Legal Dualism, Legal Ethics, and Fidelity to Law

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Legal Dualism, Legal Ethics, and Fidelity to Law"

Transcription

1 1 Legal Dualism, Legal Ethics, and Fidelity to Law Synopsis Joshua P. Davis* This Article argues that there is an important relationship between the nature of law and legal ethics. A crucial claim in support of this thesis is that the nature of law varies with the purpose for which it is being interpreted. In particular, the Article contends that natural law provides the best account of the nature of law when an interpreter seeks moral guidance from the law, and legal positivism provides the best account when an interpreter seeks instead to describe the law or to predict how others will interpret it. This philosophical position it labels legal dualism. Legal dualism has a significant implication for legal ethics: to the extent the law serves as a source of moral guidance for interpreters, they must act as natural lawyers. The Article tests legal dualism and its corollary for legal ethics against Bradley Wendel s justly lauded book, LAWYERS AND FIDEL- ITY TO LAW. Wendel pairs legal positivism and the moral legitimacy of law, commitments that legal dualism suggests are incompatible. The Article argues that, while Wendel makes many important contributions, his argument is not fully successful to the extent it conflicts with legal dualism. It concludes that he and others should acknowledge and address the need for ethical attorneys to act as natural lawyers. That means lawyers sometimes must make moral judgments in saying what the law is. Introduction A jurisprudential issue underlies any ethical obligation attorneys may have to follow the law. Such an obligation would presumably constrain what lawyers can do on behalf of their clients. After all, the ethical rules and plausible ethical * Associate Dean for Academic Affairs, Professor, and Director, Center for Law and Ethics, University of San Francisco School of Law. I am grateful for valuable comments from Steve Bundy, Geoff Hazard, Morris Ratner, Bill Simon, Manuel Vargas, and Brad Wendel, participants in the International Legal Ethics Conference VI in London, England, participants in the Bay Area Legal Ethics Forum, participants in the faculty workshop at the University of Kansas, and participants in the International Legal Ethics Conference VII in New York City. I am particularly appreciative of the valuable discussion this article has generated with Brad Wendel. The draft has benefited greatly from his comments. All errors of course remain my own.

2 2 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER theory prohibit lawyers, for example, from assisting clients in violating the law 1 and from making frivolous arguments in court. 2 If the content of the law were uncontroversial, so might be this constraint on attorney conduct. But what if interpreting the law involves moral judgments? Attorneys may not always be able to say what the law is without considering what it should be. That, at least, is a crude expression of what has come to be known as natural law or non-positivism. 3 What if natural lawyers are right? What if saying what the law is at least sometimes requires resolution of some moral issues? Should lawyers then make moral judgments in deciding what legal services they may provide to clients so as to avoid assisting a violation of the law or in determining what legal positions they may take so as not to make frivolous arguments? Should they refuse to assist a client or to make an argument on a client s behalf based in part on their views of morality? In other words, should attorneys impose their morality on their clients? To do so could seem immodest. Who are lawyers, one might ask, to play judge in their clients cases, at least where doing so requires resolution of contestable moral issues? This Article explores these issues. In particular, it analyzes the significance for legal ethics of a novel claim about the nature of law. The claim can aptly be called legal dualism. It holds that law can best be understood in two relevant ways: sometimes as consistent with natural law when an interpreter seeks moral guidance from the law and other times as consistent with legal positivism when an interpreter seeks merely to describe the law or to predict how others will interpret it. In other words, interpreters should be natural lawyers when they seek moral guidance from the law and legal positivists when they do not; the nature of law varies with the purpose for which it is being interpreted See, e.g., MODEL RULES OF PROF L CONDUCT Preamble (2016) ( A lawyer s conduct should conform to the requirements of the law, both in professional service to clients and in the lawyer s business and personal affairs. A lawyer should use the law s procedures only for legitimate purposes and not to harass or intimidate others. A lawyer should demonstrate respect for the legal system and for those who serve it, including judges, other lawyers and public officials. While it is a lawyer s duty, when necessary, to challenge the rectitude of official action, it is also a lawyer s duty to uphold legal process. ); MODEL RULES OF PROF L CONDUCT R. 8.4 (2016). 2. See, e.g., MODEL RULES OF PROF L CONDUCT R. 3.1 (2016); FED. R.CIV. P SCOTT J. SHAPIRO, LEGALITY 27 (2011). 4. In a sense, this argument accepts Brian Bix s invitation to focus on the ways in which different jurisprudential theories address different questions rather than the ways in which they provide different answers. BRIAN BIX, JURISPRUDENCE: THEORY AND CONTEXT 3 (6th 2012). Note that legal dualism is not meant to preclude the possibility that alternative understandings of the nature of law may prove useful when interpretation serves some other purpose. Legal dualism may thus be a special application of legal pluralism. That issue is beyond the scope of this Article.

3 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 3 Legal dualism has implications for legal ethics. It suggests that a lawyer who has a moral obligation to take the law into account in deciding what she should do cannot always avoid making moral judgments in determining what the law is. The same is true of other actors, including judges and ordinary citizens. For interpreters on whom law exerts a moral influence, what the law should be informs efforts to describe the law. Bradley Wendel s book, LAWYERS AND FIDELITY TO LAW, 5 provides a useful test of legal dualism as applied to legal ethics. His analysis warrants attention in part because his treatment of legal theory is unusually sophisticated and explicit for a work by a legal ethicist. He dedicates significant portions of the book to jurisprudence and brings to that task a great depth and breadth of knowledge. 6 Of particular importance for present purposes, Wendel stakes out a position that conflicts with legal dualism. In relevant part, Wendel argues that lawyers have a moral obligation to serve as partisans for the legal rights of their clients (rather than their interests) 7 and that in determining those rights lawyers the content of the law ultimately depends on social facts, not on moral judgment. 8 Most pertinent, this position entails that legal rights impose moral obligations 9 and that legal positivism provides the best understanding of the nature of those legal rights. 10 In other words, he would marry law as a source of moral guidance with legal positivism. Legal dualism rejects that pairing. If dualism is correct, natural law correlates to ascribing moral force to the law and legal positivism to describing the law or predicting how it will be interpreted. One cannot mix and match in the way that Wendel attempts. So which must give way, legal dualism or Wendel s position? This Article argues that Wendel does not manage to reconcile moral obligations with legal positivism. And the reason Wendel does not succeed is predicted by the justifications for dualism: he has not provided a viable alternative to morality as a way to make law sufficiently determinate to provide guidance. These conclusions, it further contends, support legal dualism as a theory. 5. BRADLEY WENDEL, LAWYERS AND FIDELITY TO LAW (2010). 6. See, e.g., id. at Another excellent and jurisprudentially sophisticated account of legal ethics is TIM DARE, THE COUNSEL OF ROGUES: A DEFENCE OF THE STANDARD CONCEPTION OF THE LAWYER S ROLE (2009). 7. Id. at Id. at 140, n. 62 ( Different flavors of legal positivism exist, but in all cases the essential positivist claim is that the legal validity of a norm is a matter of locating it with the sources specified by the rule of recognition. The rule of recognition specifies binding criteria for legal officials to use in deciding whether a given norm is a rule that is part of the legal system. ) (citing H.LA. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 94-95, 100 (2d ed. 1994)). 9. Id. at 122 ( If the arguments up to this point are sound, then the fundamental obligation of the lawyer s role is fidelity to the law itself. ). 10. See, e.g., id. at 140 & n. 62 (appearing to endorse inclusive legal positivism).

