. The diagram illustrates very schematically the problem of measurement that concerns us. It illustrates the effects of a single epidemic. Imagine the epidemic is expected in the future, and that it might be possible to prevent it by some public health measure. We want to measure how much harm the epidemic will do. Conversely this comes to the same thing we want to measure the benefit that will be achieved by preventing the epidemic. The diagram has two halves. The right half shows what will happen if the epidemic occurs; the left what will happen if it is prevented. Each half is a multiple graph. In each, time is measured in a horizontal direction. A vertical dotted line marks the date when the epidemic occurs, if it does. Each horizontal dotted line marks out the life of a single person; corresponding lines in the two halves of the diagram belong to the same person. Each line is the horizontal axis of a little graph that shows the course of the person s life. A person s graph begins at the time she is born and ends when she dies. During her life, the height of the graph above the axis represents the person s wellbeing how well her life is going. One line in the diagram has no graph on it; this indicates that one particular person will not live at all if the epidemic occurs. The diagram shows the following effects caused by the epidemic. All of them are typical of disease.

2 One person is killed at the time of the epidemic. One person is disabled by the epidemic, but her life is not shortened. One person s life is shortened by the epidemic, but she does not die immediately. One person who would have been born is not born as a result of the epidemic (perhaps because one of her parents is killed). One person born later, who would have been born healthy is born disabled (perhaps because of genetic damage to one of her parents). Our measure of the harm done by the epidemic must take into account events of all these sorts. The diagram shows that, although the epidemic occurs at a single date, its effects are spread across time. This is typical of disease, and complicates our attempt to measure it. In practice, we are rarely dealing with the effects of a single epidemic. Disease is always with us, and the effort to control it always continues. Still, we shall want to know how much harm is done by the disease that occurs at a particular date, or how much benefit is achieved by a particular development in public health. This means we need to sort out the effects of events that occur at one date from the effect of events that occur at other dates. When causes act continuously, as diseases do, this is complicated. In this paper, I shall not try to sort out these causal matters. That is why I have chosen to illustrate the problem of measurement with the comparatively simple example of a single epidemic. The vertical dimension in the diagram shows the wellbeing people enjoy at particular times. I shall call this temporal wellbeing whenever I need to in order to avert confusion. There are serious difficulties about measuring it, both in theory and in practice. In this paper, I shall have to skate over most of those difficulties. 1 I shall simply assume temporal wellbeing can be measured on a cardinal scale that is comparable both between different times and between different people. The zero on the scale is also important, and I shall say something about it in section 7. To measure the harm done by the epidemic, we need to compare the values of the states of affairs shown in the two halves of the diagram. The harm is the difference between their values. I assume that the value of a state of affairs is determined only by the factors that are illustrated in the diagram. That is to say, it is determined by which people exist, by the dates when those people are born and die, by their temporal wellbeing at all the times they are alive, and by nothing else. That is to say, the value is determined only by the distribution of wellbeing. The diagram shows two alternative distributions. Our general task is to measure the value of distributions like this. The value of a state of affairs is some sort of an aggregate of people s temporal wellbeing. Somehow, the wellbeing of all the people, at every time they are alive, comes together to determine the overall value of the state of affairs. This is a two-dimensional aggregation; we have to aggregate across people and also across time. When I speak of aggregation, I do not necessarily mean simply adding up; an aggregate may be a much more complicated compound than a simple total. The main subject of this paper is to work out how this aggregation should be done. As it turns out, I shall give support to aggregation by addition. 2. Why wellbeing and not health? Why does my diagram show people s wellbeing, as opposed to their state of health? Since we are trying to measure health, surely it is health we should be looking at. Health is a part of wellbeing, but it is not the whole of it. So why in the diagram have I not shown just the component of wellbeing that is health? 2

3 Elsewhere in this volume, 2 I argue that we cannot separate out health as a component of wellbeing. So in fact I have no choice. But I think it should also be clear that we should not want to separate it out. We are interested in the harm done by disease, and the benefit caused by preventing disease. Disease causes harms of a great many sorts, which are often not themselves specifically changes in health. For example, some diseases prevent their victims from working, and so deprive them of income and the other benefits that accompany work: companionship, self-esteem and so on. Indeed, the harms that are always treated as changes in health often consist in deprivation of goods other than health. For example, in measures of health, death is universally included as a loss of health. But death is bad at least partly because it deprives its victim of all the good things she would have enjoyed in the rest of her life. These are goods of all sorts, and not only elements of health. So the badness of death consists in the loss of many things that are not themselves elements of health. Similarly, much of the harm caused by disabilities is not particularly a matter of health. For instance, if you are paralysed, you do not have access to many of the ordinary goods that other people enjoy. That is a major part of your loss. So we ought not to be trying to measure the harm done by disease in terms of health only, but in terms of the whole of wellbeing. The measure we shall emerge with may accurately be called a measure of the burden of disease, but it would be inaccurate to call it a measure of health. If it is not a measure of health, why should the World Health Organization take any particular interest in it? Because it measures the harm caused by disease, or the benefit caused by controlling disease. The cause is specifically to do with health. The effect is harm or benefit in general. In practice we need a measure now, and we cannot wait till someone has developed a way to measure wellbeing. We will not soon have a good theory of wellbeing, let alone a practical way of measuring it. Yet we do already have sensible measures of a person s health. More accurately, we have measures of the badness of particular sorts of ill-health. 3 I think it is sensible to start using these measures immediately, but recognize that they are only approximations. All the measures we have are scaled in such a way that a year of healthy life always has the value of one. Years in less good health have a value less than one. So a year of healthy life always makes the same contribution to the aggregate measure, however good or bad that year is in respects other than health. This too may be defensible as an approximation. As a rough approximation, when we are working on a very large scale, it may be defensible to assume that all healthy people are equally well off. But it is defensible as an approximation only. If we could find ways to be more accurate, we should use them. However, many authors think it is a matter of principle that we should count each healthy year equally. It is not merely an acceptable approximation. They think there is actually a moral reason why the measurement of health should be scaled in this way. They believe fairness demands it. 4 In this respect, they think our measurement of health should be guided by the consideration of fairness. Christopher Murray explains this view using the example of two patients who are each in a coma caused by meningitis. 5 Only one can be treated, and the other will die. One is richer than the other. Suppose that, because she is richer, her wellbeing will be higher if she is saved. Then more good would be done by saving her. Should she be chosen for the treatment on that account? Murray thinks not. He evidently believes that would be unfair to the poorer patient. For this reason he thinks our measurement of the benefit of treatment should be blind to the person s wealth. This can be achieved by assigning the same value to a year of good 3

