The Expressivist Circle: Invoking Norms in the Explanation of Normative Judgment

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The Expressivist Circle: Invoking Norms in the Explanation of Normative Judgment"

Transcription

1 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXV, No. 1, July 2002 The Expressivist Circle: Invoking Norms in the Explanation of Normative Judgment JAMES DREIER Brown University "States of mind are natural states. They are extremely hard to define."1 1. Naturalizing Normative Judgment To naturalize normative judgment is to give some account of it, in naturalistic and non-normative terms. Simon Blackburn's Ruling Passions embraces naturalism, about ethics especially. To be a naturalist is to see human beings as frail complexes of perishable tissue, and so part of the natural order. It is thus to refuse unexplained appeals to mind or spirit, and unexplained appeals to knowledge of a Platonic order of Forms or Norms; it is above all to refuse any appeal to a supernatural order... So the problem is one of finding room for ethics, or of placing ethics within the disenchanted, non-ethical order which we inhabit, and of which we are a part. [48-49] Some kinds of naturalism are reductivist, but expressivism is not. All versions of expressivism agree that it is impossible to give any descriptive predicate that is analytically equivalent (roughly, synonymous) with a moral or other normative predicate. Normative assertions express psychological states that are not mainly representational. Normative predicates supply the expressive role. I need not go into details in this essay.2 Here is Blackburn: Valuing something, it [my theory] says, is not to be understood as describing it in certain terms, any more than hoping for or desiring something are describing it in particular terms. Rather, the state of mind of one who values something is distinctive, but nevertheless it is itself a natu- ral, and naturally describable, state. [49] 2 Ruling Passions (Oxford: 1998) p. 53. References to this book are hereafter by page number alone, cited in square brackets in the main body of the text. See especially pp JAMES DREIER

2 So reductive analysis in the sense of providing a descriptive analytic equivalent for a normative predicate is out of the question. Nevertheless, expressivism is naturalistic. While I have never quite been able to believe expressivism, I am much more sympathetic than many to its kernel. It does seem to me that the core explanation of normative judgment must be broadly expressivist. The alternative, I think, is that there is no explanation at all. And while we can't rule out the possibility that the very idea of normative judgment cannot be any further explained,3 I regard that possibility as a last resort. So it comes as an uncomfortable surprise to me that there is a potential snag in the general form of expressivist explanations of normative judgment. If the snag cannot be untangled, it renders the explanation circular, or plunges it into an infinite regress. Blackburn observes the snag from the deck of Ruling Passions but does not seem to think it is very serious. I aim to alert fellow travelers (and critics) to the danger, and then to suggest how the snag might be untangled. II. The Problem The problem I am after has been mentioned, or at least approximated, by a few philosophers, but to my knowledge it has not yet appeared in any published article.4 In any case, for expository purposes I will present my own formulation. It is sometimes said that belief and desire are normative concepts. I will put it this way: ascriptions of beliefs and desires to agents are themselves normative judgments. I am neither endorsing this claim nor denying it, but it is undoubtedly popular. I will be quoting some of Blackburn's discussion of the claim. In a nutshell, the idea is that when we say that someone desires to drink, we imply (analytically) that insofar as he believes that the only way he can drink is by pouring water into the cup before him, he ought to pour the water. As it's sometimes put, the very idea of a desire (or a belief) with a certain content is analytically bound up with what it 'makes sense' for the desirer to do.5 If this is right, then the problem I'm worried about appears right away. The expressivist analysis of normative judgment invokes ascriptions of Jean Hampton raised the possibility that normativity is inexplicable in The Authority of Reason (Cambridge: 1998). As far as I can tell, she believed normativity is inexplicable. See especially pp. 100ff. Frank Jackson raises a related problem in "Noncognitivism, Normativity, Belief', Ratio 1999; 12(4), In his unpublished "Five not-much-discussed problems for noncognitivism" Michael A. Smith counts it among the five. Nick Zangwill skirts very close to it in an unpublished paper, "An argument for normative realism". This notion of what 'makes sense' is regarded by Allan Gibbard, and now it seems by Blackburn too, as the most fundamental normative notion. See Gibbard, Wise Choices, Apt Feelings (Harvard: 1990) p. 6. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 137

