Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals"

Transcription

1 Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant Copyright Jonathan Bennett All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis.... indicates the omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are rerported between square brackets in normal-sized type.] In the title, Groundwork refers not to the foundation that is laid but to the work of laying it. First launched: July 2005 Last amended: September 2008 Contents Preface 1 Chapter 1: Moving from common-sense knowledge to philosophical knowledge about morality 5 Chapter 2: Moving from popular moral philosophy to the metaphysic of morals 14 Chapter 3: Moving from the metaphysic of morals to the critique of pure practical reason 41

2 Chapter 3: Moving from the metaphysic of morals to the critique of pure practical reason The concept of freedom is the key to explaining the autonomy of the will Will is a kind of causality that living beings exert if they are rational, and when the will can be effective independent of outside causes acting on it, that would involve this causality s property of freedom; just as natural necessity is the property of the causality of all non-rational beings, through which they are caused to act in specific ways by the influence of outside causes. The account of freedom I have just given is negative ( it says there is freedom when the active will does not have external causes acting on it ), and so it isn t fruitful for insight into what freedom is; but there flows from it a concept of freedom that is positive, and accordingly richer and more fruitful. Although freedom is not a property of the will according to laws of nature, it doesn t follow that freedom is lawless! It must in fact be a causality according to immutable laws of a special kind. The concept of lawless free-will would be an absurdity, because the concept of causality brings with it the concept of laws according to which if something we call a cause is given then something else, the effect, must occur. And since freedom conceptually involves causality, and causality conceptually involves law, it follows that freedom conceptually involves law. We saw that natural necessity is a heteronomy of effective causes, because each effect can come about only through a law according to which something else gets the cause to exercise its causality. What can the freedom of the will be, then, but autonomy, i.e. the will s property of itself being a law? However, the proposition: The will itself is a law in all its actions only expresses the principle: Act only on a maxim that can also have itself as a universal law for its object. And this is just the formula of the categorical imperative and is the principle of morality. Therefore a free will and a will under moral laws are identical. [Earlier in this paragraph Kant said that all causality involves an effect s being caused by something else. What he is now treating as the mark not of causality as such but of heteronomous causality in particular is the cause s being stirred into action by something else. In the next paragraph, something else occurs again in a manner that does seem to conflict with what Kant first said about causality in general.] So if we start with freedom of the will, we get morality (together with its principle) from it merely by analysing its concept. But the principle of morality: An absolutely good will is one whose maxim can always include itself regarded as a universal law, is a synthetic proposition, because that property of the maxim can t be found by analysis of the concept of an absolutely good will. What makes such a synthetic proposition possible is there being two cognitions [= items of knowledge ] that are connected with each other through their both being contained in some third cognition. In the case of physical causes, the third cognition that ties the cause to the effect is the nature of the sensible world; but the concept of that conjoins the two concepts of something as cause in relation 41

3 to something else as effect; so it doesn t meet our present needs. In our present context, the third cognition that does the job is the positive concept of freedom. Two tasks present themselves: (1) To show what this third cognition is to which freedom directs us and of which we have an a priori idea, and (2) To make comprehensible the deduction of the concept of freedom from pure practical reason, and along with that the possibility of a categorical imperative. But I can t do either of these right here and now; first, some further preparation is needed. Freedom must be presupposed as a property of the will of all rational beings It isn t enough to ascribe freedom to our will, on whatever grounds, if we don t also have sufficient grounds for attributing it to all rational beings. For morality serves as a law for us only because we are rational beings, so it must hold for all rational beings; and morality must be derived solely from the property of freedom; so freedom must be shown to be a property of the will of all rational beings. And it doesn t suffice to do this on the basis of certain supposed empirical facts concerning human nature: we need an a priori proof ( which empirical facts can t provide ), and we need a result concerning absolutely all rational beings endowed with a will ( and not merely concerning human beings ). Now I say this: Any being who can t act otherwise than under the idea of freedom is, just for that reason, really free in his conduct i.e. all laws that are inseparably bound up 16 with freedom hold for him just as if his will were validly pronounced free in itself as a matter of theoretical philosophy. 16 Now I maintain this: We must necessarily equip every rational being who has a will with the idea of freedom, this being an idea under which he must act. For the thought of such a being includes the thought of a reason that is practical, i.e. has causality with respect to its object. Now we can t conceive of a reason that would consciously take direction (about how to judge) from outside itself, for then the person whose reason it was would think that what settled how he judged was not his reason but some external impulse. Reason must regard itself as the author of its principles, owing nothing to external influences; so it must as practical reason, or as the will of a rational being regard itself as free. That is to say, the will of a rational being can be his will only under the idea of freedom, so that from a practical point of view such a will must be ascribed to all rational beings. Why should I be moral? We have finally traced the determinate concept of morality back to the idea of freedom, but we couldn t prove freedom to be actual in ourselves and in human nature. We saw only that we must presuppose it if we want to think of a being as rational and as conscious of himself as the cause of his own actions, i.e. as endowed with a will; and so we find that on just those same grounds we must ascribe to each being I start in a way that is sufficient for my purposes, with freedom as something posited by all rational beings merely in idea as the basis for their actions. I go about things in this way so as to avoid having to prove freedom also in its theoretical respect. Even if the latter actual, factual, theoretical freedom is left unproved, it makes no difference, because the laws that would hold for a being who was really free hold also for a being who cannot act except under the idea of his own freedom. Thus we escape the burden of proof that the theoretical assertion of freedom would impose upon us. 42