4 health, regardless of other aspects of a person s wellbeing. I agree with Murray that we ought not to give priority to the richer patient. But I do not agree that this should lead us to distort our measurement of goodness. The truth is that, if one patient will live a better life than the other, as we are assuming, then more good would be done by saving her than by saving the other. We should not hide this truth. Instead, we should learn something different from the example: doing the most good should not be our only criterion in making decisions of this sort. We also need to take account of fairness. In this case fairness requires us to be impartial between the patients, even though maximizing good would lead us to discriminate between them. Furthermore, fairness is a very important consideration, and in this case outweighs the extra benefit that would be achieved by saving the rich patient. We ought to choose in a non-discriminatory way, perhaps by holding a lottery. 6 Once we see that fairness is a distinct consideration from goodness, we will not need to try and incorporate considerations of fairness into our measure of goodness. In any case, Murray s attempt to incorporate fairness into goodness fails. Modify his example. Suppose neither of the coma patients is richer than the other, but one is disabled and the other is not. Say that one has lost an arm. Should the other be saved on that account? Murray appears to be ambivalent about a case of this sort, 7 but I do not think we need be ambivalent. If it is unfair to discriminate between patients on grounds of their wealth, it is certainly unfair to discriminate on grounds of this disability. It would plainly be unfair to let the disabled person die because she has already lost an arm. But we cannot make our measurement of health blind to disability, because disability is one of the main things we aim to measure. Our measure is bound to show that more good is done by saving the person who is not disabled. Yet this is unfair. So we have to recognize fairness as a separate consideration, which cannot be incorporated into our measure of goodness. I have been oversimplifying. I think fairness is itself a sort of good. The separation I am really making is between fairness on the one hand and other sorts of good on the other. But for convenience I shall continue to use the terms goodness and wellbeing to contrast with fairness. Strictly, these terms include all sorts of good apart from fairness. Why separate out fairness from other sorts of good? Because it works differently. Fairness is essentially a matter of how people fare in comparison with each other. Consequently, the arithmetic of fairness is different from the arithmetic of other goods; a simple example appears in my All goods are relevant in this volume. Fairness therefore needs separate accounting,. My diagram in section 1 shows people s wellbeing or good apart from fairness. Fairness does not appear in the diagram. 3. Aggregation and separability of people We have to aggregate temporal wellbeing across people and across time. How should we do it? Here is a simple possibility. First aggregate each person s wellbeing, to determine an aggregate value for each person. We may call this personal aggregate the person s lifetime wellbeing. Then aggregate together people s lifetime wellbeings to determine the overall value of the distribution. This simple route to aggregation takes the two dimensions separately. First we aggregate across time for each person. Then we aggregate across people. The two questions of how to aggregate across times and across people remain open. I shall come to them in due course: section 4 will discuss aggregation across people, and sections 7 and 8 aggregation across times in a person s life. This is a comparatively simple way to aggregate, but is it correct? At the first stage of aggregation, it requires us to assess each person s lifetime wellbeing on the basis of her 4

5 temporal wellbeing at all the times in her life. We can only do this if each person s life can be correctly evaluated independently of how things go for other people. The assumption that this is possible I call separability of people. Is it a correct assumption? At first, you might well think not. You might well think we should attach value to equality between people, and at first sight, this concern seems inconsistent with separability between people. If we are interested in equality, we are interested in how some people fare in comparison with other people. Are some much better off than others, or are most people at about the same level? If one person has a good life, say, we might assign her life more value if most other people are at about the same level than we would if she was much better off than most other people. In the latter case, her good life contributes to inequality in the society; in the former case it does not. This suggests we cannot value one person s life separately from other people s, so the assumption of separability is false. Various replies may be made to this objection to separability on grounds of equality. In my book Weighing Goods I gave one that I favour on theoretical grounds, 8 but here I shall give a more pragmatic one. I have already stated the basis of it in section 2. If equality is indeed valuable, that can only be because it is unfair. It is unfair that some people are worse off than others, if they do not deserve to be. But fairness must be accounted for separately from goodness; it should not be incorporated into our measure of goodness. 9 The assumption that people are separable is about the aggregation of goodness. Consequently, this matter of fairness cannot be an objection to it. If fairness is to be accounted for separately, we cannot determine how we should act simply on grounds of goodness. Suppose we are wondering where to concentrate our resources in promoting health. Suppose it turns out that more good will be done by concentrating them on the cities rather than the country; suppose the resources will promote people s wellbeing more effectively in the cities. This is not enough to determine that the cities are where they should be used. Separately, we also need to consider fairness. If city-dwellers are already well off compared with people in the country, it might turn out unfair to give the city-dwellers still more. If so, the extra benefit of using the resources in the cities will need to be weighed against the extra fairness of using them in the country. That deals with one possible doubt about separability of people. You might have a different doubt. We have to bear in mind that our decisions about health will affect the numbers of people who exist. A person exists in one half of my diagram who does not exist in the other half. In comparing the values of the two halves, we cannot ignore this difference. This means, in effect, that we shall have to attach a value (positive or negative) to the person s existence. I know that many people find it intuitively difficult to accept the idea that existence has value, and I shall say more about it in section 5. Here I shall only point out a consequence of assuming separability of people. It implies, not only that we can evaluate a person s life independently of how things go for other people, but also that the value of a person s existence is independent of how many other people exist and of how things go for them. This conflicts with an assumption that people very commonly make when they think about population. They think that we should aim for the greatest wellbeing, on average, for the people who live. For example, when China chose to limit the number of Chinese, I presume its motive was to try and achieve the greatest average wellbeing for the Chinese people. It assumed that increasing population tends to decrease average wellbeing, and for this reason it decided to control the increase in population. If your objective is the average wellbeing of the people, you will be in favour of adding a person to the population if her existence will increase the average. This will be so if her 5

6 wellbeing will be above the average of the people who already exist, and if her existence will not harm other people. You will be against adding a person if her wellbeing will be below the average, and if her existence will not benefit other people. So the value of adding a person depends on how her wellbeing will compare with the wellbeing of the people who already exist. This conflicts with separability of people, which requires the value of her existence to be independent of the wellbeing of other people. As it happens, I think separability wins this particular conflict. The average principle is mistaken, precisely because it conflicts with separability. But I shall not try to justify this claim in this paper. 10 In this paper, I cannot go deeply into the value of population. I needed to mention the second doubt about separability, but having mentioned it I shall pass on. 4. Addition across people Separability of people permits the two-stage route to aggregation I mentioned: first aggregating temporal wellbeing across times to determine each person s lifetime wellbeing, and then aggregating lifetime wellbeings across people. But separability does much more than this. It also allows us to derive remarkable conclusions about how the second step of aggregation is to be done. Consequently, I shall discuss this second step first, and come to the first step afterwards. Separability of people turns out to be a remarkably powerful assumption. If it can be justified, a very strong conclusion can be drawn from it by mathematical means. It implies that aggregation across people must take an additively separable form. This means that a distribution s value takes the form: (1) f 1 (g 1 ) + f 2 (g 2 ) f P (g P ). In this formula, g 1, g 2 and so on stand for the lifetime wellbeings of each person. The functions f 1 (&), f 2 (&) and so on are transformations that are applied to the wellbeings before they are added up. The addition runs over all the people who exist. Missing people, like the one missing on the right of the diagram, are ignored. The spectacular conclusion expressed in (1) more precisely its derivation from separability of people stems originally from a mathematical theorem first established by John Harsanyi, 11 and subsequently developed and interpreted by many other authors. 12 There is a lot of background to it that I have not mentioned and do not propose to mention. It makes several other assumptions besides separability of people, and several of them are controversial. I do not pretend that (1) is established truth. However, with some qualifications, I believe it can be soundly defended. I shall take it for granted in this paper. The presence of the transformations f 1 (&), f 2 (&) and so on allows the formula (1) to accommodate so-called priority view. This is the view that we should be more concerned about the wellbeing of less well-off people than about the wellbeing of better-off people. 13 We should attach more value to increasing the wellbeing of the less well off; we should give priority to the worse off. If the transformation functions in (1) are all the same, so f 1 (&) = f 2 (&) =.... = f P (&), and if they are strictly concave, they will have the effect of giving priority to the worse off. This is how the priority view can be accommodated. The priority view does not value equality directly, but it gives a derivative value to equality. For any given total of wellbeing, it prefers this wellbeing to be more equally distributed rather than less equally. That is one of its attractions. I think the priority view is mistaken. The argument that leads me to this conclusion is long and arduous, and I do not need to rehearse it here. 14 Only the result matters here. But for anyone who is interested, here is a brief sketch. For the priority view even to make sense, we 6