3 propositional attitudes. In some early versions the attitudes were proper desires, or preferences; in some others the attitudes are 'valuings' or 'norm acceptance'. Whatever they are, the considerations that make it plausible that belief ascriptions and desire ascriptions are normative apply alike to the other propositional attitude ascriptions. And this means that the kernel of expressivist analysis invokes normative concepts. This circularity is a big problem. The expressivist analysis now appears circular. Insofar as all the various normative notions we use freely in ordinary language are supposed to be explained by the same basic type of expressivist analysis, an apparently vicious circularity (or possibly an infinite regress) will arise if each analysis must invoke some normative concept of its own.6 III. Really Any Problem? Blackburn seems to have noticed this problem, in two different parts of Ruling Passions. In the Common Questions appendix, he presents the following question and answer: Q. 20. If all descriptions of human psychology, including descriptions of what people believe and desire, are implicitly normative, how can normativity be essentially a matter of attitude? Ans. All such descriptions are plausibly regarded as normative because they seem to imply views about what it 'makes sense' for a person to do, if they are in the states attributed to them. And affirming that something did or did not make sense is entering a normative judgment. If we accept this line of reasoning, all I then add is that the verdict that a person's behaviour does or does not make sense itself expresses an attitude. And where is the harm in that? [319-20] Let's try to say explicitly where the harm is. As I said, if 'descriptions' of human psychology are really always normative, and these descriptions appear in the expressivist analysis of normative terms, then the analysis seems to be trapped in a circle or a regress. This point may not be so obvious as I have made it out to be. It is pretty clear 6 There is another problem. The observation that propositional attitude ascriptions are normative looks to be incompatible with the quotation from Ruling Passions that I've used as an epigram, and also with the remark, cited above: "Rather, the state of mind of one who values something is distinctive, but nevertheless it is itself a natural, and naturally describable, state." [49] States of mind, it might be said, are not natural states at all, any more than moral virtues are. (Of course, in one sense an expressivist is happy to agree that virtues are natural states-there is such a thing as courage, after all, and what could it be but a natural state? But attributing a virtue is not merely saying that a person is in some particular natural state; nor, it appears, is attributing a belief or desire.) And they are not "extremely hard to define" if by "define" is meant, to give a purely descriptive equivalent. They are impossible to define. But this is not the problem I want to focus on. Were it not for the problem of circularity discussed in the text, an expressivist could simply discard the idea that states of mind are natural states. 138 JAMES DREIER

4 that it some contexts, explaining one normative concept by means of another is perfectly acceptable. For example, a consequentialist theory that seeks to explain the idea of moral rightness by reference to the idea of moral goodness is not subject to any objection that this is entirely the wrong kind of explanation. Within normative theory there are interesting and controversial reductions of just this sort. But expressivism is not a view within normative theory at all. It is supposed to be explaining normativity, not just explaining one kind of normative judgment by reference to another. Consequentialism is not a competitor of expressivism.7 When Blackburn asked where the harm is, maybe he was suggesting that it might simply turn out to be true that moral judgment is the expression of some certain complicated intentional state, and that attributing such a state would indeed turn out to be expressing some further complicated state. If it is true, and expressivists are committed to it, well what could be the harm? It could be true, yes. But it could not be an explanation of normative judgment. For conveying it presupposes normative judgment. Using some normative terms to explain the meaning (or role) of some others is not, as I noted, always a pointless enterprise; it is one interesting project within normative theory. But if the aim is to explain normative judgment in general, then using some normative terms in the explanation of others is merely pushing the problem to one side. When we then try to explain what this judgment of 'making sense' is all about, we cite further attitudes (or the same ones) that the judgment expresses, and we are heading down an infinite regress (or around a circle). IV. How Blackburn Understands the Normativity of Belief and Desire Though Blackburn's answer to the question in the Appendix shrugs it off, in the text of Ruling Passions he takes the challenge more seriously. The strategy that he adopts is to 'de-fang' the norms associated with intentional states. Once again, there is a second potential harm. If 'descriptions' of human psychology are really always normative, then they are not really properly called 'descriptions' at all, according to expressivist theory. There may be no harm, in ordinary language or even some kinds of philosophizing, in calling them 'descriptions', but they are not best understood that way if they are normative. They are rather expressions of attitude. The contrast between genuine describing and expressing is a crucial one in expressivism. Valuing something, it says, is not to be understood as describing it in certain terms, any more than hoping for or desiring something are describing it in particular terms. Rather, the state of mind of one who values something is distinctive, but nevertheless it is itself a natural, and naturally describable, state. [49] But now it appears that saying what state someone expresses by a normative judgment is not describing, or not exclusively describing. Attributing an intentional state is at least partly expressing a state of one's own. The state of mind of one who values is no more a natural state than moral wrongness is a natural property. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 139