4 endowed with reason and will this property of settling for himself how he will act, doing this under the idea of freedom. From the presupposition of this idea of freedom there flowed also the consciousness of a law of action: The subjective principles of actions (i.e. maxims) must always be adopted in such a way that they can hold also as objective, i.e. hold as universal principles, thereby serving as universal laws that we give to ourselves. But why ought I, just because I am a rational being, subject myself to this law? And why should all other beings endowed with reason do so? Admittedly no interest impels me to do this, for that wouldn t yield a categorical imperative; but I must still take an interest in it, and have insight into how it comes about. For this ought is really a shall that holds for every rational being whose reason isn t hindered in its generating of actions. For beings like ourselves, that necessity of action is expressed only as ought, and the subjective necessity is thus distinguished from the objective. By beings like ourselves I mean ones who are affected not only by reason but also by action-drivers that come from the senses beings who don t always do what reason would have done if left to itself. So it seems that all we have done with respect to the moral law (i.e. the principle of the autonomy of the will) is to presuppose it in the idea of freedom, as though we couldn t independently prove its reality and objective necessity. Even that would bring some gain, because in doing it we would at least have defined the genuine principle more accurately than had been done before; but we wouldn t have made any progress regarding the validity of the moral law or the practical necessity of subjecting ourselves to it. If anyone asked: Why do our actions have to be based on maxims that could be universally valid as laws? What is the basis for the value that we ascribe to this way of acting a value so great that no interest, anywhere, can outweigh it? How does it come about that a man believes that it is only through this that he feels his own personal value, in contrast to which that of a pleasant or unpleasant state is to be regarded as nothing? we couldn t give him any satisfactory answer. We do indeed find that we can take an interest in a personal quality that makes us fit to enjoy some condition if reason were to allot that condition to us, even though the personal quality doesn t automatically bring the condition with it. An example might be: taking an interest in being the sort of person who would be a good spouse, this being distinct from taking an interest in being married. That is, we can take an interest in being worthy of happiness without having being happy as a motive. But this judgment about value this taking of an interest is in fact only the effect of the importance we have already ascribed to the moral law (when through the idea of freedom we detach ourselves from every empirical interest). But we are confronted by the proposition that We ought to detach ourselves from every empirical interest, to regard ourselves as free in acting and yet as subject to certain laws, in order to find right there within ourselves a value that would compensate for the loss of everything that could make our situation desirable. How this is possible, and hence on what grounds the moral law is binding, can t be grasped through my procedure up to here. 43

5 It has to be admitted that there is a kind of circle here from which there seems to be no escape. We take ourselves to be free in the order of effective causes so that we can think of ourselves as subject to moral laws in the order of ends; and then we think of ourselves as subject to these laws because we have ascribed to ourselves freedom of the will. This is circular because freedom and self-legislation by the will are both autonomy; so they are equivalent concepts, which is why neither of them can be used to explain or support the other. At most they can be used for the logical purpose of bringing apparently different representations of the same object under a single concept (like reducing the both of the fractions and to 3 4 ). There remains open to us, however, one way out of the circle, namely, to pursue an inquiry into these: thinking of ourselves as causes that are effective a priori through freedom, and thinking of ourselves in terms of our actions considered as empirically observable effects. For example: thinking of myself as voluntarily raising my arm, and thinking of myself as seeing my arm go up. The question is: Don t these involve different standpoints? [In this next paragraph and later on, Kant refers to a certain world that he calls Verstandeswelt = world of understanding. Evidently this world has at least as much to do with reason as with understanding, and we shall see on the next page that Kant distinguishes these from one another. So world of understanding would be a misleading label, and intelligible world is used instead. In some places where Verstandeswelt would be especially misleading, Kant instead uses intelligibel Welt.] What I am about to say requires no subtle reflection, and presumably even the most ordinary intellect could arrive at it (doing so in its own way, through an obscure exercise of judgment that it calls feeling!). All mental representations that come to us involuntarily (as do those of the senses) enable us to know objects only as they affect us, which leaves us still ignorant of what they are in themselves; and therefore representations of this kind, however closely and sharply we attend to them, can give us only knowledge of appearances, never knowledge of things in themselves. This distinction may be made just by noticing the difference between representations that we passively receive from somewhere else and ones that we actively produce out of ourselves. Once the distinction has been made somehow, it automatically follows that we must admit and assume behind the appearances something else that is not appearance, namely things in themselves. But we have to accept that we can t get any closer to them, and can t ever know what they are in themselves, because all we can know of them is how they affect us. This must yield a distinction, though a rough one, between a sensible world, which can be very different to various observers, because of differences in their sensibilities, and an intelligible world, which underlies the sensible world, and remains always the same. A man shouldn t claim to know even himself as he really is by knowing himself through inner sensation i.e. by introspection. For since he doesn t produce himself (so to speak) or get his concept of himself a priori but only empirically, it is natural that he gets his knowledge of himself through inner sense and consequently only through how his nature appears and how his consciousness is affected. But beyond the character of his own subject, which is made up out of these mere appearances, he necessarily assumes something else underlying it, namely his I as it is in itself. Thus in respect to mere perception and receptivity to sensations he must count himself as belonging to the sensible world; 44

