Is the New Natural Law Thomistic?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Is the New Natural Law Thomistic?"

Transcription

1 Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? Michael Pakaluk Abstract. Whether the new natural law theory counts as a plausible interpretation of St. Thomas Aquinas is not a mere antiquarian question in the history of philosophy but is itself a philosophical question, which bears on how we should interpret and assess the NNLT. Through an examination of problems in Germain Grisez influential paper The First Principle of Practical Reason, which proposed an interpretation of Summa theologiae I II, q. 94, a. 2, it is argued that the NNLT is on every major point at odds with Aquinas, such that the NNLT involves a rejection of the classical and Catholic traditions of natural law and not a reformulation, revival, or saving of that tradition. The NNLT gives a flawed account of individual morality, not a Thomistic account of law as binding a community. National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly 13.1 (Spring 2013): The Question and Its Importance I shall argue here that the celebrated interpretation by Germain Grisez in his 1965 paper, The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa Theologiae, 1 2, Question 94, Article 2 1 is unsound and may be shown to be so. Suppose that it is: What then? A defender of the new natural law theory could retort that the conclusion is irrelevant, because the history of philosophy is one thing, but philosophy is something else, and the NNLT is advanced as a contribution to the latter. That the NNLT originated in an article interpreting St. Thomas Aquinas Michael Pakaluk, PhD, is a professor of philosophy and chairman of the philosophy department of Ave Maria University in Ave Maria, Florida. 1 Germain Grisez, The First Principle of Practical Reason: A Commentary on the Summa theologiae, 1 2 Question 94, Article 2, Natural Law Forum 10 (1965): The National Catholic Bioethics Center 57

2 The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Spring 2013 hardly means that it must be viewed now as such. 2 Moreover, since Aquinas was fallible, if his view in Summa theologiae I II, q. 94, a. 2 (henceforth, 94.2 ) were shown to be different from the truth, then so much the worse for his view. But not all NNL theorists thus dissociate their theory from Aquinas. Grisez, in his most authoritative exposition of the NNLT, attributes it to Aquinas and contrasts it with the voluntaristic approach developed by Francisco Suarez. 3 He recommends his 1965 article for its explanation of the Thomistic approach. 4 So Grisez at least continues to claim that the NNLT gives an authentic interpretation of Aquinas on natural law. And this is unsurprising, because Aquinas is the great synthesizer of classical and Christian thought. To break radically with a central view in Aquinas, about so fundamental a matter, is to risk breaking also with the considered judgments of Aristotle, the Stoics, the Roman jurists, Augustine, and Sacred Scripture. No Catholic who believed in an inheritance of shared wisdom deriving from such sources would sever the history of philosophy from philosophy. Indeed, the NNLT rose to prominence through proposing what seemed a stimulating new interpretation of Aquinas, and so it would be correspondingly weakened if it turned out that that early attention had been misguided. In fact, why should we have regarded the NNLT as a theory of law, except that the 1965 paper gives an interpretation of Aquinas specifically on law? With its talk of basic goods and principles of practical reason pertaining to an individual, why is not the NNLT simply a moral theory? There are many moral theories put forward by philosophy professors: Why should this one in particular get introduced into discussions of philosophy of law? Indeed, what recommends this moral theory in particular to Catholics, other than the purely negative consideration that it is not consequentialist? Again, since the 1965 paper is the link between the NNLT and the Catholic intellectual tradition, if that paper gives no sound interpretation of Aquinas, then the NNLT gains no support from that tradition, except incidentally. It would be as if Aquinas had never existed and all the work of showing that there was some reality which could rightly be called natural law was to be accomplished merely by the arguments of the NNL theorists. Could the NNLT support that onus probandi? Suppose no one was on the lookout for first principles of practical reason which corresponded to what Aquinas asserts in 94.2: then who would think (for example) that the philosophical commonplace, that some goods are not purely instrumental, implied the existence of a natural law? Or would anyone have supposed that, because health is not an instrument in the manner of legal tender, the precept health is a good to be done (in just that unusual form, Grisez insists) is a basic and selfevident principle of practical reason? 2 See John Finnis and Germain Grisez, The Basic Principles of Natural Law: A Reply to Ralph Mclnerny, American Journal of Jurisprudence 26.1 (1981): Germain Grisez, The Way of the Lord Jesus, vol. 1, Christian Moral Principles (Quincy, IL: Franciscan Herald Press, 1983), See also John Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980), 43 47, 54 57,