4 4 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER But that does not mean Wendel s argument fails. All that dualism requires of Wendel is that he cede one or more of his commitments. He could give up his claim that law imposes moral obligations and the aspects of his argument that seem inconsistent with legal positivism. That, however, would be a drastic step to take. Much of his analysis would fall by the wayside. Alternatively, Wendel could abandon legal positivism in favor of legal dualism. This Article suggests that strategy. It would allow Wendel to retain most of his analysis as he has formulated it. He could still pursue what appears to be a core contention that attorneys should aggressively pursue the legal rights (as opposed to the mere interests) of their clients 11 as well as the argument based in political morality that he makes in support of that contention. 12 Embracing legal dualism, however, would require him to address a crucial difficulty: lawyers at times must exercise moral judgment in deciding what they may do on behalf of their clients. Wendel does not address this difficulty. 13 This Article concludes that his apparent reason for not doing so the positivist view that lawyers need not make value judgments in saying what the law is is unpersuasive. So Wendel should confront the challenge of lawyers imposing their moral beliefs on their clients. And so should we all, scholars, judges, and attorneys alike. Otherwise, some of the most important and controversial judgments made by lawyers and other legal interpreters will evade scrutiny. Moral judgments will lurk behind decisions, denied in theory though they occur in fact. The resulting lack of transparency will obscure the nature of legal interpretation, making it more difficult for us to hold legal interpreters accountable for the contestable moral judgments they make. 14 Part I defines legal positivism, natural law, and legal dualism. Part II then offers a summary of the argument for legal dualism, explaining how it accommodates key criticisms of legal positivism and natural law by suggesting that each provides the best account of the nature of law within its proper domain. Part III applies the argument for legal dualism to legal ethics. It notes that lawyers at times merely describe the law often characterizing it in a way favorable to their clients and at other times likely have an obligation to look to the law for moral guidance. It also suggests that the standard conception of the law- 11. Id. at Id. 13. Id. at Ironically, this opacity about the interplay of morality and law is in part what historically motivated legal positivists. Legal positivists wanted clarity about what the law is precisely so that it could be subjected, as appropriate, to criticism. See, e.g., Joshua P. Davis, Legality, Morality, Duality, 2014 UTAH L. REV. 55, ; H.L.A. Hart, Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals, 71 HARV. L. REV. 593, (1958) (arguing the great legal positivists John Austin and Jeremy Bentham insisted on the distinction between what the law is and what it ought to be in part to allow for effective criticism of unjust laws).

5 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 5 yerly role under which lawyers are morally free to act as partisan advocates on behalf of their clients 15 seems to imply that the law exerts a moral force. In other words, there would appear to be an element of reciprocity lawyers cannot rely on the moral force of the law to liberate them to act within the adversarial system without recognizing that the law also makes moral demands on them. Assuming law does have some moral force, Part III explores when lawyers should operate as legal positivists and when they should act as natural lawyers. Part IV tests the above analysis against Bradley Wendel s book, LAWYERS AND FIDELITY TO LAW. Wendel argues both for legal positivism and for the law imposing moral obligations including what Wendel calls the obligation of fidelity to law. 16 Legal dualism holds that those two positions cannot be reconciled. Legal positivism correlates to a purely descriptive or predictive approach to law. When law gives rise to moral obligations when it requires fidelity interpreters must be natural lawyers. So Wendel s book provides a healthy challenge to legal dualism. Part IV argues that Wendel s argument succumbs to the challenge. Legal dualism emerges intact. Wendel, it concludes, must adjust his theory ideally by abandoning legal positivism for interpreters seeking moral guidance from the law. Part V concludes by exploring an additional issue Wendel would have to address were he to accept legal dualism and to defend his modified version of the Standard Conception. He would have to justify lawyers at times making moral judgments in interpreting the law for their clients. That task, it suggests, is the natural result of his argument that lawyers should pursue their clients legal rights, not their interests. I. Defining Legal Positivism and Natural Law Legal dualism presupposes a distinction between natural law and legal positivism, one that depends on the role of morality in legal interpretation. Clarity requires precision in defining these terms. Unfortunately, there is no readily available consensus. 17 Legal positivism derives its name from the notion that law consists of positive norms, that is, norms created by human action. 18 Along these lines, one common approach is to define legal positivism by the Social Facts Thesis and natural law by opposition to that thesis WENDEL, supra note 5, at See, e.g., id. at 122 and the title of his book. 17. See generally Jules Coleman, The Architecture of Jurisprudence, 121 YALE L.J. 2 (2011) (discussing difficulty of defining legal positivism). 18. See, e.g., INTERNET ENCYCLOPEDIA OF PHILOSOPHY, (last visited June 1, 2016). 19. See, e.g., Kenneth Einar Himma, Inclusive Legal Positivism, in THE OXFORD HANDBOOK OF JURISPRUDENCE &PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 126 ( The most fundamental of positivism s core commitments is the Social Facts Thesis, which asserts that law is, in essence, a social creation or artefact. ).

6 6 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER The Social Facts Thesis holds that all legal facts are ultimately determined by social facts alone. 20 Specifying social facts 21 involves only description, not prescription saying what the law is, not what it should be. 22 According to legal positivism, a purely descriptive claim plays the ultimate role in saying what the law is. The words ultimately and ultimate in this context can be taken to mean foundational or fundamental. 23 In other words, the foundation for giving content to the law is descriptive, not prescriptive. And no prescriptive claims are necessary to support that foundation. 24 Theorists often contrast legal positivism with natural law. 25 According to the Social Facts Thesis, natural law claims that the content of the law ultimately de- 20. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 27 & n.27 (citing JULES L. COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRINCIPLE 75 (2001)); JOSEPH RAZ, THE AUTHORITY OF LAW: ESSAYS ON LAW AND MORALITY 37 (1979); Gerald J. Postema, Coordination and Convention at the Foundation of Law, 11J. LEGAL STUD. 165 (1982)). Shapiro calls this proposition the Ultimacy Thesis. Id. at However, although it may be more precise, I find this label less accessible than the Social Facts Thesis, and it is less commonly used. See William A. Edmundson, Shmegality, 2JURISPRUDENCE 273, 273 (2011) (noting the Social Fact Thesis is the standard term). Similarly, Brian Leiter uses the term Social Thesis, BRIAN LEITER, NATURALIZING JURISPRUDENCE: ESSAYS ON AMERICAN LEGAL REALISM AND NATURALISM IN LEGAL PHILOS- OPHY 66 (2007). Wendel appears to adopt the Social Facts Thesis as a definition of legal positivism, at least implicitly: The incorporation of morality into law may be a social fact, in the sense that one can trace the validity of a proposition of law back to its having been relied upon by an official institutional actor, such as a judge or a legislator, as one of the grounds for a legal judgment. If moral truth is irrelevant to legal validity (with validity understood in terms of social sources), then it is irrelevant whether a lawyer believes some interpretation of law would be better, morally speaking. WENDEL, supra note 5, at Shapiro usefully characterizes the relevant social facts as depending on what people think, intend, claim, say, or do. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 27. Further, although he acknowledges controversy about the nature of the relevant social facts, he suggests a plausible understanding of the relevant social facts along the following lines: the fact that legal officials treat the state conventions as having had the power to ratify the Constitution makes it the case that the Constitution is legally binding on them. Id. The most important points for present purposes is that legal positivists claim that legal facts ultimately depend on only social facts and that specifying social facts involves only descriptive claims, not moral claims. 22. See id. 23. Leiter, for example, uses the term fundamental at times in defining what I have called the Social Facts Thesis. See, e.g., LEITER, supra note 20, at 66, Some legal positivists hedge in this regard. Shapiro, for example, attempts to remain agnostic about the nature of social facts themselves and whether they are reducible to other factual claims (e.g., about individual psychology and action) or require recourse to moral facts as well. SHA- PIRO, supra note 3, at 44. It is not clear that this concession is merely marginal, but I will not pursue the point in this Article. 25. Id. at 27. The term natural law is awkward at least as applied to modern theorists, including Lon Fuller and Ronald Dworkin to the extent it could be read to imply some kind of religious commitment. See, e.g., BRIAN H. BIX, JURISPRUDENCE: THEORY AND CONTEXT 67 & n.2