5 Then the question is how to take references to 'making sense' in these clauses. They seem to be statements about what you would expect from an agent. It would surprise you, and lead you to scramble for another interpretation of X, if X does not behave in ways that make sense. Similarly we might say that the circuit is wired up if it is in a state such that, when the key is turned, there ought to be a spark. But the 'ought' here speaks not of duties and values, but just about what you would expect. If there is no spark, then something has gone wrong, but this too means simply loss of expected or intended function. [56] This passage makes it appear that when we say that someone who believes that if Socrates is a man then he is mortal ought to believe (say) that if Socrates is not mortal, he is not a man, the 'ought' is merely the 'ought' of expectation. It is not really normative at all. No meaning would be lost by replacing all occurrences of "ought to" with "is likely to". When I conclude "there ought to be a spark" from "the key was turned in the ignition", there is no implication at all that the proposition that the key was turned in the ignition is normative. Saying that if you fear dogs, then when you come upon one you ought to flee, is just saying that this is the kind of behaviour you would expect of people who fear dogs. There is no implication that if you do not flee, you are somehow irrational. You are only to some extent doing something unexpected, to be explained with further investigation, and even indicative that your fear of dogs is not all that real. [56] I have two doubts about this strategy. First, it simply seems wrong to say that our ordinary idea of what someone ought to think or do, given what else he thinks and wants, is not normative. When someone believes that all men are mortal, and that Socrates is a man, then he ought to believe that Socrates is mortal, and if he doesn't then he is flouting rationality. While there certainly does seem to be a non-normative notion of what 'makes sense', the ought of what someone ought to believe seems to be paradigmatically normative. Second, while in the example of the key in the ignition we are inclined to say that there ought to be a spark, we do not think that it is analytic that there ought to be a spark when the key is turned. On the other hand, we are inclined to say (though I haven't given much of an argument for this claim) that it is analytic, constitutive of the very idea of belief and desire, that when someone has certain beliefs and certain other desires he ought to behave a certain way. This difference is important, I think. It suggests that (insofar as these oughts are normative) the belief and desire attributions are normative themselves, while the proposition that someone turned the key in the ignition is not. V. Toward a Solution Maybe there are two different ways in which something could 'make sense' to do. Or rather, as an expressivist would prefer to put it, there are two different 140 JAMES DREIER

6 things we can do by saying that something 'makes sense'. One thing we can do is to express norms approving of that sort of thing. The other thing we can do also makes use of norms, but does not express them. We can say, for instance, that in Monopoly it makes sense to build houses as soon as you own a monopoly, or that in chess it makes sense to castle early, or that in a close baseball game it makes sense to sacrifice a baserunner to second. Sometimes we might be expressing our approval of such tactics. But not always. Even if I think that baseball is a stupid waste of time, I can still see that it makes sense to use various tactics relative to the goals and rules of baseball itself. If I make this relativization explicit, or even if I leave it tacit, I drain the expressive (or as Hare says, 'prescriptive') function of the other- wise normative terms. Usually when I say what makes sense in a game, the norms to which I relativize are the goals of the game. But I may also relativize to the rules of the game. I can say what one 'may' do in chess (capture diagonally with a pawn), what one 'must not' do (move into check), what one is 'required' to do (move or interpose or capture the attacking piece if possible when in check). When I say such things, it is not always plausible to understand me as expressing norms I accept.8 I am not telling anyone what to do, except in the sense of telling them what to do if they are to play chess. Compare Blackburn: Consider the example of game-playing. Here, too, there is a definite normative order: a game is defined by its rules. There is a limit to the extent to which people can fail to conform to the rules. [57] You could break a rule of chess and still be said to be playing-just playing very badly, as a six year old who jumps his bishop over a pawn. But if you break too many rules too often, then we just don't count you as playing chess. And then we would stop telling you what you are 'required' to do, we'd say, "Oh, well, do what you like, of course, but that isn't chess." To summarize the point of the analogy with games: Some rules are regulative, and the normative judgments powered by them express normative attitudes. Some rules are constitutive, and the normative judgments underwritten by them are analytic. Maybe the words 'belief and 'desire' and the verb 'to value' are like that. We cannot attribute beliefs and desires without 'buying into' the normative game that defines them, any more than we can speak seriously about promises while staying neutral about whether the man we say has promised has really obligated himself, or speak seriously about 'castling' without invoking the rules of chess. 8 Thanks to John Devlin for forcing me to see this point, which now seems perfectly obvious, but which I inexplicably resisted at the time. Thanks also to Russ Shafer-Landau for helpful comments. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 141