3 Pakaluk Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? Boundaries on the Interpretation of 94.2 Often one may set boundaries to a correct interpretation of text, without deciding how all the details of the passage are to be explained. Doing so is especially important for Aquinas, because he writes in articulated sections which contribute to some carefully designed whole: the arguments of any section should be interpreted relative to that section s purpose. So, what is the purpose of 94.2? Aquinas says it concerns what precepts are precepts of the natural law 5 and whether the natural law contains one precept or many precepts 6 slightly different questions, but obviously if one s manner of identifying the precepts leads to the conclusion that there is more than one precept, then in answering the first form of the question we answer the second. Good enough, but what is the philosophical puzzle (aporia) which motivates this article? A grasp of the puzzle is necessary for a grasp of the solution. 7 The puzzle is this: All human law is derived from the natural law, yet we see that only some human laws are said to be of (or from) the law of nature, and, moreover, these constitute a rather disparate class, involving laws against suicide, concerning marriage, and concerning worship of God. 8 Why then do only such laws get picked out as of the law of nature, and how do they constitute a true class, which warrants our use of the singular, the or a law of nature? The puzzle is a twofold difficulty about how to reconcile a philosophical thesis ( all human law is derived from the natural law ) with what we are wont to say (namely, that particular kinds of precepts involve the law of nature); also, why we are wont to speak of a law of nature, despite our apparently recognizing a plurality of such precepts. Aquinas s solution is clever and involves two philosophical innovations: first, he extends natural law to cover three natural inclinations, not only two, as had been traditional; second, he appeals to a fundamental law, which he calls the first precept of law. The first innovation can be discerned if we observe how Aquinas proceeds, in contrast, in the passage from the Sentences Commentary just cited. In that passage, Aquinas defines natural law in such a way that it can extend to only two areas of law: because man is by nature a rational animal, there is one group of precepts of natural law corresponding to the genus, animal, and another corresponding to the species, rational. But in 94.2, perhaps because he will need to deal later in the Summa with 5 Aquinas states this in the introduction to q. 94: quae sint praecepta legis naturalis. This and all other translations of Aquinas in this essay are my own, unless otherwise noted. 6 For example, Videtur quod lex naturalis non contineat plura praecepta, sed unum tantum, in obj See Aristotle, Metaphysics, book III, part 1. 8 The occasions are few where Aquinas asks whether a precept is of the law of nature (de lege naturali; de lege naturae) or pertains to the law of nature (pertinent ad ius naturale): basically Summa theologiae (ST) II II, q. 64, a. 5 corpus; ST II II, q. 85, a. 1 corpus; and Scriptum super libros sententiarum IV, d. 33, q. 1, a. 1 corpus, referred to hereafter as Sentences Commentary. 59

4 The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Spring 2013 suicide also being contrary to the natural law, Aquinas innovates by referring to a third aspect of human, namely, an inclination to self-preservation which belongs to us simply in virtue of our being a natural substance. The second innovation, as mentioned, is his appeal to a fundamental law, which he calls the first precept of law, which is that good is to be done and sought after, and evil is to be avoided. This fundamental law is sometimes referred to, incorrectly, as the first principle of practical reason ; Aquinas refers to it, significantly, as the first precept of the law, which he indeed says is a first or ultimate principle which is in practical reason. 9 The nature of the puzzle requires that we understand this fundamental law in such a way that, first, it explains the attribution of various laws within the three classes mentioned to a natural inclination of human nature (Aquinas does not say that there are only three precepts of the law of nature, corresponding to the three natural inclinations), and second, it groups together only the laws within these classes and not anything else (since this fundamental law is meant to explain why there is a single body of law which can be called natural law). The first precept of law has to be interpreted such that it yields not just three precepts (that is, one for each inclination) and not all precepts (that is, any precept at all, in the manner of a completely general principle of practical rationality). Yet this purpose of 94.2 has been obscured by inaccurate translations. 10 Consider for example this paragraph from near the end of the corpus: Tertio modo inest homini inclinatio ad bonum secundum naturam rationis, quae est sibi propria, sicut homo habet naturalem inclinationem ad hoc quod veritatem cognoscat de Deo, et ad hoc quod in societate vivat. Et secundum hoc, ad legem naturalem pertinent ea quae ad huiusmodi inclinationem spectant, utpote quod homo ignorantiam vitet, quod alios non offendat cum quibus debet conversari, et cetera huiusmodi quae ad hoc spectant. Two interrelated questions, which look at first to be mere quibbles, are crucially important here: (1) what should we regard as the referent of the emphasized pronoun, and (2) how should pertinent be understood in this context? With reference to the first question: it seems we should take the pronoun to mean those precepts, as regards which utpote then serves to introduce examples, and spectant accordingly tells us what these precepts are solicitous for. The examples of precepts which he gives are avoid ignorance and do not harm those among whom you must live (that is, your neighbor). What these precepts are solicitous for are the good of knowledge of God and the good of living in society with others. With 9 In the corpus of the article, as well as ad 2 and ad 3, it is simply the first precept, namely, of law. 10 In confirmation of the emphasis placed on the study of original languages by the motu proprio of Pope Benedict XVI, Latina lingua (November 10, 2012), n. 2: Nostris quoque temporibus Latinae linguae et cultus cognitio perquam est necessaria ad fontes vestigandos ex quibus complures disciplinae ceteroqui hauriunt, exempli gratia Theologia, Liturgia, Patrologia et Ius Canonicum. 60