7 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 7 pends at least in part on moral facts, 26 not just on social facts. 27 So, for example, constitutional law is a kind of natural law if the proper way to interpret the Constitution depends ultimately in part on political morality. 28 If, on the other hand, the right way to specify the content of constitutional doctrine ultimately involves recourse only to social facts if the content depends, say, only on prevailing practice then legal positivism provides the best understanding of the nature of constitutional law. 29 Legal positivism, in turn, can take two forms. It can be exclusive or inclusive. 30 Both embrace the Social Facts Thesis. 31 Inclusive legal positivism, however, allows morality to play a role in identifying the content of the law, provided the relevant social facts so permit. 32 Exclusive legal positivism, in contrast, claims that morality plays no role whatsoever in specifying the content of the law. 33 All legal positivists agree that which political actors make authoritative pronouncements regarding the content of the law depends ultimately only on social facts on the conventional practice, for example, in a particular legal system. However, inclusive legal positivists believe those social facts may permit some political actors, including judges, to make non-foundational moral judgments in determining the content of the law, whereas exclusive legal positivists do not. 34 Imagine, for instance, that the relevant social fact again, say prevailing legal practice allows judges to make moral judgments in specifying the content of constitutional doctrine in the United States. As long as the content of the law (5th ed. 2009); Ronald A. Dworkin, Natural Law Revisited, 34 U. FLA. L. REV. 165, 165 (1982). However, I follow other scholars in using the term. 26. I use the term moral facts to be consistent with others. See, e.g.,shapiro, supra note 3, at 27. To say the content of the law depends on moral facts, for my purposes, means merely that moral judgment is necessary to identify the content of the law, not that moral judgment is or can be objectively correct or that moral facts can be identified in a particular way. I do not mean to take a position here about the ontological or epistemological status of morality. For an argument defending the objectivity of moral facts and more generally robust moral realism see DAVID ENOCH,TAKING MORAL- ITY SERIOUSLY (2011); RUSS SHAFER-LANDAU, MORAL REALISM: A DEFENCE (2003). 27. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at Id. at 29. I recognize it is a contested issue whether political morality is a branch of morality. But either way, the statement in the text holds true if the content of the law ultimately depends in part on political morality, it does not depend ultimately only on social facts. 29. Id. 30. See id. at Id. at Two of the most prominent inclusive legal positivists are H.L.A. Hart and Jules Coleman. See, e.g., H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (3d ed. 2012); JULES COLEMAN, THE PRACTICE OF PRIN- CIPLE: IN DEFENCE OF A PRAGMATIST APPROACH TO LEGAL THEORY (2001). 33. To use Shapiro s terminology, all legal positivists are committed to the Ultimacy Thesis, that is, that legal facts are ultimately determined by social facts alone. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 269. Exclusive legal positivists also adhere to the Exclusivity Thesis, that is, that legal facts are determined exclusively by social facts. Id. at 269, See id. at

8 8 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER depends ultimately on only social facts, inclusive legal positivism can account for our legal system. Exclusive legal positivists, however, insist that the content of constitutional law does not depend on moral facts at all. They believe that the content of the law depends on only social facts. 35 Natural law rejects the Social Facts Thesis. It contends that the content of the law does not depend on only social facts. Note the asymmetry. Legal positivism claims that the content of the law depends ultimately on only social facts. But natural law does not entail that the law depends ultimately on only moral facts just that it depends in part on moral facts. A more aggressive natural law position might claim that the content of the law depends ultimately or even entirely on only moral facts. Natural law, in this limited sense, is more modest than legal positivism. 36 There is an alternative way to define legal positivism worth mentioning, one at odds with the Social Facts Thesis. It holds that the law may reflect moral (or normative) judgments at its foundation but only at its foundation. Those moral (or normative) judgments lead to the conclusion that morality (or some other form of normativity) should play no further role in determining the content of the law. Jeremy Waldron has dubbed this approach normative or ethical positivism. 37 It is, in a sense, the inverse of inclusive legal positivism as defined above. Normative positivism allows normative (or moral) values to inform only foundational judgments in defining the law; inclusive legal positivism excludes normative (or moral) values only from those foundational judgments. The goal of this Article is not to choose among these competing approaches to legal positivism. For purposes of clarity, it will generally assume that the Social Facts Thesis defines positivism. And when it addresses normative positivism it will use that term. But note at the outset that one definition of legal positivism appears untenable. It does not seem possible to combine inclusive legal positivism with normative positivism. After all, inclusive legal positivism allows only non-foundational 35. Exclusive legal positivists may have various reasons for reaching this conclusion. Joseph Raz, for example, believes that the authoritative nature of the law requires that it provide exclusionary reasons for complying with its dictates, that is, reasons that preclude a legal interpreter s reconsideration of the normative issues that were resolved in devising the content of the law. See LEITER, supra note 20, at 129 (discussing Raz s authoritative directives). Others rely on an argument about public guidance that the law must be knowable without value judgments for it to provide guidance to the public. See, e.g., SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 302; WENDEL, supra note 5, at 116 ( The claim in this chapter is that law can perform its function as a distinctive mode of governance precisely because of its independence from contested moral considerations. ). 36. If there were symmetry, the view that the content of law depends ultimately in part on social facts and in part on moral facts would fit neither within legal positivism nor within natural law. According to the above definitions, however, such a hybrid view qualifies as natural law. Also, if there were symmetry, one might use the term exclusive natural law for the position that only moral facts give content to the law and the term inclusive natural law for the position that the content of the law depends ultimately only on moral facts, but may depend on interstitial social facts. 37. See Jeremy Waldron, Normative (or Ethical) Positivism, in HART S POSTSCRIPT: ESSAYS ON THE POSTSCRIPT TO THE CONCEPT OF LAW 411 (2001).

9 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 9 normative (or moral) judgments and normative positivism allows only foundational normative (or moral) judgments. Combining the two would seem to permit all normative (or moral) judgments. Little or nothing would then be left to distinguish legal positivism from natural law. 38 So we should reject what one might call inclusive normative legal positivism. With these points in mind, it is possible to offer a more precise account of legal dualism. Recall that legal dualism claims that natural law provides the best account of the nature of law when an interpreter seeks moral guidance from the law and legal positivism provides the best account when an interpreter seeks merely to describe the law or to predict how others will interpret it. What does that mean? If we adopt the Social Facts Thesis: it means that when an interpreter seeks moral guidance from the law, she will have to make ultimate or foundational moral judgments in saying what the law is; in contrast, when she attempts merely to describe the law or to predict how others will interpret it, she can rely ultimately on only social facts. With these definitions in place, we are ready to consider the case for legal dualism. II. A Précis of the Case for Legal Dualism This Article is not the place to develop the full argument for legal dualism. 39 A brief overview of its main points, however, provides a basis for evaluating its implications for legal ethics. That overview begins with crucial challenges for legal positivism and natural law: respectively, Hume s Law 40 and Evil Law. 41 A. Hume s Law and Legal Positivism Hume s Law poses a challenge for legal positivism. It holds that one cannot derive an ought from an is. 42 In other words, descriptive propositions cannot yield prescriptive propositions. 43 For present purposes, Hume s Law bars us from deriving moral obligations from descriptive or predictive claims about the law. Some normative (or moral) proposition must establish the normative (or moral) significance of any descriptive claim. 38. The concern is not idle that the distinction between natural law and legal positivism may dissolve, leaving confusion over what is at stake. Ronald Dworkin, for example, has criticized Jules Coleman s inclusive legal positivism of too closely resembling Dworkin s non-positivist theory. RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE IN ROBES (2006) (discussing Pickwickian Positivism ). 39. For an initial effort to undertake that task in response to Scott Shapiro s excellent book, LEGALITY (2011), see Davis, supra note 14. For a similar initial effort in response to Brian Leiter s reworking of Legal Realism in naturalistic terms see Manuel Vargas & Joshua P. Davis, American Legal Realism and Practical Guidance, in REASONS AND INTENTIONS IN LAW AND PRACTICAL AGENCY 267 (2015). 40. DAVID HUME, A TREATISE ON HUMAN NATURE, bk. 3, pt. I, sec. I ( ). 41. A germinal development of this argument can be found in Hart, supra note 14, at See, e.g., RONALD DWORKIN, JUSTICE FOR HEDGEHOGS 17 (2011) (referring to Hume s principle rather than Hume s Law). 43. Id. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 47.