7 Suppose this is right. What does it mean for expressivist analysis of normative expressions? I think the upshot is that the analysis can be given, but expressivists have to be careful in giving it. I suggest a judicious use of the operator, so-called. If I am speaking with or about the adherents of a religion I do not share, I might say that chastity is a so-called virtue and pride a so-called sin. I mean that chastity is a virtue according to that religion, and pride a sin according to it. The operator keeps me clear of commitment myself. In a real conversation, I might often just say that chastity is a virtue and pride a sin, leaving the audience to supply the inverted commas. Note that by saying that pride is a so-called sin, I am not saying that it isn't a sin. In avowing my atheism, I might say something like, "It's all a mistake, there is no such thing as sin, so pride is no sin." But the assertion that pride is not a sin is most naturally understood as a "move within the game," and I don't want to be playing the game. And in giving their analysis of normative expressions, expressivists (nowadays) certainly do not want to say things like, "It's all a mistake, there is nothing at all that we ought to do." In presenting their analyses, they don't mean to be playing at all. So my suggestion is that expressivists should say something like this: Saying what people ought to do is expressing a so-called desire that such things be done. Of course, the attitude could be any of a number; I have chosen desire only as an example. This analysis is free from the circularity problem. The norms that are built in to the concept of desire are not expressed here, though they are made use of; the notion of a so-called desire is not a normative notion but a descriptive one, so no norms are invoked in giving the analysis. Suppose I am trying to explain to you the chess game on television. "White is in whatthey-call check," I say. If I said that white was in check, I could not resist the conclusion that white must move his king. But I do not want to draw that conclusion, because I think chess is a dangerous throwback to feudal values, so I want to say instead that white ought to insist on moving his pawns forward, thus engaging in radical rebellion against the oppressive FIDE lords. With approximately equal plausibility, I might decline to call your mental state a 'desire to avoid dogs', because I do not want to be committed to the conclusion that you ought to run away when you see a dog approaching. Instead my attitude toward people in your mental state is that I approve of them hugging any nearby dog. So I say instead that you have a so-called desire to avoid dogs. Of course, the bizarre attitudes aren't the only reasons for avoiding committing oneself to one norm or another; I might instead be doing metaphysics. Not that metaphysicians of normativity are frightened of 142 JAMES DREIER

8 commitment, or that they have bizarre attitudes, but the explanation they are giving would be ruined if it included a normative judgment. Needless to say, I hope, I am not claiming to have shown that any particular expressivist analysis is correct, nor that the general expressivist approach is correct. My goal is much more limited: to show how an expressivist analysis might explain normativity without invoking it. BOOK SYMPOSIUM 143

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN

Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN Grazer Philosophische Studien 80 (2010), 333 337. Terence CUNEO, The Normative Web. An Argument for Moral Realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008, 263 pp., 46.99, ISBN 978-0-19-921883-7. 1. Meta-ethics

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci

HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE. David Faraci Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy Vol. 12, No. 3 December 2017 https://doi.org/10.26556/jesp.v12i3.279 2017 Author HYBRID NON-NATURALISM DOES NOT MEET THE SUPERVENIENCE CHALLENGE David Faraci I t

More information

The normativity of content and the Frege point

The normativity of content and the Frege point The normativity of content and the Frege point Jeff Speaks March 26, 2008 In Assertion, Peter Geach wrote: A thought may have just the same content whether you assent to its truth or not; a proposition