5 Pakaluk Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? reference to the second question: it seems that pertinent means is assignable to or is classified as (as the verb typically means in other contexts), so that the claim is that the identified precepts, and others like them, are assignable to the law of nature. So careful attention to Aquinas s language shows that his concern is with why we pick out some precepts, among those precepts already familiar to us by custom or in positive law, and assign those in particular to the law of nature. The passage should accordingly be rendered as follows: There is present in man an inclination to good in a third way, corresponding to the nature of [his power of] reason, which is something which belongs only to man in the way, namely, that man has a natural inclination to this [good], that he know the truth about God, and to this [good], that he live in society. And corresponding to this [aspect of man s nature], those [precepts] which are solicitous for that sort of inclination are assignable to the law of nature, for example, that man should avoid ignorance, that he not harm those among whom he must live, and other [precepts] like that, which are solicitous for that [aspect of man s nature]. Note that for the sake of accuracy, good 11 must be supplied in two places, and precepts too where relevant. The Dominican Fathers render the passage in a way that may tend to suggest, misleadingly, that Aquinas hold that goods, rather than precepts, belong to the natural law: Thirdly, there is in man an inclination to good, according to the nature of his reason, which nature is proper to him: thus man has a natural inclination to know the truth about God, and to live in society: and in this respect, whatever pertains to this inclination belongs to the natural law; for instance, to shun ignorance, to avoid offending those among whom one has to live, and other such things regarding the above inclination. 12 The chief insufficiency of this translation is in the phrases, whatever pertains to and other such things, which render constructions which are not indeterminate in Aquinas s exposition but which refer to precepts Because ad hoc stands in for ad bonum beforehand. Similarly, we must supply something like aspect of man s nature, because secundum hoc stands in for secundum naturam rationis. Secundum suggests a mapping or correlation and is used by Aquinas here precisely as Aristotle uses kata. 12 Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologica, trans. Fathers of the English Dominican Province (New York: Benziger Brothers, 1947), I II, q. 94, a. 2, emphases added. 13 Other inaccuracies, emphasized above, contribute to the misleading sense: nature of his reason for naturam rationis is misleading, because what Aquinas means is, strictly, man s nature as involving reason (that is, the genitive, rationis, is what grammarians call a defining genitive ); thus for sicut is off the mark, because sicut is coordinated with modo and illustrates the manner; to know the truth about God, and to live in society are misleading because the translators have concluded that ad hoc, quod is merely a circumlocution rather than used precisely to reintroduce bonum; finally, pertains and regarding for spectant miss the sense. 61

6 The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Spring 2013 Grisez translation in his 1965 article similarly fails to distinguish when Aquinas is referring to goods and when he is referring to precepts: Third, there is in man an inclination to the good based on the rational aspect of his nature, which is peculiar to himself. For example, man has a natural inclination to this, that he might know the truth concerning God, and to this, that he might live in society. In accordance with this inclination, those things relating to an inclination of this sort fall under natural law. For instance, that man should avoid ignorance, that he should not offend those among whom he must live, and other points relevant to this inclination. 14 So a commonly used translation obscures the purpose of 94.2, and various inaccuracies in Grisez translation tend to support the mistaken view that basic precepts are meant to correspond to putative basic goods. Miscues in the Grisez Interpretation If in some passage Aquinas insists upon drawing a distinction, yet an interpretation of that passage overlooks or conflates the distinction, or treats it as unnecessary, then the interpretation is to that extent unsound. But there are several important distinctions in 94.2 which the Grisez interpretation gets wrong in such ways. The Distinction between Precepts of the Natural Law and Natural Inclinations Here is Grisez on the passage just examined: Nature is the given from which man develops and from which arise tendencies of ranks corresponding to its distinct strata. These tendencies are not natural law; the tendencies indicate possible actions, and hence they provide reason with the point of departure it requires in order to propose ends. The precepts of reason which clothe the objects of inclinations in the intelligibility of endsto-be-pursued-by-work these precepts are the natural law. Thus natural law has many precepts which are unified in this, that all of these precepts are ordered to practical reason s achievement of its own end, the direction of action toward end. 15 In the passage, Aquinas distinguishes between the natural inclinations which point toward a goal, and which therefore are naturally known to be good, and precepts which promote such a goal, or hinder what is contrary to it. In contrast, Grisez, consistent with his translation, fails to distinguish the goods from the precepts. Grisez will later go on to claim that there are seven or more inclinations or basic goods for which we strive. 16 These inclinations, he says, set down no ends for us but only indicate possible actions, and it is practical reason, not human nature, which proposes ends. When practical reason proposes an end in this way, Grisez claims, then 14 Grisez, First Principle of Practical Reason, 171, emphases added. 15 Ibid., There are seven categories of basic human goods which perfect persons and contribute to their fulfillment both as individuals and in communities, Grisez, Christian Moral Principles,