10 10 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER So, for example, one might say that Jim killed Bob. That descriptive claim, by itself, does not establish any moral proposition. Some additional prescriptive claim would be necessary to conclude that Jim acted immorally. One would need to know that killing is immoral or that it is immoral under some circumstances. That moral proposition would then determine which other descriptive claims are relevant to a moral conclusion, such as whether Jim killed Bob deliberately or whether he acted in self-defense. Legal positivists have recognized the challenge that Hume s Law poses for them. Scott Shapiro, for example, accepts Hume s Law. 44 He also acknowledges that the law includes propositions about what those subject to it should do. 45 He suggests, however, that whether the law in fact imposes moral obligations rather than merely purports to do so is an independent moral question, one that does not require consideration of morality in saying what the law is. 46 According to Shapiro, one can determine the entire massive and elaborate structure of the law without any inquiry into morality. That structure may be framed in terms of obligations. But one should separately assess whether the structure or any part of it in fact imposes moral obligations to act or not to act in a particular manner. Shapiro s approach could succeed in theory. One could imagine interpreters disentangling descriptive claims about the content of the law from moral claims about the content of the law, and then separately asking whether the law has any moral (or normative) force. Shapiro s solution, however, gives rise to serious difficulties in practice. A primary source of difficulties is pervasive indeterminacy in the law, at least in complex legal systems like the one in the United States. 47 That indeterminacy occurs at a foundational level in answering foundational questions about what the ultimate sources of law are and how they should be interpreted as well as in making non-foundational call them interstitial judgments, such as how to address apparent gaps or inconsistencies in the law. Legal indeterminacy triggers Hume s Law. When the law is susceptible to more than one interpretation, how ought an interpreter to choose among them? i. Foundational Indeterminacy The issue of foundational indeterminacy can take the form of the problem of theoretical disagreements, a label that Shapiro applies to an argument made by 44. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 48-49, 188. Jules Coleman has identified the challenge of Hume s Law as well. See Jules Coleman, supra note 17, at (2011). 45. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at Id. at Legal positivists generally acknowledge the indeterminacy of the law. See, e.g., HART, supra note 32, at ; SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 256; WENDEL, supra note 5, at It is unclear whether they would argue that the law is sufficiently determinate to support legal positivism. Wendel does seem to suggest the law yields determinate answers with some frequency, but see infra Part IV.B.i for an argument that Wendel s own examples of legal interpretation require moral judgments to produce determinate results.

11 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 11 Ronald Dworkin. 48 Theoretical disagreements arise when legal interpreters have different views about which social facts are relevant to legal interpretation. 49 Consider the issue of whether the death penalty constitutes cruel and unusual punishment as proscribed by the Eighth Amendment. 50 Legal interpreters within our legal system may disagree on this issue at various levels of generality, inter alia, about the relevant views of the Framers or of the citizenry at the time of adoption of the Bill of Rights, about whether the death penalty is cruel and unusual under a contemporary understanding of those terms, about whether the original understanding or the modern understanding should govern constitutional interpretation, and about the grounds for choosing between those and other potential interpretive methodologies. Some of these disagreements may turn merely on social facts for example, what the views of the founders were 51 but others arise over which social facts matter to legal interpretation. Indeed, theoretical disagreements about the nature of the law contribute to foundational indeterminacy. That is because the controversy that permeates any effort to identify the content of the law includes legal theory itself. Exclusive legal positivists, for example, often view recourse to social facts alone as the best and only proper means of addressing metainterpretive questions questions about the proper method of interpretation. 52 Natural lawyers, in contrast, may claim there is no alternative but to base legal interpretation in part on morality. 53 This disagreement runs to the extremes of generality. Scott Shapiro s ultimate philosophical methodology, for example, appears to eschew moral judgment. 54 Ronald Dworkin, in contrast, claims legal interpretation is a branch of political morality and, ultimately, a branch of morality. 55 A reasonably determinate description of the law would depend on some resolution if only implicit of these foundational disputes. How should an interpreter resolve them? The question 48. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at Dworkin makes the argument, inter alia, in RONALD DWORKIN, LAW S EMPIRE 45 (1986). 49. See SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at Id. at But note that this issue gives rise to various others. Which founders? How should we aggregate their views? Should we consider the concepts they adopted in abstract terms (as they often were expressed when codified) or as they thought they would be applied? See RONALD DWORKIN, A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE (1985) ( The Forum of Principle ). 52. See, e.g., SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 345. Raz is a possible exception his approach seems to be that theory need not inform legal practice, a questionable position. See Joshua P. Davis, Jurisprudential Jujutsu, at 7 n. 30 (2012), available at abstract_id= Wendel does not assert this argument. 53. See, e.g., DWORKIN, supra note 42, at Shapiro questions whether morality can inform our understanding of the nature of law. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at See, e.g., DWORKIN, supra note 42, at 405.

12 12 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER is normative. Given that the law is a political institution, answering the question would seem to require judgments about political morality. 56 The debate between Justice Scalia and Ronald Dworkin is instructive in this regard. Justice Scalia was the most renowned recent sitting judge to champion legal positivism. Yet his ultimate justification for his criticism of what he calls the Living Constitution 57 his criticism of interpreting the Constitution as changing over time with society s values 58 sounded in political morality. He argued, for example, that the Bill of Rights should protect unpopular minorities, 59 that licensing judges to base their views of constitutional rights on morality has injected politics into the process for selecting judges, 60 and that the Living Constitution leads to a degradation of genuinely unpopular minority rights... notably, rights of criminal defendants and prisoners. 61 Dworkin responded in two key ways to Scalia: first, arguing that a moral reading of the Constitution will enhance not undermine the most important individual rights; 62 and, second, observing that Justice Scalia relied an argument about political morality about the best understanding of democracy and the best way to protect individual rights within a democracy to support his position. 63 In reply, Scalia addressed the first point squarely, predicting that, as a result of our embrace of a Living Constitution, for individual rights disfavored by the majority... there are hard times ahead. 64 However, he did not contest indeed, 56. See, e.g., id. at ; Scott Hershovitz, The End of Jurisprudence, 124 YALE L.J (2015) (arguing legal obligations are a subset of moral obligations); Mark Greenberg, The Moral Impact Theory of Law, 123 YALE L.J (2014) (same). Support for this suggestion comes from an interesting place, the renowned legal positivist, H.L.A. Hart. He wrote about interpretation when the law is unclear: What is it then that makes such decisions correct or at least better than alternative decisions? Again, it seems true to say that the criterion which makes a decision sound in such cases is some concept of what law ought to be; it is easy to slide from that into saying that it must be a moral judgment about what the law ought to be. Hart, supra note 14, at 608. Hart resists this conclusion primarily by arguing that the aims of the law can be evil. Id. at 613; see also id. at 601, 613. His response may well succeed if one assumes law has the same nature for all purposes. But if one relaxes that assumption and limits the analysis to when the law has moral legitimacy, Hart s response no longer appears persuasive. Morally legitimate law would seem to serve moral purposes and recourse to those purposes would be expected to implicate moral judgments, as Hart seemed to recognize. 57. ANTONIN SCALIA, AMATTER OF INTERPRETATION: FEDERAL COURTS AND THE LAW 44 (1997) [hereinafter A MATTER OF INTERPRETATION ]. 58. Id. at 40, Id. at Id. at 46-47, Id. at 149 (emphasis in original). 62. See Dworkin, Comment, in AMATTER OF INTERPRETATION, supra note 57, at Id. at Id. at 149.