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University

THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM. Matti Eklund Cornell University THE FREGE-GEACH PROBLEM AND KALDERON S MORAL FICTIONALISM Matti Eklund Cornell University [me72@cornell.edu] Penultimate draft. Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Quarterly I. INTRODUCTION In his

More information

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN

Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, ISBN Bart Streumer, Unbelievable Errors, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017. ISBN 9780198785897. Pp. 223. 45.00 Hbk. In The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, Bertrand Russell wrote that the point of philosophy

More information

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth

Reactions & Debate. Non-Convergent Truth Reactions & Debate Non-Convergent Truth Response to Arnold Burms. Disagreement, Perspectivism and Consequentialism. Ethical Perspectives 16 (2009): 155-163. In Disagreement, Perspectivism and Consequentialism,

More information

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ

HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ HAVE WE REASON TO DO AS RATIONALITY REQUIRES? A COMMENT ON RAZ BY JOHN BROOME JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY SYMPOSIUM I DECEMBER 2005 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JOHN BROOME 2005 HAVE WE REASON

More information

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD?

DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD? DO NORMATIVE JUDGEMENTS AIM TO REPRESENT THE WORLD? Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl Ratio 26 (2013): 450-470 Also in Bart Streumer (ed.), Irrealism in Ethics Published version available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/rati.12035

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford

Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1. Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford Philosophical Perspectives, 16, Language and Mind, 2002 THE AIM OF BELIEF 1 Ralph Wedgwood Merton College, Oxford 0. Introduction It is often claimed that beliefs aim at the truth. Indeed, this claim has

More information

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY

TWO ACCOUNTS OF THE NORMATIVITY OF RATIONALITY DISCUSSION NOTE BY JONATHAN WAY JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE DECEMBER 2009 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT JONATHAN WAY 2009 Two Accounts of the Normativity of Rationality RATIONALITY

More information

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory

Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory Fairfield University DigitalCommons@Fairfield Philosophy Faculty Publications Philosophy Department 1-1-2011 Hybridizing moral expressivism and moral error theory Toby Svoboda Fairfield University, tsvoboda@fairfield.edu

More information

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES

WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES WHY THERE REALLY ARE NO IRREDUCIBLY NORMATIVE PROPERTIES Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In David Bakhurst, Brad Hooker and Margaret Little (eds.), Thinking About Reasons: Essays in Honour of Jonathan

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Self-ascriptions of mental states, whether in speech or thought, seem to have a unique status. Suppose I make an utterance of the form I

More information

Moral Relativism Defended

Moral Relativism Defended 5 Moral Relativism Defended Gilbert Harman My thesis is that morality arises when a group of people reach an implicit agreement or come to a tacit understanding about their relations with one another.

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument

Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument University of Gothenburg Department of Philosophy, Linguistics and Theory of Science Shafer-Landau's defense against Blackburn's supervenience argument Author: Anna Folland Supervisor: Ragnar Francén Olinder

More information

Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism

Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism Moral Cognitivism vs. Non-Cognitivism First published Fri Jan 23, 2004; substantive revision Sun Jun 7, 2009 Non-cognitivism is a variety of irrealism about ethics with a number of influential variants.

More information

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY

THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY THE UNBELIEVABLE TRUTH ABOUT MORALITY Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl 9 August 2016 Forthcoming in Lenny Clapp (ed.), Philosophy for Us. San Diego: Cognella. Have you ever suspected that even though we

More information

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST:

HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: 1 HOW TO BE (AND HOW NOT TO BE) A NORMATIVE REALIST: A DISSERTATION OVERVIEW THAT ASSUMES AS LITTLE AS POSSIBLE ABOUT MY READER S PHILOSOPHICAL BACKGROUND Consider the question, What am I going to have

More information

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres

THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres FORO DE DEBATE / DEBATE FORUM 221 THE TACIT AND THE EXPLICIT A reply to José A. Noguera, Jesús Zamora-Bonilla, and Antonio Gaitán-Torres Stephen Turner turner@usf.edu University of South Florida. USA To

More information

MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier

MAKING REASONS EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier Forthcoming in Abstracta MAKING "REASONS" EXPLICIT HOW NORMATIVE IS BRANDOM'S INFERENTIALISM? Daniel Laurier daniel.laurier@umontreal.ca Abstract This paper asks whether Brandom (1994) has provided a sufficiently

More information

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM?

SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? 17 SWINBURNE ON THE EUTHYPHRO DILEMMA. CAN SUPERVENIENCE SAVE HIM? SIMINI RAHIMI Heythrop College, University of London Abstract. Modern philosophers normally either reject the divine command theory of

More information

A problem for expressivism

A problem for expressivism ANALYSIS 58.4 OCTOBER 1998 A problem for expressivism Frank Jackson & Philip Pettit 1. Introduction Language, Truth and Logic added expressivism to the inventory of substantive positions in meta-ethics,

More information

Aboutness and Justification

Aboutness and Justification For a symposium on Imogen Dickie s book Fixing Reference to be published in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. Aboutness and Justification Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu September 2016 Al believes

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University

David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University David Copp, ed., The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006, pp. 665. 0-19-514779-0. $74.00 (Hb). The Oxford Handbook of Ethical Theory contains twenty-two chapters written

More information

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS

PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 217 October 2004 ISSN 0031 8094 PHILOSOPHY OF LANGUAGE AND META-ETHICS BY IRA M. SCHNALL Meta-ethical discussions commonly distinguish subjectivism from emotivism,

More information

Solving the problem of creeping minimalism

Solving the problem of creeping minimalism Canadian Journal of Philosophy ISSN: 0045-5091 (Print) 1911-0820 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rcjp20 Solving the problem of creeping minimalism Matthew Simpson To cite this

More information

Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem

Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem Norm-Expressivism and the Frege-Geach Problem I. INTRODUCTION Megan Blomfield M oral non-cognitivism 1 is the metaethical view that denies that moral statements are truth-apt. According to this position,

More information

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis

Buck-Passers Negative Thesis Mark Schroeder November 27, 2006 University of Southern California Buck-Passers Negative Thesis [B]eing valuable is not a property that provides us with reasons. Rather, to call something valuable is to

More information

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames

What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames What is the Frege/Russell Analysis of Quantification? Scott Soames The Frege-Russell analysis of quantification was a fundamental advance in semantics and philosophical logic. Abstracting away from details

More information

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology

Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology Mark Schroeder s Hypotheticalism: Agent-neutrality, Moral Epistemology, and Methodology Forthcoming in a Philosophical Studies symposium on Mark Schroeder s Slaves of the Passions Tristram McPherson, University

More information

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity

Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Judith Jarvis Thomson s Normativity Gilbert Harman June 28, 2010 Normativity is a careful, rigorous account of the meanings of basic normative terms like good, virtue, correct, ought, should, and must.

More information

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer

PRACTICAL REASONING. Bart Streumer PRACTICAL REASONING Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl In Timothy O Connor and Constantine Sandis (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action Published version available here: http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444323528.ch31

More information

A DILEMMA FOR MORAL FICTIONALISM Matthew Chrisman University of Edinburgh

A DILEMMA FOR MORAL FICTIONALISM Matthew Chrisman University of Edinburgh A DILEMMA FOR MORAL FICTIONALISM Matthew Chrisman University of Edinburgh Forthcoming in Philosophical Books The most prominent anti-realist program in recent metaethics is the expressivist strategy of

More information

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology

Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology Review of Nathan M. Nobis s Truth in Ethics and Epistemology by James W. Gray November 19, 2010 (This is available on my website Ethical Realism.) Abstract Moral realism is the view that moral facts exist

More information

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION

EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION EXTERNALISM AND THE CONTENT OF MORAL MOTIVATION Caj Strandberg Department of Philosophy, Lund University and Gothenburg University Caj.Strandberg@fil.lu.se ABSTRACT: Michael Smith raises in his fetishist

More information

A CRITIQUE OF KRIPKE S FINITUDE ARGUMENT. In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language [WRPL], Kripke interprets Wittgenstein as

A CRITIQUE OF KRIPKE S FINITUDE ARGUMENT. In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language [WRPL], Kripke interprets Wittgenstein as 1 A CRITIQUE OF KRIPKE S FINITUDE ARGUMENT In Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language [WRPL], Kripke interprets Wittgenstein as wrestling with the following problem about meaning: Is there any fact

More information

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar

Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar Early Russell on Philosophical Grammar G. J. Mattey Fall, 2005 / Philosophy 156 Philosophical Grammar The study of grammar, in my opinion, is capable of throwing far more light on philosophical questions

More information

* Thanks to Mark Murphy for his very helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter.