7 must have an arithmetic (more precisely, cardinal) scale of people s lifetime wellbeing, which is defined before we come to aggregating wellbeing across people. Wellbeing measured on this independent scale is transformed by the transformations f 1 (&), f 2 (&) and so on. But I do not believe we have a clearly defined arithmetical scale. I believe our quantitative notion of wellbeing is actually formed by the process of aggregating across people. Implicitly, we define the scale of wellbeing for ourselves in such a way that we can aggregate wellbeing simply by adding, without transformation: (2) g 1 + g g P. Part of the attraction of the priority view is the indirect value it assigns to equality. But it is not the only way of assigning value to equality. I explained in section 3 that the value of equality is best understood as the value of fairness, and I explained that I am not treating fairness as a part of goodness in this paper. It needs to be accounted for separately. So if we adopt (2) as our account of goodness, we need not repudiate a concern for fairness and equality. 5. Population Formula (2) is more or less correct, but not quite. It is slightly oversimplified; it is correct only if we are evaluating distributions that all contain the same number of people. For most of this paper I shall ignore changes in population, so (2) will be adequate. But the diagram in section 1 shows that when we concern ourselves with health, we really ought to allow for different numbers of people. In that case, the correct formula is: (3) (g 1 ) + (g 2 ) (g P ). Here, stands for a particular level of lifetime wellbeing that I call the neutral level. Imagine a person is added to the population, and her wellbeing is. Then (3) tells us that adding her is neither good nor bad; the distribution that contains this extra person is equally as good as the distribution that does not. In this sense, adding this person is ethically neutral; hence the name the neutral level. (3) says that to evaluate a distribution of wellbeing, we first calculate how much each person s lifetime wellbeing exceeds the neutral level. (This will be a negative amount if it falls below the neutral level.) Then we add these amounts across people. Once again, I shall not argue for (3), but simply mention sources. This formula was first defended by Charles Blackorby and David Donaldson, 15 and there is a further defence in my Weighing Lives. Although it can be derived by reasonably secure arguments, formula (3) is very contentious. It is much more contentious even than the simple additive formula (2), used to compare distributions that have the same population. (3) implies there is only a single neutral level of wellbeing. It implies it is a good thing to add a person to the population if her wellbeing is above, and a bad thing to add a person if her wellbeing is below. Only if her wellbeing is exactly is her addition ethically neutral. This is strongly in conflict with many people s intuitions. Many people believe that adding a person to the world is generally neutral. That is to say, increasing the world s population is not in itself either good or bad. Adding a person no doubt has effects on other people. For example, the existence of a new person may be harmful because of the demands the person makes on the earth s resources. But apart from such external effects, the addition of a person is neutral in itself. Call this the intuition of neutrality. It says there is not just one neutral level, as (3) implies, but that most levels of wellbeing are neutral. (I say most because adding a person whose life will be bad is intuitively not neutral, but bad.) The intuition of neutrality must be wrong. Consider three options. Option A is to add a 7

8 person whose lifetime wellbeing would be high. Option B is not to add this person at all. Option C is to add her (the same person), but in such a way that her wellbeing would be less than it is in A. Everyone apart from the added person is equally as well off in A as she is in B and in C. According to the intuition, A is equally as good as B. The difference between A and B is simply that the person is added in A, and that is neutral. Similarly B is equally as good as C, according to the intuition of neutrality. Equally as good as is a transitive relation, so it follows that A is equally as good as C. But this is false. A and C have the same population; the difference between them is only that our added person is better off in A than she is in C. Everyone else if equally well off in A and C. So A must be better than C. Given that the intuition of neutrality is false, we have to face up to the question of the value of adding people to the population. This is particularly inevitable when it comes to measuring health. One of the greatest effects of disease is that it restricts the world s population. One of the greatest effects of reducing disease is that it expands the world s population. The amazing explosion of population that has occurred in the last two centuries is primarily due to improvements in public health, and this population explosion is perhaps the most important thing that has ever happened to humanity. It cannot be ignored. Up to now, I suspect it has been ignored in measures of health because of the presumption that it has no value in itself. This is the intuition of neutrality, and it is not sustainable. On a small scale, the diagram in section 1shows how odd it would be to ignore the addition of a person to the population. The epidemic illustrated in the diagram kills one person, and we count the years of life that person loses as a harm done by the epidemic. It causes one person, not yet born, to live a disabled rather than a healthy life, and we count the disability as a harm caused by the epidemic. It causes one person, not yet born, never to be born at all. Suppose we were to count that as neutral, as the intuition of neutrality suggests. In comparison to our treatment of the other two cases, that would be odd. In this paper I shall not try to pursue the question of how to value population. Nor shall I insist very firmly that (3) is the right formula. I chiefly want to emphasize that the problem of valuing population cannot be ignored. Having said that, I shall from here on ignore it. 6. Is life incommensurable? Separability of people has brought us to a simple formula for aggregating people s lifetime wellbeings. For the most part, we simply add up. That solves one part of the aggregation problem; we know how to aggregate across people. Our other problem is to aggregate across time in each person s life, to determine her lifetime wellbeing as an aggregate of her temporal wellbeing. Before coming to the details of aggregation across time, I should take up a preliminary topic. In setting up the problem of aggregation, I have taken it for granted that a person s lifetime wellbeing depends both on the length of her life and on her temporal wellbeing while she is alive. Both factors contribute to her lifetime wellbeing, and that makes them implicitly comparable in value. As a general rule, I assume that a decline in temporal wellbeing at some time could be made up for by an increased length of life. This assumption is certainly implicit in any summary measure of health: a summary measure is a single measure that is supposed to incorporate both the length of people s lives and the quality of their lives. Yet some people think there is something wrong with this assumption. They think of life as a special sort of good, which cannot properly be put on the same scale as the mundane goods that make up the quality of life. One version of this view gives absolute priority to prolonging life over other sorts of good; 8