13 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 13 his rejoinder seemed to concede that the debate ultimately turns in part on a judgment about political morality. 65 Justice Scalia thus abandoned the Social Fact Thesis. Judgments about political morality informed his view of the content of the law, even if those judgments operate only at the level of foundational theory. 66 To be sure, he preferred to make his moral judgments as a predicate to his interpretive theory and not otherwise. But his view was premised on moral judgments nonetheless. So if Scalia qualified as a positivist, he would appear to have been a normative positivist. 67 As confirmation, consider a major issue recently addressed by the Supreme Court: same-sex marriage. 68 The Court held in Obergefell v. Hodges that there is a right to marry that extends to same-sex couples. 69 Justice Scalia made clear the nature of his objection to the majority s ruling: [I]t is not of special importance to me what the law says about marriage. It is of overwhelming importance, however, who it is that rules me. Today s decree says that my Ruler, and the Ruler of 320 million Americans coast-to-coast, is a majority of nine lawyers on the Supreme Court. The opinion in these cases is the furthest extension in fact and the furthest extension one can even imagine of the Court s claimed power to create liberties that the Constitution and its Amendments neglect to mention. This practice of constitutional revision by an unelected committee of nine, always accompanied (as it is today) by extravagant praise of liberty, robs the People of the most important liberty they asserted in the Declaration of Independence and won in the Revolution of 1776: the freedom to govern themselves. 70 Justice Scalia s opinion continues by explaining albeit in abbreviated form why the Supreme Court serves as a poor representative of the people when the Justices act on their policy views as opposed to their skills as lawyers. 71 Others can and do disagree. An example is Christopher Eisgruber s trenchant argument that members of the Supreme Court promote democratic selfgovernment at times by making judgments about moral principles Id. 66. I mean to take no position here on whether Justice Scalia in fact makes interstitial moral judgments in interpreting the law. 67. Note that this characterization of Scalia s judicial philosophy, if accurate, could spell trouble for some positivists. Shapiro, for example, seems sympathetic to Scalia s meta-interpretive theory, see, e.g., SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at , one that the text argues is not in fact consistent with positivism as defined in this Article and by Shapiro. See supra notes and accompanying text. 68. Obergefell v. Hodges, 576 U.S., 135 S. Ct (2015). 69. Id. 70. Id. at 2627 ( Justice Scalia, dissenting). 71. Id. at CHRISTOPHER EISGRUBER, CONSTITUTIONAL SELF-GOVERNMENT (2001). See also JEFFREY ROSEN, THE MOST DEMOCRATIC BRANCH: HOW THE COURTS SERVE AMERICA (2006) (arguing courts

14 14 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER But what matters for present purposes is not whether Justice Scalia or Professor Eisgruber is more persuasive. The key point is that their disagreement turns on judgments about political morality including about the extent to which democracy can be equated with majoritarianism as expressed of elected officials. In other words, they disagree about foundational issues of political morality essential to determining the content of the law. And they agree, at least implicitly, that interpreters must take into account political morality in resolving those foundational issues. Scalia s attack on the majority in Obergefell sounds in political theory. ii. Interstitial Indeterminacy But foundational moral judgments are unlikely to be sufficient by themselves to yield the degree of determinacy necessary for the law to serve as a source of moral guidance. There are pervasive points of disagreement in legal interpretation, many of which occur at lower levels of generality. These are instances of interstitial indeterminacy that is, locations of ambiguity, inconsistency, or opacity within any descriptive or predictive account of the law. 73 Even if interpreters agree on foundational issues such as what the ultimate sources of law are and how they should be interpreted they will sometimes disagree about more concrete matters, such as which of several apparently inconsistent legal rules apply in a case and, if more than one does, which one should govern. Modern legal positivists tend to acknowledge even to assert that such indeterminacy exists. 74 In resolving these issues, it would be natural for judges to take into account an amalgam of value judgments, policy considerations, predicted consequences, ascribed purposes of the law, and the like. 75 at times are more responsive to popular will than elected branches of government). Arguments along these lines often focus on two points: the Supreme Court is more reflective of popular will than many assume (elected representatives appoint and confirm justices and justices are responsive to the views of citizens, particularly about underlying moral and political principles) and other branches of government are less reflective of popular will than many assume (those holding elected office are in many ways not responsive to citizens). They also often make arguments about the meaning of democracy as reflecting deep commitments to moral values other than just majority rule. See, e.g., RONALD DWORKIN, FREEDOM S LAW 1-35 (1996). 73. Any indeterminacy should be susceptible to categorization as either interstitial or foundational. Little depends for the present argument on whether these categories are distinct or overlapping, although that might matter in deciding whether inclusive legal positivism or normative positivism can provide an adequate account of the law. Inclusive legal positivism can tolerate the use of moral judgment to eliminate interstitial indeterminacy but not foundational indeterminacy; the converse is true for normative positivism. 74. See HART, supra note 32, at ; id. at ( Postscript ) (noting and expanding on the sources of indeterminacy in the law); SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at 256; WENDEL, supra note 5, at How much indeterminacy there is and how to frame claims about degrees of indeterminacy are matters of some dispute. See WENDEL, supra note 5, at See also infra Part IV.B and accompanying text disputing whether the law is as determinate as Wendel claims it sometimes is. 75. BENJAMIN N. CARDOZO, THE NATURE OF THE JUDICIAL PROCESS 9-13, (1921) (noting the numerous influences on legal interpretation).

15 LEGAL DUALISM, LEGAL ETHICS, AND FIDELITY TO LAW 15 In turn, these concrete issues ineluctably implicate more general ones, for political morality will inform arguments both about whether moral judgments should be used to resolve indeterminacy in the law and about when moral judgments should play that role. Should judges tolerate relatively unjust or counterintuitive results so as to minimize the discretion they may yield? That question is difficult to answer without taking recourse to more general or abstract moral judgments. Legal interpreters disagree on these points. There is no purely descriptive analysis no non-normative fact-of-the-matter that can resolve them. In this regard, consider another recent Supreme Court decision, King v. Burwell. 76 At issue was the availability of tax subsidies under the Affordable Care Act. The Act confers tax subsidies on taxpayers who enroll in an insurance plan through an Exchange established by the State. 77 The parties disagreed about whether an Exchange is established by the State if a State uses an exchange created by the federal government. 78 One way to understand the justices different views on this issue is as turning on relatively narrow judgments of fact, e.g., whether the key phrase in the statute is ambiguous and whether it is at odds with the purposes of the statute. 79 But those views also seem to mix fact and value, such as about how ambiguous the text of a statute needs to be and how at odds with the statute s purposes for a court to put aside the most natural sense 80 of the text and to rely instead on the context and structure of the statute. 81 As Justice Scalia s dissent makes clear, those issues in turn depend on judgments about political morality, including how much power the courts do and should have to clarify or correct a law that may have been drafted with insufficient care and deliberation. 82 Justice Scalia may well be right when he pronounces, It is up to Congress to design its laws with care, and it is up to the people to hold them to account if they fail to carry out that responsibility. 83 If he is, however, he is not self-evidently right. Perhaps courts should play an active role in assisting legislatures to achieve the ends they intend. 84 Or perhaps, as Justice Scalia contends, courts should exercise restraint, forcing legislatures to take care 76. King v. Burwell, 135 S. Ct (2015). 77. Id. at Id. 79. Compare id. at 2491 (holding the statute is ambiguous) and (holding that denying state use of a federal exchange is an exchange established by the state would be antithetical to the purpose of the statute), with id. at 2497 (Scalia, J., dissenting) (arguing the statute is unambiguous), and id. at (arguing the structure of the statute is consistent with concluding a federal exchange is not an exchange established by the state). 80. Id. at 2490 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 81. Id.; id. at 2497 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 82. Id. at 2495; id. at 2497 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 83. Id. at 2506 (Scalia, J., dissenting). 84. See, e.g., William Eskridge, Dynamic Statutory Interpretation, 135 U. PENN.L.REV (1987).