7 Pakaluk Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? a precept of the form, this end is to be pursued, is the result, and only precepts of that form constitute the natural law. The Distinction between Known to Experts and Known to All Aquinas in 94.2 distinguishes between propositions known in themselves by experts alone, and those known in themselves by everyone (communiter omnibus). Grisez basically ignores the distinction, saying that Aquinas introduces it only to clarify the meaning of self-evident. 17 Why does Aquinas draw the distinction? Aquinas s discussion of natural law is embedded in his general treatment of law, which he defines as (i) a precept of reason (ii) ordering actions to the common good, (iii) set down by someone with responsibility for the common good, and (iv) promulgated. 18 The natural law, if it is law, must satisfy all four conditions. In q. 94, a. 1, where he argues that the natural law consists of precepts rather than habits of affirming precepts, he effectively claims that it satisfies the first condition. In 94.2 one of his incidental concerns is to explain the natural law in such a way that it satisfies the other conditions: hence his concern to show that the terms which compose a precept of natural law are naturally known, as, indeed, the natural law is promulgated precisely through its being naturally known. 19 If the precepts of the natural law were not known simply through someone s being a human who develops in typical circumstances, they could not be said to have been promulgated to the human race. 20 Grisez oversight seems symptomatic of a shortcoming in his interpretation, namely, that it construes 94.2 as discussing not law but rather an individual s prudential reasoning. Indeed, the precepts which Grisez believes Aquinas has in mind, such as that health is to be sought (namely, by me), evidently fail to satisfy the definition of law. 21 The Naturally Known as Distinct from What Is Known in Itself So for Aquinas the natural law, since it is law, must be promulgated. The natural law is also the basis of all human law. The promulgation of the natural law consists in its being naturally known to all. But its being the basis for all human law requires that its propositions be known not through other precepts of law. For a proposition to be naturally known, its terms must be naturally known. For Aquinas, everyone naturally knows what man is; but to know what man is is to know 17 Grisez, First Principle of Practical Reason, ST I II, q See ST I II, q. 100, a. 4, ad 1: The first general precepts of the law of nature are known in themselves to anyone who has natural reason, and they stand in no need of promulgation. (See also a. 3 corpus and q. 100, a. 11 corpus.) 20 Presumably communiter in communiter omnibus indicates that everyone s access to it is of the same manner, namely, naturaliter. 21 In Christian Moral Principles, Grisez gives these precepts the more appropriate appellation of fundamental principles of morality. 63

8 The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Spring 2013 the most basic kind of thing that he is, namely, a being in the category of substance (rather than, say, a quality such as whiteness), as well as his genus ( animal), and his species (rational). Indeed, the definition of man as a natural substance which is a rational animal reveals what is known, when someone knows what man is. However, anything that has a nature, ipso facto has an inclination in virtue of its having this nature. 22 Hence to know something s nature is to know what that thing is inclined to in virtue of its nature (for man, in three corresponding ways). Thus, if what man is is naturally known, then what man is inclined to, in virtue of being man, is also naturally known. But we all naturally grasp that to be a good is to be a goal. Therefore, those things that are naturally good for man are also naturally known. Hence the terms which compose the precepts of the natural law are naturally known to everyone, and therefore so are the precepts themselves. Yet Grisez interpretation finds no room for the distinction between a proposition s being naturally known (naturaliter nota) and its being known in itself (per se nota). He conflates these, speaking only of the self-evidence and intelligibility of what he takes to be the basic precepts of the law of nature. For Aquinas, we can know what is good for man, and our judgments about what things are good for man are judgments about the world (which is why it becomes an important question for Aquinas whether this knowledge is typically attained only by experts or by people in general). But for Grisez, to judge that certain things are good is a matter of giving expression to inclinations within practical reason: In the case of theoretical knowledge, the known has the reality which is shared before the knower comes to share in it in theory the mind must conform to facts and the world calls the turn. In practical knowledge, on the other hand, the knower arrives at the destination first; and what is known will be altered as a result of having been thought about, since the known must conform to the mind of the knower. The mind uses the power of the knower to see that the known will conform to it; the mind calls the turn. 23 The Known in Itself as Distinct from the Naturally Known Two general truths which are said to be known in themselves enter into Aquinas s account: good is what all things desire, and good is to be done and its contrary, evil, is to be avoided. Aquinas also holds that if a general truth is known in itself, then an instance of that general truth is also known in itself. The first general truth, as mentioned, means something like: to be a good is to be a goal. For Aquinas, this truth serves as a schema which can be applied in different ways, given different conditions. For example, from this is an inclination inherent in the senses one can infer its object is a sensible (or sensual) good, and 22 A natural agent produces a twofold effect on the patient: for in the first place it gives it the form; and secondly it gives it the movement that results from the form. ST I II, q. 26, a. 2 corpus. (See also q. 94, a. 3.) 23 Grisez, First Principle of Practical Reason,