6 but in respect to whatever pure activity there may be in himself (which reaches his consciousness directly and not by affecting the inner or outer senses) he must count himself as belonging to the intellectual world though he doesn t know anything more about it. A thoughtful person must come to some such conclusion as this about all the things that present themselves to him. Even someone with a very ordinary mind is likely to have this thought, because we know that such people are strongly inclined to expect something invisibly active at work behind the objects of the senses; but they don t learn anything from this because they soon spoil it by trying to make the invisible something perceptible, i.e. to make it an object of intuition. They do this by wondering What is it like, this unknown something that lurks behind the appearances of things?, when their only concept of what a thing can be like is made from the concept of how things appear to them. Now a human being really finds within himself a capacity by which he distinguishes himself from all other things, and that includes distinguishing himself as something active from himself considered as affected by objects. This capacity or faculty is reason. Its pure, spontaneously active nature puts reason on a higher level even than understanding, and here is why. Understanding is like reason in this: it is spontaneously active, and does not like the faculty of sense merely contain representations that come from our being passively affected by things. But it is unlike reason in that the only concepts it can produce through its activity are ones whose only role is to bring the representations of sense under rules.... The intellectual management of the data of the senses is the understanding s only task. Without this use of sensibility the understanding wouldn t have any thoughts at all. In contrast with this, reason shows in its ideas, as we call them ( ideas relating to reason as concepts do to the understanding ), a spontaneity so pure that it goes far beyond anything that sensibility can come up with. The highest occupation of reason is to distinguish the sensible world from the intellectual world, thereby marking out limits for the understanding itself. Because of this, a rational being must regard himself in his role as an intelligence, setting aside his lower faculties as belonging not to the sensible world but to the intelligible world. So he has two standpoints from which he can consider himself and recognize the laws for the use of his powers and hence for all his actions. (1) As belonging to the sensible world, he falls under the laws of nature (heteronomy). (2) As belonging to the intelligible world, he is under the moral authority of laws that are independent of nature, and so are not empirical but based entirely on reason. As a rational being and thus as belonging to the intelligible world, a human being can never think of the causality of his own will except under the idea of freedom; because reason must always take itself to be independent of the determining causes of the sensible world, and that independence is what freedom is. Now we have the idea of freedom inseparably connected with the concept of autonomy, which is bound up with the universal principle of morality, which is ideally the ground of all actions of rational beings, just as the law of nature is the ground of all appearances. That allays the suspicion (the one that I stirred up earlier) that there might be a hidden circle in our reasoning from freedom to autonomy and from that to the moral law that we might have laid down the idea of freedom for the sake of the moral law so that we could later derive the law from freedom! That would have made us unable to give 45

7 any basis for the law.... But now we see that when we think of ourselves as free, we carry ourselves into the intelligible world as members of it and recognize the autonomy of the will and the morality that autonomy brings with it; whereas when we think of ourselves as under an obligation, we regard ourselves as belonging to the sensible world and at the same time also to the intelligible world. How is a categorical imperative possible? A rational being counts himself, as an intelligence, as belonging to the intelligible world, and only as an effective cause belonging to this world does he call his causality a will. On the other side, though, he is conscious of himself as a bit of the sensible world in which his actions are encountered as mere appearances of that causality of his will. But we aren t acquainted with that causality of his will, so there s no way we can grasp how these actions can arise from it; and so they must instead be regarded as caused by other appearances, namely, desires and preferences belonging to the sensible world. Considered only as a member of the intelligible world, my behaviour would completely accord with the principle of the autonomy of the pure will; considered as a bit of the sensible world, my behaviour would have to be assumed to conform wholly to the natural law of desires and preferences and thus to the heteronomy of nature. (The former behaviour would rest on the supreme principle of morality, and the latter on that of happiness.) But the intelligible world contains the ground or basis of the sensible world and therefore of its laws, and so the intelligible world is (and must be conceived as) directly law-giving for my will, which belongs wholly to the intelligible world. Therefore I see myself, in my status as an intelligence, as subject to the law of the intelligible world, i.e. the law of reason which is contained in the idea of freedom, and as subject to the autonomy of the will. Therefore the laws of the intelligible world must be regarded as imperatives for me, and actions that conform to them must be regarded as duties. All this holds, despite the fact that on the other side I am a being that belongs to the sensible world. So this is how categorical imperatives are possible: The idea of freedom makes me a member of an intelligible world; if I were a member only of that world, all my actions would always conform to the autonomy of the will; but since I confront myself also as a member of the world of sense, my actions ought to conform to it. This categorical ought presents a priori a synthetic proposition. It is synthetic because in it (1) my will affected by my sensuous desires has added to it the idea of (2) something that reason says contains its supreme condition, namely that very same will considered as pure, self-sufficiently practical, and belonging to the intelligible world. It is a genuine addition; there s no way you could extract (2) from (1) by sheer analysis. [Kant adds a not very helpful comparison of this with his doctrine, expounded in his Critique of Pure Reason, about a priori synthetic propositions that are essential to our knowledge of any system of nature.] The practical application of common-sense confirms the correctness of this deduction. When we present examples of honesty of purpose, of steadfastness in following good maxims, and of sympathy and general benevolence (even with great sacrifices of advantage and comfort), there is no man, not even the most malicious villain (provided he is otherwise accustomed to using his reason), who doesn t wish that he also might have these qualities. It s merely because of his preferences and impulses that he can t make himself be like this; but he would like to be free of the burden of such preferences. He thus shows himself as having a thought in which he, with a will free from all impulses of sensibility, 46