9 any extension of life is worth any sacrifice to achieve. A more moderate version is that prolonging life is incommensurable with other sorts of good; they cannot be measured on the same scale. If this is so, it means we cannot put length of life and quality of life together in a single measure of health. Either version threatens summary measures. So I need to say something about this view. First, it is very plausible that the value of living is nothing more than the value of receiving other sorts of good. The only benefit of staying alive is to gain the opportunity of enjoying all the ordinary goods that life brings. If this is right, there can be no problem about weighing the value of life against ordinary goods. The value of life is just the same thing as those ordinary goods. True, there may be problems of incommensurability amongst the ordinary goods themselves. Perhaps the value of love cannot be precisely weighed against the value of good health, for example. But I have already ignored that problem when I assumed there is such a thing as a unified notion of temporal wellbeing. Implicitly, I set aside any problems there might be about weighing one sort of ordinary good against another. I am not suggesting that love and health can be precisely weighed against each other, but implicitly I assumed they can be roughly weighed well enough to let us make sense of a scale of temporal wellbeing. My present suggestion is that there is no further problem about weighing life against these goods. That may not be a sufficient answer to the idea that life is incommensurable with other goods, because some people believe life has a value of its own, quite apart from the good things it contains. That may be so. But even if it is so, it does not follow that its value cannot be weighed against other goods. No doubt we cannot expect to weigh it precisely, but it might be weighed against health, say, as much as love can be weighed against health. Some evidence that life can be weighed against other goods is that in our own lives we regularly do this sort of weighing, and feel it right to do so. We sometimes pursue other goods even at the risk of shortening our lives. For example, mothers sometimes sacrifice their health, and so shorten their lives, in the course of bringing up their children. We do weigh life against other goods, and it does not seem absurd to do so. It seems no more absurd than, say, weighing honour against money. So I think the onus of proof is on those who doubt that life can be weighed against other goods. We need at least a special argument why this sort of weighing, in particular, should be impossible. 7. Additivity across times: the default Now to temporal aggregation itself. It is much less clear cut than aggregation across people. I believe there are solid arguments for the interpersonal additive formula (3). But for aggregation across time, I can offer nothing more than a default theory. I do not insist it is correct. I see it more as a convenient basis for organizing the discussion. Still, it is simple and attractive, and I do not think we should depart from it without a good reason. I shall mention some putative reasons that have been offered for doing so, but I find none of them very convincing. They are mostly mere intuitions, without the backing of argument. I would rather stick with the default. As it happens, there are some formal arguments that could be used in support of this default. Aggregating wellbeing across time is roughly analogous to aggregating wellbeing across people. Consequently, the default theory may be defended by formal arguments that are roughly analogous to the arguments for (2). However, these arguments depend on an assumption that I have no faith in: separability of times in a life. I have no need to spell out 9

10 exactly what this amounts to, but it is analogous to separability of people. Whereas I think separability of people is correct, I have no faith in separability of times. Consequently, I do not put my trust in the formal arguments for the default theory. 16 The default theory is simply that a person s lifetime wellbeing is the total of the temporal wellbeing in her life: (4) g p = g p 1 + g p g pt. This is a formula for the wellbeing of a person who is identified by the index p. g p is this person s lifetime wellbeing, and g p1, g p 2 and so on are her temporal wellbeings at the times she is alive. For convenience in writing this formula, I have divided time into discrete periods. This additive formula only makes sense once we have an arithmetic (strictly, cardinal) scale for temporal wellbeing. As I said in section 1, in this paper I shall not try to deal with the construction of this scale. But I need to say something about the zero. If we were comparing only lives of equal length using (4), the zero would make no difference; a cardinal scale of temporal wellbeing would be enough. However, for lives of different length, the zero matters. The formula shows us how we must interpret the zero of temporal wellbeing. Suppose a person s life is made longer by one period, and her wellbeing in that period is zero. Then according to the formula, her lifetime wellbeing is unaffected. Extending a person s life at level zero is equally as good for the person as not extending it. This means we must interpret the zero of wellbeing as the level of wellbeing such that living a period of life at that level is equally as good as not living it. I call this the neutral level of temporal wellbeing (to distinguish it from the neutral level of lifetime wellbeing I mentioned in section 5). We might say it is the level that lies on the borderline between periods of life that are worth living and periods that are not worth living. If this neutral level is to serve as our zero of wellbeing, it must be a constant. It must not depend on how the rest of the person s life has gone. It constancy is questionable. Some intuitions are against it. For example, we might think a life that has been lived at a high level would be spoiled by having a merely mediocre period at the end. At the end of this high-level life, then, the neutral level of wellbeing would be high. On the other hand, if a life has been generally mediocre, an extra period that is slightly less mediocre might improve the life as a whole. If so, the neutral level of wellbeing at the end of a mediocre life is low. So the neutral level will depend on how the rest of the life has gone. If the neutral level is not constant, the default theory shown in (4) is not correct. I have no strong reason for rejecting the intuition I described in the previous paragraph. Nor do I have a strong reason for accepting it. So I shall stick to the default in this respect. 8. Other patterns of aggregation across time Let us continue to review the reasons we might have for doubting the default theory. One is the thought that perhaps we should give some priority to worse times in a life. This would be analogous to giving priority to the worse-off people, when aggregating across people. It could be achieved by applying a strictly concave transformation f(&) to temporal wellbeing before adding up. It would give us the formula g p = f(g p1 ) + f(g p2 ) f(g pt ). However, I see no particular reason why we should give priority to worse times. There is a case for giving priority to the worse off, but this case depends on the separateness of persons, to use Rawls s phrase. The better-off are separate people from the worse-off. Consequently, 10