16 16 JOURNAL OF THE PROFESSIONAL LAWYER or live with the consequences. In either case, Justice Scalia s argument relies in part, again, on equating majoritarianism with democracy and, again, that is a contestable position that depends on judgments about political morality. 85 Hume s Law, then, poses a problem for legal positivism when a legal interpreter seeks moral guidance from the law. Foundational and interstitial moral judgments may be necessary to render the law sufficiently determinate to guide conduct. And those moral judgments, according to Hume s Law, must derive from an ought, not an is. A comparable issue confronts natural law. B. Evil Law and Natural Law Just as Hume s Law poses a problem for legal positivism, Evil Law poses one for natural law. 86 Natural lawyers claim that determining the content of the law at times requires recourse to moral facts. 87 But it is hard to see what role moral facts could play in an evil legal system, one that serves nefarious ends. Consider the law of Nazi Germany. 88 What role could morality play in a legal system that is so morally bankrupt? Yet Nazi law appears to qualify as law. 89 Many consider this critique the most formidable one of natural law. Note in this regard Thomas Nagel s summary in the New York Review of Books of the life work of his longtime colleague and renowned natural lawyer, Ronald Dworkin. 90 Nagel s largely sympathetic account of Dworkin s view included a note of skepticism about the position he ascribed to Dworkin that morality always informs what the law is: If one thinks of the American legal system before the Civil War, with its constitutionally protected compromises over slavery, it seems strained to understand the truth about what the law was as part of morality what was morally required or permitted in light of the morally best overall justification of the existing institutions, laws, and precedents. Looking at it from our external perspective, a positivist reading 85. See supra Part II.A.i. 86. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at This is arguably Hart s central and most persuasive point in Hart, supra note 14, at Shapiro treats this point as definitional of natural lawyers. Id. at 27. He attributes the natural law position, so defined, to Ronald Dworkin, among others. Id. at 27 n.28. He does note an alternative natural law position holding merely that immoral or unreasonable laws are defective as laws. Id. (citing Mark C. Murphy, Natural Law Jurisprudence, 9 LEGAL THEORY 241, 254 (2003)). 88. Lon L. Fuller and H.L.A. Hart address the puzzle of Nazi law in their famous debate. See Lon L. Fuller, Positivism and Fidelity to Law A Reply to Professor Hart, 71 HARV. L. REV. 630, 633 (1958); Hart, supra note 14, at Additionally, Shapiro offers the law of the Soviet Union as an example. SHAPIRO, supra note 3, at Hart, supra note 14, at Although Dworkin did not generally embrace the label natural lawyer, he seemed to acknowledge that he qualified as one given the standard terms used in jurisprudence. See Ronald Dworkin, Natural Law Revisited, 34 FL. L. REV. 165, 165 (1982) ( If the crude description of natural law I just gave is correct, that any theory which makes the content of law sometimes depend on the correct answer to some moral question is a natural law theory, then I am guilty of natural law. ).

Legality, Morality, Duality

Legality, Morality, Duality Utah Law Review Volume 2014 Number 1 Article 2 2014 Legality, Morality, Duality Joshua P. Davis Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.law.utah.edu/ulr Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons Recommended

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Rethinking Legal Positivism. Jules L. Coleman Yale University. Introduction

Rethinking Legal Positivism. Jules L. Coleman Yale University. Introduction Dear Participants in the USC Workshop The following is a 'drafty' paper -- a term I use intentionally to convey a double meaning: it outlines a large research project and provides the outlines of a full

More information

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM

PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM PROFESSOR HARTS CONCEPT OF LAW SUBAS H. MAHTO LEGAL THEORY F.Y.LLM 1 INDEX Page Nos. 1) Chapter 1 Introduction 3 2) Chapter 2 Harts Concept 5 3) Chapter 3 Rule of Recognition 6 4) Chapter 4 Harts View

More information

The Architecture of Jurisprudence

The Architecture of Jurisprudence 02.COLEMAN.80.DOC 10/12/2011 5:05:47 PM Jules L. Coleman The Architecture of Jurisprudence abstract. Contemporary jurisprudence has been dominated by an unhelpful interest in taxonomy. A conventional wisdom

More information

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution.

Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. Freedom's Law: The Moral Reading of the American Constitution. By Ronald Dworkin. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996.389 pp. Kenneth Einar Himma University of Washington In Freedom's Law, Ronald

More information

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.

-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text. Citation: 21 Isr. L. Rev. 113 1986 Content downloaded/printed from HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org) Sun Jan 11 12:34:09 2015 -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's

More information

Beyond the Separability Thesis: Moral Semantics and the Methodology of Jurisprudence

Beyond the Separability Thesis: Moral Semantics and the Methodology of Jurisprudence Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Vol. 27, No. 4 (2007), pp. 581 608 doi:10.1093/ojls/gqm014 Beyond the Separability Thesis: Moral Semantics and the Methodology of Jurisprudence JULES L COLEMAN* Abstract

More information

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral (forthcoming in the OXFORD JOURNAL OF LEGAL STUDIES) Andrei Marmor USC Legal Studies Research Paper No. 05-16 LEGAL STUDIES RESEARCH PAPER SERIES

More information

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law

Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law The Catholic Lawyer Volume 26 Number 2 Volume 26, Spring 1981, Number 2 Article 4 September 2017 Kelsen's Pure Theory of Law Henry Cohen Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl

More information

HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW

HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW HART ON SOCIAL RULES AND THE FOUNDATIONS OF LAW: LIBERATING THE INTERNAL POINT OF VIEW Stephen Perry* INTRODUCTION The internal point of view is a crucial element in H.L.A. Hart s theory of law. Hart first

More information

Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral

Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral Cornell University Law School Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository Cornell Law Faculty Publications Faculty Scholarship Winter 2006 Legal Positivism: Still Descriptive and Morally Neutral Andrei

More information

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE

SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE SANDEL ON RELIGION IN THE PUBLIC SQUARE Hugh Baxter For Boston University School of Law s Conference on Michael Sandel s Justice October 14, 2010 In the final chapter of Justice, Sandel calls for a new

More information

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true.

Legal Positivism: the Separation and Identification theses are true. PHL271 Handout 3: Hart on Legal Positivism 1 Legal Positivism Revisited HLA Hart was a highly sophisticated philosopher. His defence of legal positivism marked a watershed in 20 th Century philosophy of

More information

Social Rules and Legal Theory

Social Rules and Legal Theory Yale Law Journal Volume 81 Issue 5 Yale Law Journal Article 3 1972 Social Rules and Legal Theory Ronald M. Dworkin Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.yale.edu/ylj Recommended

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid?

Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? University of Birmingham Birmingham Law School Jurisprudence 2007-08 Assessed Essay (Second Round) Does law have to be effective in order for it to be valid? It is important to consider the terms valid

More information

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb

Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi pp, hb Brian Leiter (ed), Objectivity in Law and Morals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, xi + 354 pp, hb 42.50. Legal philosophy since the 1960s has been gradually moving away from discussion of

More information

Book Review: Justice in Robes by Ronald Dworkin (2006)

Book Review: Justice in Robes by Ronald Dworkin (2006) Osgoode Hall Law School of York University Osgoode Digital Commons All Papers Research Papers, Working Papers, Conference Papers 2-11-2008 Book Review: Justice in Robes by Ronald Dworkin (2006) Dan Priel

More information

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that

Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that Legal Positivism A N I NTRODUCTION Polycarp Ikuenobe Legal positivism represents a view about the nature of law. It states that there is no necessary or conceptual connection between law and morality and

More information

McCOUBREY & WHITE S TEXTBOOK ON JURISPRUDENCE

McCOUBREY & WHITE S TEXTBOOK ON JURISPRUDENCE THE DENNING LAW JOURNAL The Denning Law Journal 2009 Vol 21 pp 183-188 BOOK REVIEW McCOUBREY & WHITE S TEXTBOOK ON JURISPRUDENCE J E Penner, 4 th edn (Oxford: Oxford University Press 2008) ISBN 9781847030221

More information

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal

Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge Gracia's proposal University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2016 Mar 12th, 1:30 PM - 2:00 PM Conditions of Fundamental Metaphysics: A critique of Jorge

More information

FACULTY OF LAW UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW 300 JURISPRUDENCE AND CRITICAL PERSPECTIVES. Fall 2015

FACULTY OF LAW UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW 300 JURISPRUDENCE AND CRITICAL PERSPECTIVES. Fall 2015 FACULTY OF LAW UNIVERSITY OF BRITISH COLUMBIA LAW 300 JURISPRUDENCE AND CRITICAL PERSPECTIVES Fall 2015 Professor Benjamin J Goold Office: Allard Hall, Room 455 Phone: (604) 822-9255 E-mail: goold@allard.ubc.ca

More information

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism

Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Comment on Martha Nussbaum s Purified Patriotism Patriotism is generally thought to require a special attachment to the particular: to one s own country and to one s fellow citizens. It is therefore thought

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law

Law and Authority. An unjust law is not a law Law and Authority An unjust law is not a law The statement an unjust law is not a law is often treated as a summary of how natural law theorists approach the question of whether a law is valid or not.