8 transfers himself into an order of things altogether different from that of his desires in the field of sensibility. In this thought he doesn t look for any gratification of desires or any state of affairs that would satisfy any desire that he has or can imagine having; for if that were his aim, the very idea that elicits this wish from him would lose its pre-eminence. All he can be looking for is a greater intrinsic value as a person. He believes himself to be this better person when he shifts himself to the standpoint of a member of the intelligible world, to which he is automatically taken by the idea of freedom (i.e. of not being acted on by causes in the sensible world). And in this standpoint he is conscious of a good will which on his own confession constitutes the law for his bad will as a member of the sensible world. He recognizes the status of the law even while he breaks it. The moral ought is therefore his own necessary will as a member of the intelligible world, and it is conceived by him as an ought only because he regards himself at the same time as a member of the sensible world. Concerning the outermost boundary of all practical philosophy All human beings think of themselves as having free will. That is the source of all judgments that acts that weren t performed ought to have been performed. But this freedom isn t something of which we have an experiential concept; it can t be, because even when experience shows the opposite of things that are represented as necessary on the supposition of freedom, freedom still remains, which shows that it can t be defeated by facts of experience because it isn t in the same arena, so to speak, as they are. On the other hand it is equally necessary that everything that happens should be inexorably caused in accordance with natural laws; and this natural necessity [a single word in German] is also not something of which we have an experiential concept, because it brings with it the concept of necessity and thus of something that can be known a priori, i.e. without consulting experience. But this concept of a system of nature is confirmed by experience, and it has to be presupposed if experience is to be possible experience being knowledge of the objects of the senses interconnected by universal laws. So freedom is only an idea of reason, whose objective reality in itself is doubtful, whereas nature is a concept of the understanding, which does and necessarily must exhibit its reality in examples drawn from experience. From this there arises a dialectic of reason a seeming conflict of reason with itself because the freedom ascribed to the will seems to contradict natural necessity, and reason finds itself drawn to each side of the apparent conflict at this parting of the ways. For speculative purposes such as the pursuit of scientific theories, reason finds the road of natural necessity more well-trodden and usable than that of freedom. But for practical purposes thinking about what to do and what not to do the only way of bringing reason to bear is along the path of freedom; which is why even the subtlest philosophy can t argue freedom away, any more than the most ordinary common-sense can. So philosophy has to assume that no real contradiction will be found between freedom and natural necessity as applied to the very same human actions, for it can t give up the concept of nature any more than it can that of freedom. We ll never be able to grasp how freedom is possible, but in the meantime we should at least eradicate in a convincing way this apparent contradiction. For if the very thought of freedom contradicted itself or contradicted nature (which is 47

9 equally necessary), freedom would have to be surrendered in favour of natural necessity. But this contradiction couldn t be escaped if the subject who seems to himself to be free were thinking of himself in the same sense or in the same relationship when he calls himself free as when he takes himself to be subject to natural law with respect to the very same action. So speculative philosophy can t be excused from its task of showing at least this much: that the ways of talking that produce the illusion of contradiction come from our thinking of the person in a different sense and relationship when we call him free from that in which we consider him as a part of nature and subject to its laws; and that these two standpoints not only can very well coexist but must be thought of as necessarily united in one and the same subject. If this much is not shown, we are left with no basis for burdening reason with an idea as troublesome as that of freedom an idea which, though it can without contradiction be united with the well-established concept of natural necessity, nevertheless entangles us in troubles that sorely embarrass reason in its theoretical use. It is only theoretical philosophy that has this duty; its purpose is to clear the way for practical philosophy. So it isn t up to the philosopher to decide whether to remove the apparent contradiction or rather to leave it untouched; for if he doesn t remove it, the theory about it would be a no-man s-land which the fatalist would be entitled to take over, as a squatter, driving all morality out. But we still haven t reached the boundary of practical philosophy. For the settling of the controversy over freedom doesn t belong to it. The situation is just that practical philosophy demands that theoretical reason put an end to the discord in which it entangles itself in theoretical questions, so that practical reason may have peace and security from outward attacks that could put into dispute the land on which it wants to build. The common-sense claim to have freedom of the will is based on the person s consciousness of something that has also been conceded as a presupposition, namely that reason is independent of causes that determine a person s psychological state causes that are all of the sort that sensation can inform us about, and that can be brought under the general name sensibility. A human being, who in this way regards himself as an intelligence, when he thinks of himself as an intelligence with a will, and consequently with causality, puts himself in a different order of things and in a relationship to determining grounds of an altogether different kind from what comes into play when he perceives himself as a phenomenon in the world of sense (as he really is also), and subjects his causality to external causal factors according to natural laws. Now he soon realizes that both can exist together indeed, that they must. For there is not the slightest contradiction between (1) a thing in appearance (belonging to the sensible world) being subject to certain laws from which as (2) a thing in itself it is independent. That he must think of himself in this twofold way rests on (1) his consciousness of himself as an object affected through the senses, and (2) his consciousness of himself as an intelligence (i.e. as independent of sensible impressions in the use of reason), and thus as belonging to the intelligible world. [The indented portion of this paragraph is a first-person rendition of something that Kant writes using he rather than I.] That s how it comes about that a human being claims to have a will that doesn t make him accountable for what belongs only to his desires and preferences, but thinks of this same 48