11 the higher wellbeing of the better-off does not compensate the worse-off for their lower wellbeing. That is a precondition for the idea that we should give priority to the worse-off people. But the good times in a life can indeed compensate for the bad times: they compensate the single person whose life it is. So the corresponding precondition for giving priority to the worse times is not satisfied. A second thought that conflicts with the simple formula (4) is that inclines may be better than declines. 17 Take two lives that have the same total of temporal wellbeing, and suppose they last for the same length of time. But suppose one goes uphill it gets progressively better and ends well whereas the other goes downhill. It is plausible that the former is a better life than the latter. Yet the default theory implies the two lives are equally good. The view that inclines are better than declines might be formalized in various ways. The simplest way is to say that later periods of life count for more in lifetime wellbeing than earlier periods. This means modifying formula (4) by adding weighting factors to different periods in life: g p = a 1 g p 1 + a 2 g p a T g pt, where a 1, a 2 and so on are weights. Later periods have bigger weights. This formulation can join forces with the slightly different thought that the end of a person s life is particularly important in determining how good the life is. Suppose we are evaluating a person s life once it has ended. I think we are inclined to put much more weight on the closing years than on the person s childhood. An unhappy childhood is unfortunate, but for someone who has lived a long time it may count for very little. But an unhappy old age will always be significant. Again, this suggests that later years should have greater weight. The idea that later times in life count for more than earlier times is intuitively attractive. However, measures of health in practice are much more often influenced by the opposite view, that wellbeing in later years should be discounted compared with earlier years. Later times are often discounted in two ways. First, the temporal wellbeing that comes in the later years of a person s life is counted for less than the temporal wellbeing that comes in earlier years. Second, the lifetime wellbeing of people who are born later is counted for less than the lifetime wellbeing of people who are born earlier. Why should we discount later wellbeing? There are various sources for the idea of discounting, and I cannot possibly examine them all in the detail they require. I can only mention some and assess them very briefly. One is the supposition that people typically discount their own later wellbeing in their decision-making. Let us grant this as a fact, and ask whether it licenses us to apply discounting in forming measures of health or other measures of wellbeing. When a person makes a decision, she does so at a particular time, and makes it from the perspective of that time, looking forward at the future. From the perspective of that time, later future times are more distant than earlier future times. It may well be a feature of our person s psychology that she counts later times for less because they are more distant. Distant objects look smaller, even though in fact they are not. Later times will not always be more distant. When the person looks back over the same period, the later times will be closer than the earlier times. Will she still count them for less? I do not think so. When we evaluate past stretches of our life, I do not think we give extra weight to times in the more distant past. The later times are nearer, and for that reason, I think we tend to count them for more. Decision-making is special in that it is inevitably forward-looking. This is because we can 11

12 only affect the future. Decision-making takes the perspective of a particular time, and looks forward from then. Later times are therefore more distant than earlier ones. This explains psychologically why later times may seem less important in our decision-making. When we draw up measures of health should we similarly take the perspective of a particular time? We should not. We should look at the world impartially, and give each time its proper weight. It is surely incorrect to count a period for less just because, at the moment, it happens to be more distant. That is a distortion. A second source of discounting is that some sorts of good are genuinely less valuable in later years than in earlier years. Money is an example. $1 in December 2001 is less valuable than $1 in December This is because $1 in December 2000 can actually be exchanged for more than $1 in 2001, by leaving it in a bank at interest. Most economic commodities are like that. You can exchange beer in December 2000 for more beer in December 2001 by selling it now, banking the proceeds at interest, and using the money plus accrued interest to buy beer in December Provided the price of beer has not gone up by more than the rate of interest, you will end up with more beer. The ultimate explanation of why this is possible is that we have a productive economy. The economy is able to turn economic commodities used as inputs into a greater quantity of economic commodities as outputs at a later date. It is therefore correct practice in economics and accounting to value later commodities less than earlier ones. More precisely, this is correct for produced commodities. But for scarce resources, which are not produced, it is not normally correct, and normally these goods ought not to be discounted. Like scarce resources, people s wellbeing does not participate directly in the economy s productive process. True, we can exchange wellbeing at one time for wellbeing at a later time. Suppose you save some of your present wealth instead of spending it. Suppose you invest it, and use the proceeds for spending in the future. You sacrifice some of the wellbeing you might have derived from your wealth in the present, and instead gain some wellbeing in the future. This is exchanging present wellbeing for future wellbeing. But there is no guarantee you will get more wellbeing in the future than you sacrifice in the present. With most economic commodities, there is a good reason why you will normally end up with more of them if you choose to exchange present ones for future ones. This is because they directly participate in the productive process. But wellbeing does not directly participate, and there is no reason why you should end up with more of it. I state all this boldly. It takes some detailed economic analysis to support it, 18 and I would be misleading you if I did not admit that the economic analysis leads to some debate. Still, the outcome is as I say. There is good reason for discounting most economic commodities. This has created a habit of discounting. But the reasons for discounting commodities cannot legitimately be transferred to wellbeing. I conclude that the grounds for discounting temporal wellbeing are weak. If we discounted, we would attach greater weight to earlier years than to later ones. I see no reason for departing from the default in that direction. On the other hand, I mentioned some intuitions that attach greater weight to later years than earlier ones. These are attractive, but they are merely intuitions, and I think they are not enough reason for departing from the default in that direction either. In the calculation of DALYs, a different pattern of weights has been used. 19 More weight is given to the middle periods of life, and less to early and late periods. However, the reason given by Christopher Murray for this system of weights is not that he thinks wellbeing in the middle period of life is actually more valuable than wellbeing at other periods. The reason is 12

13 to do with the benefits that people bestow on each other. People in the middle years of life support the young and the old economically, and they give benefits to the young and the old in other ways too. For that reason they are more valuable. In economists terms, this value is an externality. In a diagram like mine in section 1, showing a distribution of benefit, the benefit that one person, p, gives to another, q, will show up within q s life. It will automatically be incorporated in the value we assign to the distribution when we aggregate wellbeing across it. There is no need to allow for it by a further system of weights like Murray s. Murray accounts for externalities differently, by attaching weights to the quality of p s life. He is forced to this expedient because he restricts his attention to states of people s health. The external benefits that p bestows on q will not normally take the form of improvements in q s health. So they will not normally appear directly in any measure that is based on states of health only. Murray s weights are the only way he has of taking them into account, given the restricted nature of his measure. But as I said in section 2, our measure of the harm done by disease ought not to be based on states of health only. The harm done takes many forms, and ill-health is only one of them. This is an example. If a disease kills people in the middle years of life, one harmful consequence is that the old and young are deprived of support and other benefits that they would otherwise have received. This is a harm caused by disease that is not a change in their state of health. Consequently, it can only be incorporated in Murray s measure by distorting the aggregation of states of health. That is the effect of his weights. The correct way to take the harm into account is to use a measure that is based more generally on wellbeing. In sum, it gives no reason to depart from the default theory of aggregation. 9. Conclusions I believe that existing measures of the burden of disease are all additive, except that they sometimes discount later wellbeing and sometimes apply age-weighting. I have supported additivity. Additivity across people can be supported by fairly solid argument. Additivity across time has less argument behind it, but it is a reasonable default position. I have argued that there is no good reason to apply different weights to wellbeing that comes at different dates. For instance, there is no good reason to discount, or to apply age-related weights. I have argued that measures of the burden of disease should be based on people s wellbeing rather than on the state of their health only. This is because the bad effects of disease are multifarious, and not confined to health. Measures of the burden of disease usually ignore the effect of disease on the world s population. I have argued that this is a very large effect, and it cannot be assumed to be neutral in value. It therefore must not be ignored. References Atkinson, Anthony B., and Joseph E. Stiglitz, Lectures on Public Economics, McGraw-Hill, Blackorby, Charles, and David Donaldson, Social criteria for evaluating population change, Journal of Public Economics, 25 (1984), pp Broome, John, All goods are relevant, this volume. Broome, John, Can there be a summary measure of health, this volume. Broome, John, Discounting the future, Philosophy and Public Affairs, 23 (1994), pp , reprinted in my Ethics Out of Economics, pp