9 Pakaluk Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? from this is an inclination of a thing of that kind one can infer the object of that inclination is good for a thing of that kind. The second general truth is said by Aquinas to be analogous to the principle of noncontradiction. The very purpose of this truth is to construct bridges between judgments about how the world is what things are good and judgments about how the world should be what things ought to be done. Those who maintain that there can be no such bridge owe us an explanation as to how the principle of noncontradiction is possible, since that principle constructs bridges from statements of the form A is F to statements of the form F ought to be affirmed of A and F ought not be denied of A. This second general truth, too, serves as a schema for instances asserted with particular conditions, and in particular: What is good for man is to be done, and its contrary to be avoided, by man. We said that the first principle of law needed to be qualified, for the purposes of 94.2, as to make it especially relevant to the formulation of law, and this qualification captures the relevant restriction. The principle in this form comes into play in Aquinas s account as follows. For Aquinas, what man is is naturally known to all men (communiter omnibus). Hence, that man is a natural substance who is an animal, and rational, is also naturally known. Therefore, that man has three kinds of inclinations, implied by these three aspects of his natural form, is also naturally known. But we grasp the general truth, that to be a good is to be an object of an inclination, simply because we grasp in itself the general truth that a good is a goal. But instances of that truth are also known in themselves: so that the objects of man s natural inclinations are natural goods for man is also something known in itself. (Observe that this truth is known not simply in itself, but also naturally so, because its terms are.) But we also grasp, as known in itself, the general truth that what is good is to be done, and its contrary is to be avoided. Thus we additionally grasp, as known in itself, any instances of that truth, such as that what is good for man is to be done, and its contrary is to be avoided, by man. Therefore, finally, we grasp, as both known in itself and as naturally known, instances of this last claim, that is, where instances of any of the natural goods are supplied for those things that are good for man. That is why a precept such as Man is to avoid the death of man ( Thou shalt not kill ) can both serve as a basic precept (because it is known in itself) and be regarded as promulgated (because it is naturally known). I said that What is good for man is to be done, and its contrary to be avoided, by man, was the particular specification of the first principle in practical reason which would put that principle in the requisite form so that it could serve as the first principle of law. By adding that qualification, we can arrive at precepts which satisfy two other conditions of law, namely, that it consists of precepts which order to the common good since now a common good is specified and advanced (what is good for man), which is advanced by precepts which direct us toward that good (is to be done by man). Grisez interpretation misses the significance of these two general truths. Because it misses the role of natural teleology in Aquinas s account, it fails to 65

10 The National Catholic Bioethics Quarterly Spring 2013 recognize how Aquinas believes that on the basis of natural inclinations we can infer natural goods. Because it insists on a chasm between indicative and prescriptive statements, it fails to recognize how the first precept of law precisely presupposes that there is no such chasm. Ironically, that principle in Aquinas which NNL theorists regard as best testifying to the underivability of ought from is claims is proposed by Aquinas precisely to allow for the derivation of prescriptions of law from descriptions of goods. Grisez overlooking of the relevant qualification in the first precept of law, which makes it serviceable for an account of natural law, is yet another example of his reduction of natural law to a theory of individual morality. The Distinction between the Natural Law As Measure and the Natural Law As Measured Question 94, a. 2 does not address the fourth part of the definition of law, namely, that law is set down by someone with authority for the common good, but its account is consistent with what Aquinas says elsewhere, namely, that the natural law is a participation in the eternal law of God, and that, consequently, in the natural law man both measures and is measured. By the former, Aquinas means that when we articulate precepts of the natural law, our lawmaking coincides with God s directive providence; by the latter, that our articulation of precepts of the natural law is answerable to some standard set by God that the correctness or incorrectness of that articulation depends upon whether it is itself in conformity with law. The picture of natural law reasoning which emerges from 94.2 is of man as a steward of his own nature. He discerns his own nature and, through his reason which itself is a natural power directs himself toward those ends to which his nature inclines. Lawmaking is an art which completes nature, as does any art. Natural law measures because it is man s own articulation, which serves as the standard for all other human laws; but natural law is measured, because its correctness consists in its precepts correctly ordering human actions so as to promote what is aimed at by natural inclinations, and safeguard against what is contrary. One need only add that God is naturally known as the author of nature, which Aquinas also holds, and then, on this account, the natural law is set down by God. 24 On Grisez interpretation, in contrast, there is no sense in which the natural law is measured, as it is not articulated as in conformity with anything. Grisez account describes the prudential reasoning of an individual in such a way that perhaps, after the fact, it could be accounted for in relation to God and God s purposes, 25 yet the account requires no reference to any lawgiver besides man. 24 ST I, q. 2, a. 3 corpus. 25 See Finnis, Natural Law and Natural Rights, 390: The theory of Eternal Law... must not be treated as a theory which could guide investigation and verification of suggested norms... rather, it is a speculation about why those norms whose holding has been appropriately verified or established do hold. See all of chapter 8. 66

11 Pakaluk Is the New Natural Law Thomistic? Conclusion The foundational text of the NNLT is Grisez interpretation of Aquinas. Some proponents of the NNLT, including its leading expositor, claim that that interpretation is Thomistic understandably so, because if a connection with Aquinas is broken, then the NNLT becomes one among many doubtful theories in moral philosophy. Yet Grisez interpretation fails to satisfy even minimal conditions of a sound interpretation and on every fundamental point is at odds with Aquinas. Fifty years later we can see that it was a misapprehension, if ever the NNLT was associated with the tradition of natural law. A clear assessment requires that we acknowledge that the NNLT abandons that tradition and does not save it. 67

12

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau

Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau Volume 12, No 2, Fall 2017 ISSN 1932-1066 Wisdom in Aristotle and Aquinas From Metaphysics to Mysticism Edmond Eh University of Saint Joseph, Macau edmond_eh@usj.edu.mo Abstract: This essay contains an

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers

Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers Self-Evidence in Finnis Natural Law Theory: A Reply to Sayers IRENE O CONNELL* Introduction In Volume 23 (1998) of the Australian Journal of Legal Philosophy Mark Sayers1 sets out some objections to aspects

More information

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95.