10 will as making possible indeed necessary actions that he can perform only by disregarding all his desires and sensuous attractions. The causality of these actions lies in him as an intelligence and in an intelligible world s principles concerning effects and actions. All he knows about this intelligible world is this: In this sensible world the law is given only by reason, and indeed pure reason independent of sensibility. Moreover, since it is only as an intelligence that I am a genuine self (as a human being I am only an appearance of myself ), those laws apply to me immediately and categorically; so that nothing that I am pushed into doing by preferences or impulses thus, nothing caused by the sensible world can count against the laws of my volition as an intelligence. Indeed, he doesn t hold himself responsible for those preferences and impulses or attribute them to his genuine self (i.e. to his will); though when he allows them to influence his maxims in ways that go against the rational laws of his will, he holds his will to account for that. By thinking itself into an intelligible world, practical reason doesn t at all step across that world s boundaries, but it would do so if it tried to see or feel its way into it. The thought of the intelligible world is only a negative thought with respect to the sensible world; it doesn t give reason any laws for determining the will. The only positive thing about it is this: Freedom as a negative determination i.e. as something that involves not being interfered with by sensible causes is also connected with a positive power and even a causality of reason, a causality that we call a will.....but if practical reason were to borrow an object of the will (i.e. a motive) from the intelligible world, it would be overstepping its boundaries and pretending to be acquainted with something of which it knows nothing. So the concept of an intelligible world is only a standpoint that reason sees itself as having to take, outside appearances, in order to think of itself as practical. Reason couldn t be practical if the influences of sensibility settled how the human being behaved, but it must be practical unless his consciousness of himself as an intelligence, and thus as a rational and rationally active cause (i.e. a cause acting in freedom), is to be contradicted. This thought certainly brings with it the idea of an order and a law-giving different from that of the mechanism of nature, which has to do with the sensible world; and it necessitates the concept of an intelligible world, i.e. the totality of rational beings as things in themselves; but without the slightest pretence to have any thoughts about it that go beyond its formal condition i.e. the universality of the maxim of the will as law, and thus the will s autonomy which is required for its freedom. All laws that are fixed on an object make for heteronomy, which belongs only to natural laws and can apply only to the sensible world. We can explain things only by bringing them under laws governing things that could be confronted in experience. But freedom is only an idea of reason ; there is no way its objective reality could be shown through natural laws or, therefore, through any experience. Because it can t be illustrated even in an analogical way with examples, we can t ever grasp it or even see into it a little. It holds only as a necessary presupposition of reason in a being who believes himself conscious of having a will, i.e. a faculty or capacity different from that of mere desire a capacity to get himself to act as an intelligence, and thus to act according to laws of reason and independently of natural instincts. But when we come to an end of causation according to 49

11 natural laws, we are at an end of all explanation, and all that is left for us to do is to defend i.e. to refute objections from those who purport to have seen more deeply into the essence of things and who boldly declare freedom to be impossible. We can only show them that the supposed contradiction they have discovered in the idea of freedom lies simply in this: They have to regard a human being as appearance in order to bring natural laws to bear on his actions; and now when we require them to think of him-asintelligence as a thing in itself, they still persist regarding considering him as appearance. Separating his causality (his will) from all natural laws of the sensible world does indeed involve a contradiction if this is the very same subject that we previously brought under natural laws; but the contradiction will disappear if they will think again, and admit that behind appearances things in themselves must stand as their hidden ground, and that we can t insist that the laws of operation of these grounds must be the same as those that govern their appearances. The subjective impossibility of explaining the freedom of the will is the same as the impossibility of discovering and making graspable an interest which a human being can take in moral laws. 17 Yet he does actually take an interest in them, and our name for the foundation of this is moral feeling. Some have wrongly offered this moral feeling as our standard for moral judgment, whereas really it should be seen as the subjective effect that the law has on the will; the objective grounds for moral judgment come not from 17 feeling but from reason. If a sensuously affected rational being is to will an action that reason alone prescribes as what he ought to do, reason must of course be able to instil a feeling of pleasure or satisfaction in the fulfilment of duty, and hence must have a causal power to affect sensibility in accordance with its own principles. But it is wholly impossible to conceive a priori how a mere thought with nothing sensuous in it produces a sensation of pleasure or unpleasure. For that is one particular kind of causality which, like every kind of causality, we can learn about only by consulting experience, not a priori. But we can t understand this causality through experience either, because we can do that only for cause-effect pairs where both items are objects of experience, whereas here the effect does lie within experience but the cause namely, reason acting through mere ideas, which furnish no object for experience does not. So it is completely impossible for us human beings to explain how and why we have an interest in the universality of the maxim as law and thus an interest in morality. Only this much is certain: (1) It is not the case that the law holds for us because we have an interest in it (for that would be heteronomy, making practical reason depend on sensibility in the form of an underlying feeling, which could never yield a moral law); and (2) It is the case that we have an interest in the moral law because it holds for us as human beings, because it has arisen from our will as intelligence, and hence from our genuine self. That source for the moral law is what gives it its authority, what It is by interest that reason becomes practical, i.e. becomes a cause acting on the will. That is why it is only of a being with reason that we say He takes an interest in something; non-rational creatures don t have interests only sensuous impulses. Reason takes an immediate interest in actions only in cases where what has moved the will in that direction is the universal validity of the action s maxim. That s the only kind of interest that is pure [= non-empirical ]. In contrast with that, reason takes an indirect or mediated interest in an action if it acts on the will only through the intervention or mediation of another object of desire or under the supposition of some particular feeling that the subject has; and since such objects of desire and particular feelings can t be found out by reason itself, unaided by experience, this mediated kind of interest is only empirical and not a pure interest of reason