14 Broome, John, Fairness, goodness and levelling down, this volume. Broome, John, Weighing Goods, Blackwell, Broome, John, Weighing Lives, Oxford University Press, forthcoming. Culyer, A. J., Commodities, characteristics of commodities, characteristics of people, utilities, and the quality of life, in Quality of Life, edited by Sally Baldwin, Christine Godfrey and Carol Propper, Routledge, 1990, pp Harsanyi, John C., Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility, Journal of Political Economy, 63 (1955), pp , reprinted in his Essays on Ethics, Social Behavior, and Scientific Explanation, Reidel, 1976, pp Murray, Christopher J. L., Rethinking DALYs, in The Global Burden of Disease, edited by Christopher J. L. Murray and Alan D. Lopez, Harvard University Press, Parfit, Derek, Equality or priority?, in The Ideal of Equality, edited by Matthew Clayton and Andrew Williams, Macmillan, 2000, pp Velleman, David, Well-being and time, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 72 (1991), pp Notes 1. My way of handling them is described in my Weighing Lives, Chapters 3 and Can there be a summary measure of health? 3. See the account in Christopher Murray s Rethinking DALYs, pp Examples are Christopher Murray, Rethinking DALYs, p. 7, and A. J. Culyer, Commodities, characteristics of commodities, characteristics of people, utilities, and the quality of life. 5. Rethinking DALYs, p See my All goods are relevant in this volume. 7. Rethinking DALYs, pp Weighing Goods, chapter My Fairness, goodness and levelling down answers a common objection to treating the value of equality this way. 10. The argument is in my Weighing Lives, chapter Cardinal welfare, individualistic ethics, and interpersonal comparisons of utility. 12. There is an interpretation, with references to other authors, in my Weighing Goods, chapter I believe the name comes from Derek Parfit s Equality or priority?, but the idea was well established in economics long before then. For instance, see the textbook Lectures on Public Economics, by Atkinson and Stiglitz, p See my Weighing Goods, chapters 9 and Social Criteria for Evaluating Population Change. 16. Details of these arguments are in my Weighing Lives, chapter For example, see David Velleman s Well-being and time. 18. The argument is in my Discounting the future?. There is also an excellent analysis in Christopher Murray s Rethinking DALYs, pp , which I agree with to a large extent. 19. See Christopher Murray, Rethinking DALYs, pp

THE BADNESS OF DEATH AND THE GOODNESS OF LIFE

THE BADNESS OF DEATH AND THE GOODNESS OF LIFE C h a p t e r 9 THE BADNESS OF DEATH AND THE GOODNESS OF LIFE joh n bro om e What harm does death do you? To put the question differently: when you die, what do you lose by dying? To put it differently

More information

Why economics needs ethical theory

Why economics needs ethical theory Why economics needs ethical theory by John Broome, University of Oxford In Arguments for a Better World: Essays in Honour of Amartya Sen. Volume 1 edited by Kaushik Basu and Ravi Kanbur, Oxford University

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

Can We Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion?

Can We Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion? THEORIA, 2016, 82, 110 127 doi:10.1111/theo.12097 Can We Avoid the Repugnant Conclusion? by DEREK PARFIT University of Oxford Abstract: According to the Repugnant Conclusion: Compared with the existence

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

THE WELFARE ECONOMICS OF POPULATION

THE WELFARE ECONOMICS OF POPULATION Oxford Economic Papers 48 (1996), 177-193 THE WELFARE ECONOMICS OF POPULATION By JOHN BROOME Department of Moral Philosophy, University of St Andrews, Fife KY16 9AL Intuition suggests there is no value

More information

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction

UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY. Peter Vallentyne. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): I. Introduction UTILITARIANISM AND INFINITE UTILITY Peter Vallentyne Australasian Journal of Philosophy 71 (1993): 212-7. I. Introduction Traditional act utilitarianism judges an action permissible just in case it produces

More information

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984) The Non-Identity Problem from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984) Each of us might never have existed. What would have made this true? The answer produces a problem that most of us overlook. One

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 The Two Possible Choice Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online

Oxford Scholarship Online University Press Scholarship Online Oxford Scholarship Online The Quality of Life Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen Print publication date: 1993 Print ISBN-13: 9780198287971 Published to Oxford Scholarship

More information

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being ) On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio I: The CAPE International Conferenc being ) Author(s) Sasaki, Taku Citation CAPE Studies in Applied Philosophy 2: 141-151 Issue

More information

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome

DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS. John Broome DEONTOLOGY AND ECONOMICS John Broome I am very grateful to Shelly Kagan for extremely penetrating comments. Abstract. In The Moral Dimension, Amitai Etzioni claims that people often act for moral motives,

More information

Scanlon on Double Effect

Scanlon on Double Effect Scanlon on Double Effect RALPH WEDGWOOD Merton College, University of Oxford In this new book Moral Dimensions, T. M. Scanlon (2008) explores the ethical significance of the intentions and motives with

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE

IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE IN DEFENCE OF CLOSURE By RICHARD FELDMAN Closure principles for epistemic justification hold that one is justified in believing the logical consequences, perhaps of a specified sort,

More information

The Discount Rate of Well-Being

The Discount Rate of Well-Being The Discount Rate of Well-Being 1. The Discount Rate of Future Well-Being: Acting to mitigate climate change clearly means making sacrifices NOW in order to make people in the FUTURE better off. But, how

More information

6. The most important thing about climate change

6. The most important thing about climate change 6. The most important thing about climate change John Broome Ethics and climate change The title of this volume Public Policy: Why ethics matters is highly significant. Among the protagonists in the debate

More information

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships

No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships No Love for Singer: The Inability of Preference Utilitarianism to Justify Partial Relationships In his book Practical Ethics, Peter Singer advocates preference utilitarianism, which holds that the right

More information

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles

Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles DEREK PARFIT Future People, the Non- Identity Problem, and Person-Affecting Principles I. FUTURE PEOPLE Suppose we discover how we could live for a thousand years, but in a way that made us unable to have

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Introduction Symbolic Logic

Introduction Symbolic Logic An Introduction to Symbolic Logic Copyright 2006 by Terence Parsons all rights reserved CONTENTS Chapter One Sentential Logic with 'if' and 'not' 1 SYMBOLIC NOTATION 2 MEANINGS OF THE SYMBOLIC NOTATION

More information

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University

Well-Being, Disability, and the Mere-Difference Thesis. Jennifer Hawkins Duke University This paper is in the very early stages of development. Large chunks are still simply detailed outlines. I can, of course, fill these in verbally during the session, but I apologize in advance for its current