More information

1. The basic idea is to look at "what the courts do in fact" (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean?

1. The basic idea is to look at what the courts do in fact (Holmes, 1897). What does this mean? Contemporary Anglo-American Jurisprudence - Important to remember that these are not just movements, they are ideas, ideas or perspectives on the law which are simultaneously alive in the law today. I.

More information

Why Legal Positivism?

Why Legal Positivism? University of Chicago Law School Chicago Unbound Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers Working Papers 2009 Why Legal Positivism? Brian Leiter Follow this and additional works at: http://chicagounbound.uchicago.edu/

More information

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon

PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon PROVOCATION EVERYONE IS A PHILOSOPHER! T.M. Scanlon In the first chapter of his book, Reading Obama, 1 Professor James Kloppenberg offers an account of the intellectual climate at Harvard Law School during

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE

JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE JUDICIAL ENFORCEMENT OF THE ESTABLISHMENT CLAUSE Richard W. Garnett* There is-no surprise!-nothing doctrinaire, rigid, or formulaic about Kent Greenawalt's study of the establishment clause. He works with

More information

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism.

PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority. Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. PHL271 Handout 2: Hobbes on Law and Political Authority 1 Background: Legal Positivism Many philosophers of law treat Hobbes as the grandfather of legal positivism. Legal Positivism (Rough Version): whether

More information

A Very Short Essay on Mormonism and Natural Law. by The Lawyer. I was recently talking with a friend of mine at Harvard Law School who describes

A Very Short Essay on Mormonism and Natural Law. by The Lawyer. I was recently talking with a friend of mine at Harvard Law School who describes A Very Short Essay on Mormonism and Natural Law by The Lawyer I was recently talking with a friend of mine at Harvard Law School who describes himself as an ex-mormon. He left the church in his teens,

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition

Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition Dworkin on the Rufie of Recognition NANCY SNOW University of Notre Dame In the "Model of Rules I," Ronald Dworkin criticizes legal positivism, especially as articulated in the work of H. L. A. Hart, and

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

University of Southern California Law School

University of Southern California Law School University of Southern California Law School Legal Studies Working Paper Series Year 2010 Paper 66 The Dilemma of Authority Andrei Marmor amarmor@law.usc.edu This working paper is hosted by The Berkeley

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1

Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1 THE STANDARD PICTURE AND ITS DISCONTENTS Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1 This paper is a rough and preliminary work in progress and is largely without citations. I would be grateful for comments of any sort. Please

More information

The Rule of Law Means Literally What it Says: The Rule of the Law : Fuller and Raz on Formal Legality and the Concept of Law+

The Rule of Law Means Literally What it Says: The Rule of the Law : Fuller and Raz on Formal Legality and the Concept of Law+ The Rule of Law Means Literally What it Says: The Rule of the Law : Fuller and Raz on Formal Legality and the Concept of Law+ MARK BENNETT* I. Introduction The rule of law means literally what it says:

More information

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian?

Seth Mayer. Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Seth Mayer Comments on Christopher McCammon s Is Liberal Legitimacy Utopian? Christopher McCammon s defense of Liberal Legitimacy hopes to give a negative answer to the question posed by the title of his

More information

Introduction. Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy

Introduction. Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy Introduction Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy 0.1 The Central Claims of Natural Law Jurisprudence and Natural Law Political Philosophy The central claim of natural law jurisprudence

More information

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems

HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Philosophical Explorations, Vol. 10, No. 1, March 2007 HABERMAS ON COMPATIBILISM AND ONTOLOGICAL MONISM Some problems Michael Quante In a first step, I disentangle the issues of scientism and of compatiblism

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

New Federal Initiatives Project

New Federal Initiatives Project New Federal Initiatives Project Does the Establishment Clause Require Broad Restrictions on Religious Expression as Recommended by President Obama s Faith- Based Advisory Council? By Stuart J. Lark* May

More information

PHIL425: Philosophy of Law MW 9:30-10:45; WAL392

PHIL425: Philosophy of Law MW 9:30-10:45; WAL392 PHIL425: Philosophy of Law MW 9:30-10:45; WAL392 Professor: Mark Murphy Office: 202-687-4521 Office: 235 New North Home: 703-437-4561 Office Hours: M 11-12, W 12:30-1:30, and by appointment Course description

More information

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS

THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS Brigham Young University BYU ScholarsArchive All Faculty Publications 1986-11-28 THE SEPARATION OF LAW AND MORALS Noel B. Reynolds Brigham Young University - Provo, nbr@byu.edu Follow this and additional

More information

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is:

We recommend you cite the published version. The publisher s URL is: Cole, P. (2014) Reactions & Debate II: The Ethics of Immigration - Carens and the problem of method. Ethical Perspectives, 21 (4). pp. 600-607. ISSN 1370-0049 Available from: http://eprints.uwe.ac.uk/27941

More information

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self Stephan Torre 1 Neil Feit. Belief about the Self. Oxford GB: Oxford University Press 2008. 216 pages. Belief about the Self is a clearly written, engaging

More information

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax:

90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado Telephone: Fax: 90 South Cascade Avenue, Suite 1500, Colorado Springs, Colorado 80903-1639 Telephone: 719.475.2440 Fax: 719.635.4576 www.shermanhoward.com MEMORANDUM TO: FROM: Ministry and Church Organization Clients

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005

MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 1 MILL ON JUSTICE: CHAPTER 5 of UTILITARIANISM Lecture Notes Dick Arneson Philosophy 13 Fall, 2005 Some people hold that utilitarianism is incompatible with justice and objectionable for that reason. Utilitarianism

More information

Originalism, the Why and the What

Originalism, the Why and the What Fordham Law Review Volume 82 Issue 2 Article 6 2013 Originalism, the Why and the What Larry Alexander University of San Diego Recommended Citation Larry Alexander, Originalism, the Why and the What, 82

More information

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January

A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January A lonelier contractualism A. J. Julius, UCLA, January 15 2008 1. A definition A theory of some normative domain is contractualist if, having said what it is for a person to accept a principle in that domain,

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation

Louisiana Law Review. Cheney C. Joseph Jr. Louisiana State University Law Center. Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue Repository Citation Louisiana Law Review Volume 35 Number 5 Special Issue 1975 ON GUILT, RESPONSIBILITY AND PUNISHMENT. By Alf Ross. Translated from Danish by Alastair Hannay and Thomas E. Sheahan. London, Stevens and Sons

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas

Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Phenomenal Knowledge, Dualism, and Dreams Jesse Butler, University of Central Arkansas Dwight Holbrook (2015b) expresses misgivings that phenomenal knowledge can be regarded as both an objectless kind

More information

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Disaggregating Structures as an Agenda for Critical Realism: A Reply to McAnulla Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4k27s891 Journal British

More information

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel

A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel A Case against Subjectivism: A Reply to Sobel Abstract Subjectivists are committed to the claim that desires provide us with reasons for action. Derek Parfit argues that subjectivists cannot account for