* Thanks to Mark Murphy for his very helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter. RELIGION AND META-ETHICS * Michael Smith Religious accounts of ethics are as diverse as religious views themselves: think, for example, of the differences between the views of Muslims, Jews, Biblical literalists,

More information

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007

finagling frege Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007 Mark Schroeder University of Southern California September 25, 2007 finagling frege In his recent paper, Ecumenical Expressivism: Finessing Frege, Michael Ridge claims to show how to solve the famous Frege-Geach

More information

The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation

The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation The Puzzle of Pure Moral Motivation *Draft* 8/9/2016 Adam Lerner Dear CHillMeta readers: This is a long paper. For those of you who don t have enough time to read the whole thing, here is some guidance

More information

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists

Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists Epistemic Normativity for Naturalists 1. Naturalized epistemology and the normativity objection Can science help us understand what knowledge is and what makes a belief justified? Some say no because epistemic

More information

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God

Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Fr. Copleston vs. Bertrand Russell: The Famous 1948 BBC Radio Debate on the Existence of God Father Frederick C. Copleston (Jesuit Catholic priest) versus Bertrand Russell (agnostic philosopher) Copleston:

More information

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University 1. INTRODUCTION MAKING THINGS UP Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University The aim of philosophy, abstractly formulated, is to understand how things in the broadest possible

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth).

BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). BELIEF POLICIES, by Paul Helm. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994. Pp. xiii and 226. $54.95 (Cloth). TRENTON MERRICKS, Virginia Commonwealth University Faith and Philosophy 13 (1996): 449-454

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality INTRODUCTORY TEXT. Perhaps the most unsettling thought many of us have, often quite early on in childhood, is that the whole world might be a dream; that the

More information

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER

PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER PHENOMENALITY AND INTENTIONALITY WHICH EXPLAINS WHICH?: REPLY TO GERTLER Department of Philosophy University of California, Riverside Riverside, CA 92521 U.S.A. siewert@ucr.edu Copyright (c) Charles Siewert

More information

Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism?

Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism? Discussion Notes Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative Ethics: A Positive Contribution to the Literature on Objectivism? Eyal Mozes Bethesda, MD 1. Introduction Reviews of Tara Smith s Ayn Rand s Normative

More information

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism

James Rachels. Ethical Egoism James Rachels Ethical Egoism Psychological Egoism Ethical Egoism n Psychological Egoism: n Ethical Egoism: An empirical (descriptive) theory A normative (prescriptive) theory A theory about what in fact

More information

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10

The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10 The Limits of Normative Detachment 1 Nishi Shah Amherst College Draft of 04/15/10 Consider another picture of what it would be for a demand to be objectively valid. It is Kant s own picture. According

More information

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge In this essay I will survey some theories about the truth conditions of indicative and counterfactual conditionals.

More information

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION

CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION DISCUSSION NOTE CHECKING THE NEIGHBORHOOD: A REPLY TO DIPAOLO AND BEHRENDS ON PROMOTION BY NATHANIEL SHARADIN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE FEBRUARY 2016 Checking the Neighborhood:

More information

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981).

Utilitarianism: For and Against (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), pp Reprinted in Moral Luck (CUP, 1981). Draft of 3-21- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #14: Williams, Internalism, and

More information

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS

II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS Meeting of the Aristotelian Society held at Senate House, University of London, on 22 October 2012 at 5:30 p.m. II RESEMBLANCE NOMINALISM, CONJUNCTIONS AND TRUTHMAKERS The resemblance nominalist says that

More information

Annotated List of Ethical Theories

Annotated List of Ethical Theories Annotated List of Ethical Theories The following list is selective, including only what I view as the major theories. Entries in bold face have been especially influential. Recommendations for additions

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT

ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT The Southern Journal of Philosophy Volume 50, Issue 4 December 2012 ASSESSOR RELATIVISM AND THE PROBLEM OF MORAL DISAGREEMENT Karl Schafer abstract: I consider sophisticated forms of relativism and their

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

xiv Truth Without Objectivity Introduction There is a certain approach to theorizing about language that is called truthconditional semantics. The underlying idea of truth-conditional semantics is often summarized as the idea that

More information

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp.

Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp. Noncognitivism in Ethics, by Mark Schroeder. London: Routledge, 251 pp. Noncognitivism in Ethics is Mark Schroeder s third book in four years. That is very impressive. What is even more impressive is that

More information

SUBJECTIVISM ABOUT NORMATIVITY AND THE NORMATIVITY OF INTENTIONAL STATES Michael Gorman

SUBJECTIVISM ABOUT NORMATIVITY AND THE NORMATIVITY OF INTENTIONAL STATES Michael Gorman 1 SUBJECTIVISM ABOUT NORMATIVITY AND THE NORMATIVITY OF INTENTIONAL STATES Michael Gorman Norms of various sorts ethical, cognitive, and aesthetic, to name a few play an important role in human life. Not

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Prof. Dr. Thomas Grundmann Philosophisches Seminar Universität zu Köln Albertus Magnus Platz 50923 Köln E-mail: thomas.grundmann@uni-koeln.de 4.454 words Reliabilism

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Realism and Irrealism

Realism and Irrealism 1 Realism and Irrealism 1.1. INTRODUCTION It is surely an understatement to say that most of the issues that are discussed within meta-ethics appear esoteric to nonphilosophers. Still, many can relate

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

Divine command theory

Divine command theory Divine command theory Today we will be discussing divine command theory. But first I will give a (very) brief overview of the discipline of philosophy. Why do this? One of the functions of an introductory

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988)

BOOK REVIEWS. Duke University. The Philosophical Review, Vol. XCVII, No. 1 (January 1988) manner that provokes the student into careful and critical thought on these issues, then this book certainly gets that job done. On the other hand, one likes to think (imagine or hope) that the very best

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Philosophy in Review XXXI (2011), no. 5

Philosophy in Review XXXI (2011), no. 5 Richard Joyce and Simon Kirchin, eds. A World without Values: Essays on John Mackie s Moral Error Theory. Dordrecht: Springer 2010. 262 pages US$139.00 (cloth ISBN 978-90-481-3338-3) In 1977, John Leslie

More information

Transforming Expressivism

Transforming Expressivism NOÛS 33:4 ~1999! 558 572 Transforming Expressivism James Dreier Brown University In chapter five of Wise Choices, Apt Feelings Allan Gibbard develops what he calls a normative logic intended to solve some

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1. Frank Jackson

In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1. Frank Jackson In Defence Of Reductionism In Ethics 1 Frank Jackson This essay is concerned with Derek Parfit's critical discussion of naturalism in On What Matters (vol. 2, chs 25, 26 and 27). I explain why I am a naturalist

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism

Two Kinds of Moral Relativism p. 1 Two Kinds of Moral Relativism JOHN J. TILLEY INDIANA UNIVERSITY PURDUE UNIVERSITY INDIANAPOLIS jtilley@iupui.edu [Final draft of a paper that appeared in the Journal of Value Inquiry 29(2) (1995):

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Metaethics: An Introduction

Metaethics: An Introduction Metaethics: An Introduction Philosophy 202 (Winter 2010) Nate Charlow (ncharlo@umich.edu) CONTENTS 1 TAXONOMY 1 2 COGNITIVISM AND NON-COGNITIVISM 3 2.1 Why Be Non-cognitivist?...............................

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life Fall 2008 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. Three Moral Theories

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2

Intro to Ground. 1. The idea of ground. 2. Relata. are facts): F 1. More-or-less equivalent phrases (where F 1. and F 2. depends upon F 2 F 2 Intro to Ground Ted Sider Ground seminar 1. The idea of ground This essay is a plea for ideological toleration. Philosophers are right to be fussy about the words they use, especially in metaphysics where

More information

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. Reply to Southwood, Kearns and Star, and Cullity Author(s): by John Broome Source: Ethics, Vol. 119, No. 1 (October 2008), pp. 96-108 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/592584.

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information