More information

Action in Special Contexts

Action in Special Contexts Part III Action in Special Contexts c36.indd 283 c36.indd 284 36 Rationality john broome Rationality as a Property and Rationality as a Source of Requirements The word rationality often refers to a property

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 By Bernard Gert (1934-2011) [Page 15] Analogy between Morality and Grammar Common morality is complex, but it is less complex than the grammar of a language. Just

More information

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples

2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3. Failed proofs and counterexamples 2.3.0. Overview Derivations can also be used to tell when a claim of entailment does not follow from the principles for conjunction. 2.3.1. When enough is enough

More information

Can there be a preference-based utilitarianism? * John Broome Department of Moral Philosophy, University of St Andrews

Can there be a preference-based utilitarianism? * John Broome Department of Moral Philosophy, University of St Andrews Can there be a preference-based utilitarianism? * John Broome Department of Moral Philosophy, University of St Andrews For Justice, Political Liberalism and Utilitarianism: Proceedings of the Caen Conference

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January 15 2008 1. A definition A theory of some normative domain is contractualist if, having said what it is for a person to accept a principle in that domain,

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York promoting access to White Rose research papers Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ This is an author produced version of a paper published in Ethical Theory and Moral

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World

Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Equality, Fairness, and Responsibility in an Unequal World Thom Brooks Abstract: Severe poverty is a major global problem about risk and inequality. What, if any, is the relationship between equality,

More information

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3

6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3 6.041SC Probabilistic Systems Analysis and Applied Probability, Fall 2013 Transcript Lecture 3 The following content is provided under a Creative Commons license. Your support will help MIT OpenCourseWare

More information

Florida State University Libraries

Florida State University Libraries Florida State University Libraries Undergraduate Research Honors Ethical Issues and Life Choices (PHI2630) 2013 How We Should Make Moral Career Choices Rebecca Hallock Follow this and additional works

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions:

Suicide. 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing between two questions: Suicide Because we are mortal, and furthermore have some CONTROL over when our deaths occur, we should ask: When is it acceptable to end one s own life? 1. Rationality vs. Morality: Kagan begins by distinguishing

More information

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 1 MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 Some people hold that utilitarianism is incompatible with justice and objectionable for that reason. Utilitarianism

More information

Unfit for the Future

Unfit for the Future Book Review Unfit for the Future by Persson & Savulescu, New York: Oxford University Press, 2012 Laura Crompton laura.crompton@campus.lmu.de In the book Unfit for the Future Persson and Savulescu portray

More information

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

What is the Social in Social Coherence? Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age Journal of Civil Rights and Economic Development Volume 31 Issue 1 Volume 31, Summer 2018, Issue 1 Article 5 June 2018 What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

Again, the reproductive context has received a lot more attention than the context of the environment and climate change to which I now turn.

Again, the reproductive context has received a lot more attention than the context of the environment and climate change to which I now turn. The ethical issues concerning climate change are very often framed in terms of harm: so people say that our acts (and omissions) affect the environment in ways that will cause severe harm to future generations,

More information

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications

2.1 Review. 2.2 Inference and justifications Applied Logic Lecture 2: Evidence Semantics for Intuitionistic Propositional Logic Formal logic and evidence CS 4860 Fall 2012 Tuesday, August 28, 2012 2.1 Review The purpose of logic is to make reasoning

More information

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI

THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI Page 1 To appear in Erkenntnis THE ROLE OF COHERENCE OF EVIDENCE IN THE NON- DYNAMIC MODEL OF CONFIRMATION TOMOJI SHOGENJI ABSTRACT This paper examines the role of coherence of evidence in what I call

More information

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem Ralph Wedgwood I wish it need not have happened in my time, said Frodo. So do I, said Gandalf, and so do all who live to see such times. But that is not for them

More information

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008)

Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Writing Module Three: Five Essential Parts of Argument Cain Project (2008) Module by: The Cain Project in Engineering and Professional Communication. E-mail the author Summary: This module presents techniques

More information

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good)

How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good) How should I live? I should do whatever brings about the most pleasure (or, at least, the most good) Suppose that some actions are right, and some are wrong. What s the difference between them? What makes

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01: Classics of Western Philosophy Mill s Utilitarianism I. Introduction Recall that there are four questions one might ask an ethical theory to answer: a) Which acts are right and which are wrong? Which acts ought we to perform (understanding

More information

Reason fundamentalism and what is wrong with it John Broome For the Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Daniel Star

Reason fundamentalism and what is wrong with it John Broome For the Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Daniel Star Reason fundamentalism and what is wrong with it John Broome For the Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity, edited by Daniel Star 1. Introduction During the last half-century, a dogma has grown up

More information

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics,

In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics, NOTE A NOTE ON PREFERENCE AND INDIFFERENCE IN ECONOMIC ANALYSIS HANS-HERMANN HOPPE In his celebrated article Toward a Reconstruction of Utility and Welfare Economics, Murray Rothbard wrote that [i]ndifference

More information

interaction among the conference participants leaves one wondering why this journal issue was put out as a book.

interaction among the conference participants leaves one wondering why this journal issue was put out as a book. 128 REVIEWS interaction among the conference participants leaves one wondering why this journal issue was put out as a book. Joseph C. Pitt Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University Beyond Optimizing,

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind criticalthinking.org http://www.criticalthinking.org/pages/the-critical-mind-is-a-questioning-mind/481 The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind Learning How to Ask Powerful, Probing Questions Introduction

More information

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism

R. M. Hare (1919 ) SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG. Definition of moral judgments. Prescriptivism 25 R. M. Hare (1919 ) WALTER SINNOTT- ARMSTRONG Richard Mervyn Hare has written on a wide variety of topics, from Plato to the philosophy of language, religion, and education, as well as on applied ethics,

More information

I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth.

I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth. I thought I should expand this population approach somewhat: P t = P0e is the equation which describes population growth. To head off the most common objections:! This does take into account the death

More information

Writing Essays at Oxford

Writing Essays at Oxford Writing Essays at Oxford Introduction One of the best things you can take from an Oxford degree in philosophy/politics is the ability to write an essay in analytical philosophy, Oxford style. Not, obviously,

More information

the negative reason existential fallacy

the negative reason existential fallacy Mark Schroeder University of Southern California May 21, 2007 the negative reason existential fallacy 1 There is a very common form of argument in moral philosophy nowadays, and it goes like this: P1 It

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

Equality and Value-holism

Equality and Value-holism By/Par Paul Bou-Habib _ Department of Government University of Essex RÉSUMÉ Dans cet article je considère un récent défi à l égalitarisme développé par Michael Huemer. Le challenge de Huemer prend la forme

More information

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS

PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS DISCUSSION NOTE PLEASESURE, DESIRE AND OPPOSITENESS BY JUSTIN KLOCKSIEM JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2010 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JUSTIN KLOCKSIEM 2010 Pleasure, Desire