REVIEW. St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp $5.95. REVIEW St. Thomas Aquinas. By RALPH MCINERNY. The University of Notre Dame Press 1982 (reprint of Twayne Publishers 1977). Pp. 172. $5.95. McInerny has succeeded at a demanding task: he has written a compact

More information

Natural Law and the "Is" - "Ought" Question: An Invitation to Professor Veatch

Natural Law and the Is - Ought Question: An Invitation to Professor Veatch The Catholic Lawyer Volume 26 Number 4 Volume 26, Autumn 1981, Number 4 Article 3 September 2017 Natural Law and the "Is" - "Ought" Question: An Invitation to Professor Veatch John Finnis Follow this and

More information

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres

Anthony P. Andres. The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic. Anthony P. Andres [ Loyola Book Comp., run.tex: 0 AQR Vol. W rev. 0, 17 Jun 2009 ] [The Aquinas Review Vol. W rev. 0: 1 The Place of Conversion in Aristotelian Logic From at least the time of John of St. Thomas, scholastic

More information

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries ON NORMATIVE ETHICAL THEORIES: SOME BASICS From the dawn of philosophy, the question concerning the summum bonum, or, what is the same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has been accounted the

More information

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB 1 1Aristotle s Categories in St. Augustine by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Because St. Augustine begins to talk about substance early in the De Trinitate (1, 1, 1), a notion which he later equates with essence

More information

Worship. A Thomistic Perspective on. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD

Worship. A Thomistic Perspective on. Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD A Thomistic Perspective on Worship Francisco J. Romero Carrasquillo, PhD Associate Professor of Philosophy, Universidad Panamericana (Mexico) Headmaster, St. John Bosco High School (Salem, OR) The Natural

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics )

The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics ) The Unmoved Mover (Metaphysics 12.1-6) Aristotle Part 1 The subject of our inquiry is substance; for the principles and the causes we are seeking are those of substances. For if the universe is of the

More information

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015

Peter L.P. Simpson January, 2015 1 This translation of the Prologue of the Ordinatio of the Venerable Inceptor, William of Ockham, is partial and in progress. The prologue and the first distinction of book one of the Ordinatio fill volume

More information

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will

QUESTION 8. The Objects of the Will QUESTION 8 The Objects of the Will Next, we have to consider voluntary acts themselves in particular. First, we have to consider the acts that belong immediately to the will in the sense that they are

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature

Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature Thomas Aquinas The Treatise on the Divine Nature Summa Theologiae I 1 13 Translated, with Commentary, by Brian Shanley Introduction by Robert Pasnau Hackett Publishing Company, Inc. Indianapolis/Cambridge

More information

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance

- 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance - 1 - Outline of NICOMACHEAN ETHICS, Book I Book I--Dialectical discussion leading to Aristotle's definition of happiness: activity in accordance with virtue or excellence (arete) in a complete life Chapter

More information

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n.

270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. Ordinatio prologue, q. 5, nn. 270 313 A. The views of others 270 Now that we have settled these issues, we should answer the first question [n. 217]. There are five ways to answer in the negative. [The

More information

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have

What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection. Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have What Lurks Beneath the Integrity Objection Bernard Williams s alienation and integrity arguments against consequentialism have served as the point of departure for much of the most interesting work that

More information

QUESTION 94. The Natural Law

QUESTION 94. The Natural Law QUESTION 94 The Natural Law We next have to consider the natural law. And on this topic there are six questions: (1) What is the natural law? (2) Which precepts belong to the natural law? (3) Are all the

More information

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings

QUESTION 44. The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings QUESTION 44 The Procession of Creatures from God, and the First Cause of All Beings Now that we have considered the divine persons, we will next consider the procession of creatures from God. This treatment

More information

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas

Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God. From Summa Theologica. St. Thomas Aquinas Five Ways to Prove the Existence of God From Summa Theologica St. Thomas Aquinas Thomas Aquinas (1225 1274), born near Naples, was the most influential philosopher of the medieval period. He joined the

More information

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It

QUESTION 87. How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It QUESTION 87 How Our Intellect Has Cognition of Itself and of What Exists Within It Next we have to consider how the intellective soul has cognition of itself and of what exists within it. And on this topic

More information

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue

QUESTION 55. The Essence of a Virtue QUESTION 55 The Essence of a Virtue Next we have to consider habits in a specific way (in speciali). And since, as has been explained (q. 54, a. 3), habits are distinguished by good and bad, we will first

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism

Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Valparaiso University Law Review Volume 20 Number 1 pp.55-60 Fall 1985 Positivism, Natural Law, and Disestablishment: Some Questions Raised by MacCormick's Moralistic Amoralism Joseph M. Boyle Jr. Recommended

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications

What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications What We Are: Our Metaphysical Nature & Moral Implications Julia Lei Western University ABSTRACT An account of our metaphysical nature provides an answer to the question of what are we? One such account

More information

William Ockham on Universals

William Ockham on Universals MP_C07.qxd 11/17/06 5:28 PM Page 71 7 William Ockham on Universals Ockham s First Theory: A Universal is a Fictum One can plausibly say that a universal is not a real thing inherent in a subject [habens

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder.

Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder. 1 Consequentialism, Incoherence and Choice. Rejoinder to a Rejoinder. by Peter Simpson and Robert McKim In a number of books and essays Joseph Boyle, John Finnis, and Germain Grisez (hereafter BFG) have

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Book Gamma of the Metaphysics Robert L. Latta Having argued that there is a science which studies being as being, Aristotle goes on to inquire, at the beginning

More information

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1

Questions on Book III of the De anima 1 Siger of Brabant Questions on Book III of the De anima 1 Regarding the part of the soul by which it has cognition and wisdom, etc. [De an. III, 429a10] And 2 with respect to this third book there are four

More information

On Truth Thomas Aquinas

On Truth Thomas Aquinas On Truth Thomas Aquinas Art 1: Whether truth resides only in the intellect? Objection 1. It seems that truth does not reside only in the intellect, but rather in things. For Augustine (Soliloq. ii, 5)

More information

Introduction. Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy

Introduction. Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy Introduction Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy 0.1 The Central Claims of Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy The central claim of natural law jurisprudence

More information

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005)

Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005) National Admissions Test for Law (LNAT) Commentary on Sample Test (May 2005) General There are two alternative strategies which can be employed when answering questions in a multiple-choice test. Some

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen

Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Stance Volume 6 2013 29 Fatalism and Truth at a Time Chad Marxen Abstract: In this paper, I will examine an argument for fatalism. I will offer a formalized version of the argument and analyze one of the

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination

Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination MP_C12.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 103 12 Henry of Ghent on Divine Illumination [II.] Reply [A. Knowledge in a broad sense] Consider all the objects of cognition, standing in an ordered relation to each

More information

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures

QUESTION 34. The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures QUESTION 34 The Goodness and Badness of Pleasures Next we have to consider the goodness and badness of pleasures. And on this topic there are four questions: (1) Is every pleasure bad? (2) Given that not

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008

Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 Can Christianity be Reduced to Morality? Ted Di Maria, Philosophy, Gonzaga University Gonzaga Socratic Club, April 18, 2008 As one of the world s great religions, Christianity has been one of the supreme

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Imagine, if you will, that I am still at Notre Dame as a graduate student in the early 90s,

Imagine, if you will, that I am still at Notre Dame as a graduate student in the early 90s, Radical Orthodoxy, Univocity, and the New Apophaticism Thomas Williams This paper was put together somewhat hastily, in the midst of preparations for moving, for a session on Radical Orthodoxy at the International

More information

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006)

The Names of God. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) The Names of God from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Questions 12-13) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) For with respect to God, it is more apparent to us what God is not, rather

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

Sample. 2.1 Introduction. Outline

Sample. 2.1 Introduction. Outline Chapter 2: Natural Law Outline 2.1 Introduction 2.2 Some problems of definition 2.3 Classical natural law 2.4 Divine law 2.5 Natural rights 2.6 The revival of natural law 2.7 The advent of legal positivism

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Egocentric Rationality

Egocentric Rationality 3 Egocentric Rationality 1. The Subject Matter of Egocentric Epistemology Egocentric epistemology is concerned with the perspectives of individual believers and the goal of having an accurate and comprehensive

More information

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word

QUESTION 34. The Person of the Son: The Name Word QUESTION 34 The Person of the Son: The Name Word Next we have to consider the person of the Son. Three names are attributed to the Son, viz., Son, Word, and Image. But the concept Son is taken from the

More information

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise

Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise Contextualism and the Epistemological Enterprise Michael Blome-Tillmann University College, Oxford Abstract. Epistemic contextualism (EC) is primarily a semantic view, viz. the view that knowledge -ascriptions

More information

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an

Who or what is God?, asks John Hick (Hick 2009). A theist might answer: God is an infinite person, or at least an John Hick on whether God could be an infinite person Daniel Howard-Snyder Western Washington University Abstract: "Who or what is God?," asks John Hick. A theist might answer: God is an infinite person,

More information

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT

WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT WHAT ARISTOTLE TAUGHT Aristotle was, perhaps, the greatest original thinker who ever lived. Historian H J A Sire has put the issue well: All other thinkers have begun with a theory and sought to fit reality

More information

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley

Phil Aristotle. Instructor: Jason Sheley Phil 290 - Aristotle Instructor: Jason Sheley To sum up the method 1) Human beings are naturally curious. 2) We need a place to begin our inquiry. 3) The best place to start is with commonly held beliefs.

More information

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University

A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports. Stephen Schiffer New York University A Problem for a Direct-Reference Theory of Belief Reports Stephen Schiffer New York University The direct-reference theory of belief reports to which I allude is the one held by such theorists as Nathan

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin

QUESTION 83. The Subject of Original Sin QUESTION 83 The Subject of Original Sin Next we have to consider the subject of original sin. On this topic there are four questions: (1) Is the subject of original sin the flesh or the soul in the first

More information

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.

Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I. Selections of the Nicomachean Ethics for GGL Unit: Learning to Live Well Taken from classic.mit.edu archive. Translated by W.D. Ross I.7 Let us again return to the good we are seeking, and ask what it

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions Part 2

The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions Part 2 The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions Part 2 In the second part of our teaching on The Trinity, The Dogma, The Contradictions we will be taking a deeper look at what is considered the most probable

More information

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted?