12 makes it hold for us, because reason necessarily makes what belongs to mere appearance subordinate to the character of the thing in itself. So the question How is a categorical imperative possible? can be answered to this extent: We can cite the only presupposition under which it is possible, namely the idea of freedom; and we can have insight into the necessity of this presupposition. That is all we need for the practical use of reason (i.e. to be convinced of the categorical imperative s validity and hence also of the moral law). But how this presupposition itself is possible can never be grasped by any human reason. However,....the presupposition of the freedom of the will is quite possible, as speculative philosophy can prove, for it doesn t involve itself in a contradiction with the principle that natural necessity interconnects all the appearances in the sensible world. More than that, it is unconditionally necessary for any rational being. I mean that it is practically necessary for him, meaning that he needs it for his consciousness of his causality through reason,....needs the idea of it as the fundamental condition of all his voluntary acts. But the question still stands: How can pure reason, all by itself without any outside help from other action-drivers, be practical? How can the mere principle of the universal validity of its maxims as laws....create, unaided, an action-driver and produce an interest that would be called purely moral? In short: How can pure reason be practical? All human reason is wholly incompetent to explain this, and it is a waste of trouble and labour to try. It is just the same as if I tried to find out how freedom itself as the causality of a will is possible, for in making that attempt I would be leaving the philosophical basis of explanation behind, and I have no other. I would still have the intelligible world, the world of intelligences, and I could drift around in that; but it couldn t supply the desired explanation, because although I have a well-founded idea of that world I don t have the least knowledge of it and I can t have such knowledge, however hard I exercise my natural faculty of reason. This intelligible world signifies only a something a whatever-it-is that is left after I have excluded from the factors acting on my will everything belonging to the sensible world, which I did merely so as to shut the principle of motives out of field of sensibility. I did this by limiting this field and showing that it doesn t contain absolutely everything, and that outside it there is still more; but that s all I know about this more, namely that it lies outside the sensible world. It is pure reason that has this idea, that is the thought of this ideal entity, the intelligible world ; it has been deprived of all matter (i.e. all knowledge of objects); so all that I am left with in trying to make sense of pure reason is the form, namely the practical law of the universal validity of maxims, and the possible role of pure reason as an effective cause acting on the will in accordance with that form. There is no room here for any external action-driver. If we insist on there being one, then the action-driver i.e. that in which reason directly takes an interest would have to be this idea of an intelligible world. But to understand how this could drive action is precisely the problem we can t solve. Here, then, is the outermost boundary of all moral inquiry [assuming that Kant wrote oberste = highest when he meant to write äußerste = outermost, as in the heading on page 47]. It s very important to locate it accurately, because if we don t, either of two disasters may occur. On the one hand, reason may search for the supreme moral motive in the sensible world, in a way harmful to morals.... On the other hand, reason may impotently flap its wings in the space so far as reason 51

13 is concerned it s an empty space! of....the intelligible world, without being able to move from its starting point and so losing itself among phantoms. For the rest, the idea of a pure intelligible world, as a whole of all intelligences to which we ourselves belong as rational beings (though on the other side we also belong to the sensible world), is always a useful and permissible idea for the purpose of a rational belief, even though all knowledge terminates at that world s boundary. Its service is that of awakening in us a lively interest in the moral law through the noble ideal of a universal realm of ends in themselves (rational beings) to which we can belong as members only when we scrupulously conduct ourselves by maxims of freedom as if they were laws of nature. Concluding remark The speculative use of reason with respect to nature leads to the absolute necessity of some supreme cause of the world. The practical use of reason with regard to freedom leads also to an absolute necessity, but only of the laws of actions of a rational being as such. Now, it is an essential principle of all use of our reason to push its knowledge to an awareness of its necessity, for otherwise it wouldn t be rational knowledge. But it is also an equally essential limitation of this very same reason that it can t see that necessarily x exists or y happens, or necessarily z ought to happen, except on the basis of some condition that applies to x or y or z. But the obtaining of a condition won t make something necessary unless the condition itself is necessary; and so if reason keeps searching for conditions it only pushes its satisfaction further and further into the future. So reason, restlessly seeking the unconditionally necessary, sees itself as having to assume it, though it has no way of making it comprehensible to itself; it is happy enough if it can merely discover the concept that is compatible with this presupposition. According to my account of the supreme principles of morality, reason can t render comprehensible the absolute necessity of an unconditional practical law (such as the categorical imperative must be). If you want to complain about this, don t blame my account blame reason! Not that blame is appropriate : reason can t be blamed for being unwilling to explain the moral law through a condition i.e. by making some interest its basis for a law explained in that way would no longer be if it did, the law would cease to be moral and would no longer be the supreme law of freedom. So we truly don t comprehend the unconditional practical necessity of the moral imperative; but we do comprehend its incomprehensibility, which is all that can fairly be demanded of a philosophy that in its principles forces its way out to the boundaries of human reason. 52

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.] IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.] PREFACE 1. Kant defines rational knowledge as being composed of two parts, the Material and Formal. 2. Formal

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 35 The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper, I will critically examine Christine Korsgaard s claim

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant Copyright 2010 2015 All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781)

THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL By Immanuel Kant From Critique of Pure Reason (1781) From: A447/B475 A451/B479 Freedom independence of the laws of nature is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but it is also

More information

Critique of Pure Reason up to the end of the Analytic

Critique of Pure Reason up to the end of the Analytic Critique of Pure Reason up to the end of the Analytic Immanuel Kant 1781 Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that

More information

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling

KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS. John Watling KANT S EXPLANATION OF THE NECESSITY OF GEOMETRICAL TRUTHS John Watling Kant was an idealist. His idealism was in some ways, it is true, less extreme than that of Berkeley. He distinguished his own by calling

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

The CopernicanRevolution

The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant: The Copernican Revolution The CopernicanRevolution Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) The Critique of Pure Reason (1781) is Kant s best known work. In this monumental work, he begins a Copernican-like

More information

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2. Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2 Kant s analysis of the good differs in scope from Aristotle s in two ways. In

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge

Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Kant Lecture 4 Review Synthetic a priori knowledge Statements involving necessity or strict universality could never be known on the basis of sense experience, and are thus known (if known at all) a priori.

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant (1785)

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant (1785) Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant (1785) Kant, Groundwork, Early Modern Texts version 1 Jonathan Bennett revised an English translation of Kant s text, to provide the version below.

More information

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity

Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity Fourth Meditation: Truth and falsity In these past few days I have become used to keeping my mind away from the senses; and I have become strongly aware that very little is truly known about bodies, whereas

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire.

KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON. The law is reason unaffected by desire. KANT, MORAL DUTY AND THE DEMANDS OF PURE PRACTICAL REASON The law is reason unaffected by desire. Aristotle, Politics Book III (1287a32) THE BIG IDEAS TO MASTER Kantian formalism Kantian constructivism

More information

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa

Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa Unifying the Categorical Imperative* Marcus Arvan University of Tampa [T]he concept of freedom constitutes the keystone of the whole structure of a system of pure reason [and] this idea reveals itself

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena Duty and Categorical Rules Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena Preview This selection from Kant includes: The description of the Good Will The concept of Duty An introduction

More information

Prolegomena [= Preliminaries] to any Future Metaphysic that can Present itself as a Science

Prolegomena [= Preliminaries] to any Future Metaphysic that can Present itself as a Science Prolegomena [= Preliminaries] to any Future Metaphysic that can Present itself as a Science Immanuel Kant Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations.

More information

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney Moral Obligation by Charles G. Finney The idea of obligation, or of oughtness, is an idea of the pure reason. It is a simple, rational conception, and, strictly speaking, does not admit of a definition,

More information

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Kantian Ethics I. Context II. The Good Will III. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation of Universal Law IV. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation

More information

Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic

Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic Immanuel Kant 1781 Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

1/5. The Critique of Theology

1/5. The Critique of Theology 1/5 The Critique of Theology The argument of the Transcendental Dialectic has demonstrated that there is no science of rational psychology and that the province of any rational cosmology is strictly limited.

More information

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial. TitleKant's Concept of Happiness: Within Author(s) Hirose, Yuzo Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial Citation Philosophy, Psychology, and Compara 43-49 Issue Date 2010-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143022

More information

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2

FREEDOM OF CHOICE. Freedom of Choice, p. 2 FREEDOM OF CHOICE Human beings are capable of the following behavior that has not been observed in animals. We ask ourselves What should my goal in life be - if anything? Is there anything I should live

More information

Treatise of Human Nature Book II: The Passions

Treatise of Human Nature Book II: The Passions Treatise of Human Nature Book II: The Passions David Hume Copyright 2005 2010 All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason Excerpt from J. Garvey, The Twenty Greatest Philosophy Books (Continuum, 2007): Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason In a letter to Moses Mendelssohn, Kant says this about the Critique of Pure Reason:

More information

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III.

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature ( ), Book I, Part III. David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (1739 1740), Book I, Part III. N.B. This text is my selection from Jonathan Bennett s paraphrase of Hume s text. The full Bennett text is available at http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/.

More information

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier

III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier III Knowledge is true belief based on argument. Plato, Theaetetus, 201 c-d Is Justified True Belief Knowledge? Edmund Gettier In Theaetetus Plato introduced the definition of knowledge which is often translated

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt

Rationalism. A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt Rationalism I. Descartes (1596-1650) A. He, like others at the time, was obsessed with questions of truth and doubt 1. How could one be certain in the absence of religious guidance and trustworthy senses

More information

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation

Lecture 25 Hume on Causation Lecture 25 Hume on Causation Patrick Maher Scientific Thought II Spring 2010 Ideas and impressions Hume s terminology Ideas: Concepts. Impressions: Perceptions; they are of two kinds. Sensations: Perceptions

More information

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism Idealism Enlightenment Puzzle How do these fit into a scientific picture of the world? Norms Necessity Universality Mind Idealism The dominant 19th-century response: often today called anti-realism Everything

More information

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Cabrillo College Claudia Close Honors Ethics Philosophy 10H Fall 2018 Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Your initial presentation should be approximately 6-7 minutes and you should prepare

More information

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik

THE MORAL ARGUMENT. Peter van Inwagen. Introduction, James Petrik THE MORAL ARGUMENT Peter van Inwagen Introduction, James Petrik THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSIONS of human freedom is closely intertwined with the history of philosophical discussions of moral responsibility.

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

Real-Life Dialogue on Human Freedom and the Origin of Evil

Real-Life Dialogue on Human Freedom and the Origin of Evil Real-Life Dialogue on Human Freedom and the Origin of Evil Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality

The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-31-2006 The Impossibility of Evil Qua Evil: Kantian Limitations on Human Immorality Timothy

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

1/6. The Second Analogy (2)

1/6. The Second Analogy (2) 1/6 The Second Analogy (2) Last time we looked at some of Kant s discussion of the Second Analogy, including the argument that is discussed most often as Kant s response to Hume s sceptical doubts concerning

More information

SCHOOL ^\t. MENTAL CURE. Metaphysical Science, ;aphysical Text Book 749 TREMONT STREET, FOR STUDENT'S I.C6 BOSTON, MASS. Copy 1 BF 1272 BOSTON: AND

SCHOOL ^\t. MENTAL CURE. Metaphysical Science, ;aphysical Text Book 749 TREMONT STREET, FOR STUDENT'S I.C6 BOSTON, MASS. Copy 1 BF 1272 BOSTON: AND K I-. \. 2- } BF 1272 I.C6 Copy 1 ;aphysical Text Book FOR STUDENT'S USE. SCHOOL ^\t. OF Metaphysical Science, AND MENTAL CURE. 749 TREMONT STREET, BOSTON, MASS. BOSTON: E. P. Whitcomb, 383 Washington

More information

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian

Copyright 2000 Vk-Cic Vahe Karamian Kant In France and England, the Enlightenment theories were blueprints for reforms and revolutions political and economic changes came together with philosophical theory. In Germany, the Enlightenment

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

Of Cause and Effect David Hume

Of Cause and Effect David Hume Of Cause and Effect David Hume Of Probability; And of the Idea of Cause and Effect This is all I think necessary to observe concerning those four relations, which are the foundation of science; but as

More information

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought

1/7. The Postulates of Empirical Thought 1/7 The Postulates of Empirical Thought This week we are focusing on the final section of the Analytic of Principles in which Kant schematizes the last set of categories. This set of categories are what

More information

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES.

RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES. MIDWEST STUDIES IN PHILOSOPHY, I11 (1978) RULES, RIGHTS, AND PROMISES. G.E.M. ANSCOMBE I HUME had two theses about promises: one, that a promise is naturally unintelligible, and the other that even if

More information

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of

An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory. Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of An Epistemological Assessment of Moral Worth in Kant s Moral Theory Immanuel Kant s moral theory outlined in The Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals (hereafter Grounding) presents us with the metaphysical

More information

From Critique of Pure Reason Preface to the second edition

From Critique of Pure Reason Preface to the second edition From Critique of Pure Reason Preface to the second edition Immanuel Kant translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn Whether the treatment of that portion of our knowledge which lies within the province of pure

More information

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness

Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness Purple Haze: The Puzzle of Consciousness The MIT Faculty has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters. Citation As Published Publisher Levine, Joseph.

More information

Is There an External World? George Stuart Fullerton

Is There an External World? George Stuart Fullerton Is There an External World? George Stuart Fullerton HOW THE PLAIN MAN THINKS HE KNOWS THE WORLD As schoolboys we enjoyed Cicero s joke at the expense of the minute philosophers. They denied the immortality

More information

Freedom of the Will. Jonathan Edwards

Freedom of the Will. Jonathan Edwards Freedom of the Will A Careful and Strict Inquiry into the Modern Prevailing Notions of that Freedom of the Will which is Supposed to be Essential to Moral Agency, Virtue and Vice, Reward and Punishment,

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion *

Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion * University of Tabriz-Iran Philosophical Investigations Vol. 11/ No. 21/ Fall & Winter 2017 Kant and Demystification of Ethics and Religion * Qodratullah Qorbani ** Associate Professor of Philosophy, Kharazmi

More information

Autonomy and the Second Person Wthin: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall's Tlie Second-Person Standpoints^

Autonomy and the Second Person Wthin: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall's Tlie Second-Person Standpoints^ SYMPOSIUM ON STEPHEN DARWALL'S THE SECOM)-PERSON STANDPOINT Autonomy and the Second Person Wthin: A Commentary on Stephen Darwall's Tlie Second-Person Standpoints^ Christine M. Korsgaard When you address

More information

Title: Kant s Account of Respect: A bridge between rationality and anthropology

Title: Kant s Account of Respect: A bridge between rationality and anthropology Shortened Title: Kant and Respect Title: Kant s Account of Respect: A bridge between rationality and anthropology Dr. Jane Singleton University of Hertfordshire School of Humanities de Havilland Campus

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order 1 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use

PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS. Methods that Metaphysicians Use PHILOSOPHY 4360/5360 METAPHYSICS Methods that Metaphysicians Use Method 1: The appeal to what one can imagine where imagining some state of affairs involves forming a vivid image of that state of affairs.

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

1/9. The First Analogy

1/9. The First Analogy 1/9 The First Analogy So far we have looked at the mathematical principles but now we are going to turn to the dynamical principles, of which there are two sorts, the Analogies of Experience and the Postulates

More information

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text.

More information

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling

Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling Kantian Review, 20, 2,301 311 KantianReview, 2015 doi:10.1017/s1369415415000060 Accessing the Moral Law through Feeling owen ware Simon Fraser University Email: owenjware@gmail.com Abstract In this article

More information

The Moral Feeling of Respect and Subordination as Subjective Determining Ground. Jason Gusdorf. Georgetown University

The Moral Feeling of Respect and Subordination as Subjective Determining Ground. Jason Gusdorf. Georgetown University Two things fill my mind with ever new and increasing admiration and reverence, the more often one reflects on them: the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me. (Conclusion of Critique of Practical

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy

A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy Friedrich Seibold A Fundamental Thinking Error in Philosophy Abstract The present essay is a semantic and logical analysis of certain terms which coin decisively our metaphysical picture of the world.

More information

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00.

Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, pages, ISBN Hardback $35.00. 106 AUSLEGUNG Rationality in Action. By John Searle. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2001. 303 pages, ISBN 0-262-19463-5. Hardback $35.00. Curran F. Douglass University of Kansas John Searle's Rationality in Action

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals 13 Copyright Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional bullets,

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical [Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical Samuel J. Kerstein Ethicists distinguish between categorical

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant Copyright 2010 2015 All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421]

38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals. [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421] 38 Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals [Ak 4:422] [Ak4:421] what one calls duty is an empty concept, we can at least indicate what we are thinking in the concept of duty and what this concept means.

More information

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views by Philip Sherrard Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Spring 1973) World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com ONE of the

More information

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan

Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason. Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan Absolute Totality, Causality, and Quantum: The Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason Kazuhiko Yamamoto, Kyushu University, Japan The Asian Conference on Ethics, Religion & Philosophy 2017

More information

Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic

Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic Critique of Pure Reason the Dialectic Immanuel Kant 1781 Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

Part I. Classical Sources

Part I. Classical Sources Part I Classical Sources 1 From Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Immanuel Kant From the Preface Since my aim here is directed properly to moral philosophy, I limit the question proposed only to

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but

More information

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics? International Journal of Humanities and Social Science Invention ISSN (Online): 2319 7722, ISSN (Print): 2319 7714 Volume 3 Issue 11 ǁ November. 2014 ǁ PP.38-42 Has Logical Positivism Eliminated Metaphysics?

More information

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability

Ayer on the criterion of verifiability Ayer on the criterion of verifiability November 19, 2004 1 The critique of metaphysics............................. 1 2 Observation statements............................... 2 3 In principle verifiability...............................

More information