More information

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment

Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 7 Compatibilist Objections to Prepunishment Winner of the Outstanding Graduate Paper Award at the 55 th Annual Meeting of the Florida Philosophical

More information

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN

Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN Equality of Capacity AMARTYA SEN WHY EQUALITY? WHAT EQUALITY? Two central issues for ethical analysis of equality are: (1) Why equality? (2) Equality of what? The two questions are distinct but thoroughly

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality

Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality Peter Singer, Famine, Affluence, and Morality As I write this, in November 1971, people are dying in East Bengal from lack of food, shelter, and medical care. The suffering and death that are occurring

More information

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University. Ethics Bites What s Wrong With Killing? David Edmonds This is Ethics Bites, with me David Edmonds. Warburton And me Warburton. David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

Trinity & contradiction

Trinity & contradiction Trinity & contradiction Today we ll discuss one of the most distinctive, and philosophically most problematic, Christian doctrines: the doctrine of the Trinity. It is tempting to see the doctrine of the

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism

SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism SIMON BOSTOCK Internal Properties and Property Realism R ealism about properties, standardly, is contrasted with nominalism. According to nominalism, only particulars exist. According to realism, both

More information

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule

Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule UTILITARIAN ETHICS Evaluating actions The principle of utility Strengths Criticisms Act vs. rule A dilemma You are a lawyer. You have a client who is an old lady who owns a big house. She tells you that

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies

Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies Philosophia (2017) 45:987 993 DOI 10.1007/s11406-017-9833-0 Epistemic Consequentialism, Truth Fairies and Worse Fairies James Andow 1 Received: 7 October 2015 / Accepted: 27 March 2017 / Published online:

More information

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance

In Defense of Culpable Ignorance It is common in everyday situations and interactions to hold people responsible for things they didn t know but which they ought to have known. For example, if a friend were to jump off the roof of a house

More information

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social

Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social Rawls s veil of ignorance excludes all knowledge of likelihoods regarding the social position one ends up occupying, while John Harsanyi s version of the veil tells contractors that they are equally likely

More information

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions Chapter 15 Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions Debate is a process in which individuals exchange arguments about controversial topics. Debate could not exist without arguments. Arguments are the

More information

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information

1 Introduction. Cambridge University Press Epistemic Game Theory: Reasoning and Choice Andrés Perea Excerpt More information 1 Introduction One thing I learned from Pop was to try to think as people around you think. And on that basis, anything s possible. Al Pacino alias Michael Corleone in The Godfather Part II What is this

More information

Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Introduction to Statistical Hypothesis Testing Prof. Arun K Tangirala Department of Chemical Engineering Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Lecture 09 Basics of Hypothesis Testing Hello friends, welcome

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome

Instrumental reasoning* John Broome Instrumental reasoning* John Broome For: Rationality, Rules and Structure, edited by Julian Nida-Rümelin and Wolfgang Spohn, Kluwer. * This paper was written while I was a visiting fellow at the Swedish

More information

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM

SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM Professor Douglas W. Portmore SATISFICING CONSEQUENTIALISM AND SCALAR CONSEQUENTIALISM I. Satisficing Consequentialism: The General Idea SC An act is morally right (i.e., morally permissible) if and only

More information

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground

An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground An Analysis of Freedom and Rational Egoism in Notes From Underground Michael Hannon It seems to me that the whole of human life can be summed up in the one statement that man only exists for the purpose

More information

RETHINKING THE GOOD. Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning. Larry S. Temkin

RETHINKING THE GOOD. Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning. Larry S. Temkin RETHINKING THE GOOD Moral Ideals and the Nature of Practical Reasoning Larry S. Temkin Contents 1. Introduction 1.1 Overview of the Book 1.2 A Guide to the Material 1.3 Intuitions 1.4 Impossibility Arguments

More information

GCE Religious Studies Unit A (RSS01) Religion and Ethics 1 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate B

GCE Religious Studies Unit A (RSS01) Religion and Ethics 1 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate B hij Teacher Resource Bank GCE Religious Studies Unit A (RSS01) Religion and Ethics 1 June 2009 Examination Candidate Exemplar Work: Candidate B Copyright 2009 AQA and its licensors. All rights reserved.

More information

Disvalue in nature and intervention *

Disvalue in nature and intervention * Disvalue in nature and intervention * Oscar Horta University of Santiago de Compostela THE FOX, THE RABBIT AND THE VEGAN FOOD RATIONS Consider the following thought experiment. Suppose there is a rabbit

More information

1.2. What is said: propositions

1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2. What is said: propositions 1.2.0. Overview In 1.1.5, we saw the close relation between two properties of a deductive inference: (i) it is a transition from premises to conclusion that is free of any

More information

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC

SUNK COSTS. Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC SUNK COSTS Robert Bass Department of Philosophy Coastal Carolina University Conway, SC 29528 rbass@coastal.edu ABSTRACT Decision theorists generally object to honoring sunk costs that is, treating the

More information

IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE

IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH? PERSPECTIVES FROM THE HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE MÈTODE Science Studies Journal, 5 (2015): 195-199. University of Valencia. DOI: 10.7203/metode.84.3883 ISSN: 2174-3487. Article received: 10/07/2014, accepted: 18/09/2014. IS THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD A MYTH?

More information

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR

SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR CRÍTICA, Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía Vol. XXXI, No. 91 (abril 1999): 91 103 SAVING RELATIVISM FROM ITS SAVIOUR MAX KÖLBEL Doctoral Programme in Cognitive Science Universität Hamburg In his paper

More information

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984)

What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984) What Makes Someone s Life Go Best from Reasons and Persons by Derek Parfit (1984) What would be best for someone, or would be most in this person's interests, or would make this person's life go, for him,

More information

Evaluating Arguments

Evaluating Arguments Govier: A Practical Study of Argument 1 Evaluating Arguments Chapter 4 begins an important discussion on how to evaluate arguments. The basics on how to evaluate arguments are presented in this chapter

More information

Act individuation and basic acts

Act individuation and basic acts Act individuation and basic acts August 27, 2004 1 Arguments for a coarse-grained criterion of act-individuation........ 2 1.1 Argument from parsimony........................ 2 1.2 The problem of the relationship

More information

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006)

in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006) in Social Science Encyclopedia (Routledge, forthcoming, 2006). Consequentialism Ethics in Practice, 3 rd edition, edited by Hugh LaFollette (Blackwell Publishers, forthcoming, 2006) Peter Vallentyne, University

More information

Spectrum Arguments: Objections and Replies Part II. Vagueness and Indeterminacy, Zeno s Paradox, Heuristics and Similarity Arguments

Spectrum Arguments: Objections and Replies Part II. Vagueness and Indeterminacy, Zeno s Paradox, Heuristics and Similarity Arguments 10 Spectrum Arguments: Objections and Replies Part II Vagueness and Indeterminacy, Zeno s Paradox, Heuristics and Similarity Arguments In this chapter, I continue my examination of the main objections

More information