QUESTION 53. The Corruption and Diminution of Habits. Article 1. Can a habit be corrupted? QUESTION 53 The Corruption and Diminution of Habits Next we have to consider the corruption and diminution of habits (de corruptione et diminutione habituum). And on this topic there are three questions:

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason

Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason Aquinas, Maritain, and the Metaphysical Foundation of Practical Reason MatthewS~ Pugh For the past thirty-five years or so, much of the debate in Thomistic ethics has concerned the following question:

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z. Notes

GS SCORE ETHICS - A - Z.   Notes ETHICS - A - Z Absolutism Act-utilitarianism Agent-centred consideration Agent-neutral considerations : This is the view, with regard to a moral principle or claim, that it holds everywhere and is never

More information

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law Law and Authority An unjust law is not a law The statement an unjust law is not a law is often treated as a summary of how natural law theorists approach the question of whether a law is valid or not.

More information

TOBY BETENSON University of Birmingham

TOBY BETENSON University of Birmingham 254 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES TOBY BETENSON University of Birmingham Bradley Monton. Seeking God in Science: An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design. Peterborough, Ont.: Broadview, 2009. Bradley Monton s

More information

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE

KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE Diametros 27 (March 2011): 170-184 KNOWLEDGE AND OPINION IN ARISTOTLE Jarosław Olesiak In this essay I would like to examine Aristotle s distinction between knowledge 1 (episteme) and opinion (doxa). The

More information

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970)

The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) The Conflict Between Authority and Autonomy from Robert Wolff, In Defense of Anarchism (1970) 1. The Concept of Authority Politics is the exercise of the power of the state, or the attempt to influence

More information

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives

Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives Analysis Advance Access published June 15, 2009 Generic truth and mixed conjunctions: some alternatives AARON J. COTNOIR Christine Tappolet (2000) posed a problem for alethic pluralism: either deny the

More information

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist?

The Five Ways. from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist? The Five Ways from Summa Theologiae (Part I, Question 2) by Thomas Aquinas (~1265 AD) translated by Brian Shanley (2006) Question 2. Does God Exist? Article 1. Is the existence of God self-evident? It

More information

Aquinas on Law Summa Theologiae Questions 90 and 91

Aquinas on Law Summa Theologiae Questions 90 and 91 Aquinas on Law Summa Theologiae Questions 90 and 91 Question 90. The essence of law 1. Is law something pertaining to reason? 2. The end of law 3. Its cause 4. The promulgation of law Article 1. Whether

More information

Theology and Ethics: Reflections on the Revisions to Part Six of the ERDs

Theology and Ethics: Reflections on the Revisions to Part Six of the ERDs Theology and Ethics: Reflections on the Revisions to Part Six of the ERDs John A. Gallagher, Ph.D. Ongoing episcopal guidance for a ministry of the church is essential. The church s social ministries serve

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7

Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7 Universal Features: Doubts, Questions, Residual Problems DM VI 7 The View in a Sentence A universal is an ens rationis, properly regarded as an extrinsic denomination grounded in the intrinsic individual

More information

Chapter 5. St. Thomas Aquinas

Chapter 5. St. Thomas Aquinas 05_Arandia.qxp_8.5 x 10.88 Standard 4/12/16 9:45 AM Page 57 Chapter 5 St. Thomas Aquinas Treatise on Law According to St. Thomas, the definition of law may be rendered thus: It is nothing else than an

More information

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability Bayesian Probability Patrick Maher September 4, 2008 ABSTRACT. Bayesian decision theory is here construed as explicating a particular concept of rational choice and Bayesian probability is taken to be

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Bartolomé De Las Casas Essay Series

Bartolomé De Las Casas Essay Series Page 1 of 5 Bartolomé De Las Casas Essay Series Fourth Essay / Fourth Essay PDF format A Friend as Other Self By Michael Pakaluk Other Selves in Public Author with son Joseph Aristotle said that, in a

More information

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza by Erich Schaeffer A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for

More information

Action in Special Contexts

Action in Special Contexts Part III Action in Special Contexts c36.indd 283 c36.indd 284 36 Rationality john broome Rationality as a Property and Rationality as a Source of Requirements The word rationality often refers to a property

More information

The Nature and Extent of Sacred Doctrine Thomas Aquinas

The Nature and Extent of Sacred Doctrine Thomas Aquinas The Nature and Extent of Sacred Doctrine Thomas Aquinas Art 1: Whether, besides philosophy, any further doctrine is required? Objection 1: It seems that, besides philosophical science, we have no need

More information

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of

The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of The Language of Analogy in the Five Ways of St. Thomas Aquinas Moses Aaron T. Angeles, Ph.D. San Beda College The Five Ways of St. Thomas in proving the existence of God is, needless to say, a most important

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology

A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology A Study of Order: Lessons for Historiography and Theology BY JAKUB VOBORIL The medieval theologian Thomas Aquinas and the Renaissance historian Niccolo Machiavelli present radically different worldviews

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas

Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas Faith and Reason Thomas Aquinas QUESTION 1. FAITH Article 2. Whether the object of faith is something complex, by way of a proposition? Objection 1. It would seem that the object of faith is not something

More information

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano

ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano ON WRITING PHILOSOPHICAL ESSAYS: SOME GUIDELINES Richard G. Graziano The discipline of philosophy is practiced in two ways: by conversation and writing. In either case, it is extremely important that a

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information