More information

The Nature of the Judicial Process and Judicial Discretion

The Nature of the Judicial Process and Judicial Discretion William Mitchell Law Review Volume 7 Issue 3 Article 1 1981 The Nature of the Judicial Process and Judicial Discretion Russell F. Pannier Follow this and additional works at: http://open.mitchellhamline.edu/wmlr

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

Philosophy of Law Summer Session II, 2016

Philosophy of Law Summer Session II, 2016 Philosophy of Law Summer Session II, 2016 Mon-Thurs. 11:30am 1:05pm 5 Washington Place, Room 202 Instructor: Chelsea Rosenthal Office 414, Department of Philosophy 5 Washington Place cwr225@nyu.edu office

More information

HOW (AND IF) LAW MATTERS

HOW (AND IF) LAW MATTERS HOW (AND IF) LAW MATTERS Frederick Schauer Mark Greenberg s deep and thoughtful review of The Force of Law 1 flatters me in two ways. Of minimal importance is Greenberg s generous appraisal of the book

More information

How To Think About Law as Morality: A Comment on Greenberg and Hershovitz

How To Think About Law as Morality: A Comment on Greenberg and Hershovitz THE YALE LAW JOURNAL FORUM J ANUARY 20, 2015 How To Think About Law as Morality: A Comment on Greenberg and Hershovitz Steven Schaus introduction In philosophy, we can sometimes hope to make progress just

More information

How Facts Make Law. Mark Greenberg* I. Introduction

How Facts Make Law. Mark Greenberg* I. Introduction I I 10 How Facts Make Law Mark Greenberg* I. Introduction Nearly all philosophers of law agree that non-normative, non-evaluative, contingent facts-descriptive facts, for short-are among the determinants

More information

EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15

EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15 EUI Working Papers MWP 2007/15 Authority, Arbitration and the Claims of the Law Lars Vinx EUROPEAN UNIVERSITY INSTITUTE MAX WEBER PROGRAMME Authority, Arbitration and the Claims of the Law LARS VINX EUI

More information

The End of Jurisprudence

The End of Jurisprudence 124 YALE L.J. (forthcoming 2015) S COTT H ERSHOVITZ * For more than forty years, jurisprudence has been dominated by the Hart-Dworkin debate. The terrain of the debate has shifted several times, but it

More information

Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client

Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client Maurice A. Deane School of Law at Hofstra University Scholarly Commons at Hofstra Law Hofstra Law Faculty Scholarship 1987 Legal Ethics and the Suffering Client Monroe H. Freedman Maurice A. Deane School

More information

Law, Obligation, and a Good Faith Claim of Justice

Law, Obligation, and a Good Faith Claim of Justice California Law Review Volume 73 Issue 6 Article 6 December 1985 Law, Obligation, and a Good Faith Claim of Justice Steven J. Burton Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.berkeley.edu/californialawreview

More information

LEGAL THEORY / JURISPRUDENCE MODEL EXAM

LEGAL THEORY / JURISPRUDENCE MODEL EXAM LEGAL THEORY / JURISPRUDENCE MODEL EXAM LAWSKOOL UK IRAC method of completing exams Issues Rules Application Conclusion - Outline the issues that you are going to discuss. - Define the legal rules that

More information

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames

HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames Brigham Young University BYU ScholarsArchive All Faculty Publications 1986-05-08 HUME AND HIS CRITICS: Reid and Kames Noel B. Reynolds Brigham Young University - Provo, nbr@byu.edu Follow this and additional

More information

SARI KISILEVSKY. wholly explained by social facts. Orthodox natural law challenges this position: a rule is

SARI KISILEVSKY. wholly explained by social facts. Orthodox natural law challenges this position: a rule is Draft Copy DWORKIN S CHALLENGE SARI KISILEVSKY 0. Introduction Legal positivism is the view that legal validity, or the binding force of legal rules, can be wholly explained by social facts. Orthodox natural

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

Bowring, B. Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas."

Bowring, B. Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas. Birkbeck eprints: an open access repository of the research output of Birkbeck College http://eprints.bbk.ac.uk Review: Malcolm D. Evans Manual on the Wearing of Religious Symbols in Public Areas." Security

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum

The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction By: VV.AA., Richard BALEY (Ed.) London: Continuum John TILLSON II Época, Nº 6 (2011):185-190 185 The Philosophy of Education. An Introduction 1.

More information

Part II: The Nature of Law and Natural Law

Part II: The Nature of Law and Natural Law Part II: The Nature of Law and Natural Law 3: LEGAL POSITIVISM AND THE SOURCES OF LAW * 1. THE NATURE OF LEGAL POSITIVISM The perennial and inexhaustible nature of the controversy concerning the positivist

More information

Chapter 1. Morality, Tolerance, and Law

Chapter 1. Morality, Tolerance, and Law Chapter 1 Morality, Tolerance, and Law What rights do we have and how do we know that we have them? As the idea of universal human rights gains momentum in the post cold war era, interest in this question

More information

What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age

What is the Social in Social Coherence? Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious Freedom in an Egalitarian Age Journal of Civil Rights and Economic Development Volume 31 Issue 1 Volume 31, Summer 2018, Issue 1 Article 5 June 2018 What is the "Social" in "Social Coherence?" Commentary on Nelson Tebbe's Religious

More information

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING

JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING JUDICIAL OPINION WRITING What's an Opinion For? James Boyd Whitet The question the papers in this Special Issue address is whether it matters how judicial opinions are written, and if so why. My hope here

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review

Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Digital Commons at Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Law Reviews 3-1-2007 Introduction Robin Bradley Kar

More information

The ontology of human rights and obligations

The ontology of human rights and obligations The ontology of human rights and obligations Åsa Burman Department of Philosophy, Stockholm University asa.burman@philosophy.su.se If we are going to make sense of the notion of rights we have to answer

More information

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections I. Introduction

Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections  I. Introduction Compromise and Toleration: Some Reflections Christian F. Rostbøll Paper for Årsmøde i Dansk Selskab for Statskundskab, 29-30 Oct. 2015. Kolding. (The following is not a finished paper but some preliminary

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, The Negative Role of Empirical Stimulus in Theory Change: W. V. Quine and P. Feyerabend Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, 1 To all Participants

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism

Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism Adam Smith and the Limits of Empiricism In the debate between rationalism and sentimentalism, one of the strongest weapons in the rationalist arsenal is the notion that some of our actions ought to be

More information

Principles of Legal Interpretation. Mark Greenberg, UCLA. In the large literature on legal interpretation, we find intelligent argument and

Principles of Legal Interpretation. Mark Greenberg, UCLA. In the large literature on legal interpretation, we find intelligent argument and Principles of Legal Interpretation Mark Greenberg, UCLA 1. Introduction In the large literature on legal interpretation, we find intelligent argument and sophisticated theoretical resources. But the field

More information

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict

Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict Symposium: Robert B. Talisse s Democracy and Moral Conflict Précis of Democracy and Moral Conflict Robert B. Talisse Vanderbilt University Democracy and Moral Conflict is an attempt finally to get right

More information

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument Author: Anna Folland Supervisor: Ragnar Francén Olinder

More information

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work

Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work Kevin Scharp, Replacing Truth, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, 352pp., $85.00, ISBN 9780199653850. At 300-some pages, with narrow margins and small print, the work under review, a spirited defense

More information

THE CONSTITUTIONAL REQUIREMENT OF SENSITIVITY TO RELIGION. Richard A. Hesse*

THE CONSTITUTIONAL REQUIREMENT OF SENSITIVITY TO RELIGION. Richard A. Hesse* THE CONSTITUTIONAL REQUIREMENT OF SENSITIVITY TO RELIGION Richard A. Hesse* I don t know whether the Smith opinion can stand much more whipping today. It s received quite a bit. Unfortunately from my point

More information

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions

Chapter 15. Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions Chapter 15 Elements of Argument: Claims and Exceptions Debate is a process in which individuals exchange arguments about controversial topics. Debate could not exist without arguments. Arguments are the

More information