World-Wide Ethics Chapter Five Deontology

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "World-Wide Ethics Chapter Five Deontology"

Transcription

1 World-Wide Ethics Chapter Five Deontology Utilitarian thinking, as seen in the previous chapter, focuses on the good and bad consequences of actions, or of action types. The reason why some actions are right and others are wrong, or why some moral rules are correct and others are incorrect, is what those actions and rules are expected to bring about. But might it not be, instead, that actions are right or wrong in themselves, apart from what they bring about? This idea is known as deontology, and in the study of ethics it is the main alternative to theories like utilitarianism. The word deontology comes from the idea of duty, which in ancient Greek was deon. A duty is an action that ought to be done, or that is morally required. Deontology, like utilitarianism, refers to a family of theories with a common element. In this case the common element is the recognition that some actions ought to be done simply for their own sakes. Actions are right not because of the good consequences they can bring about, as in utilitarianism, but because of the type of actions they are. For this reason the moral principles of deontological theories are often expressed in commands, or imperatives. Historically, this goes back as far as the Ten Commandments. A number of those commandments express religious duties, to God: such as not taking his name in vain, or keeping the sabbath day (seventh day) holy. But most of them are general moral imperatives, like Thou shalt not kill! Thou shalt not lie! and Thou shalt not commit adultery! The command-structure of morality, in deontological theories, suggests that morality itself commands our obedience, regardless of what our actions may bring about. If God or society may somehow determine what our duties are, it is morality itself that imbues them with authority. Suppose, for example, that you are a soldier who must report to your post at 1:00 for guard duty. The fact that it is your duty to be at your post at that time would be determined by your commanding officer. But commanding officers are not authorized to determine the duties of their subordinates merely through their own power, or just because they say so. They are authorized by the command-structure of the army, which can also place limits on what they are entitled to command. Similarly, if the duties in deontology may be derived from God, or society, this would only be so if these sources of duties are authorized to command, like military officers. The Bhagavad Gita The military model of duty is celebrated in The Bhagavad Gita, a scripture from ancient India, from around 300 BC. Often called the Geeta, for short, it relates the story of a reluctant warrior-prince named Arjuna. On the eve of a great battle, in a civil war, Arjuna is struck by the recognition that the opposing army he must fight includes a number of his relatives: cousins and uncles, and even grandfathers. He therefore wonders whether it can be worth it to do his duty and fight the battle, considering what the result is likely to be. Wouldn t it be better, he wonders, to allow his relatives to kill him, than for him to kill them, and then grieve for their loss? Seeking guidance, he prays to the god Krishna: My compassionate nature is overcome by the dread of sin [if I do not do my duty]. Tell me truly what may be best for me to do. I am thy 1

2 disciple, wherefore instruct me in my duty, who am under thy tuition; for my understanding is confounded by the dictates of my duty. The god then appears to Arujna, and in a long discourse, encourages him to do his duty, no matter what. If thou art slain thou wilt obtain heaven; if thou art victorious thou wilt enjoy a world for thy reward; wherefore, son of Kunti, arise and be determined for the battle. Make pleasure and pain, gain and loss, victory and defeat, the same, and then prepare for battle; thus thou shalt not incur sin. The doctrine here declared to you is according to the Sánkhya; hear now the Yoga (teaching). Let the motive be in the deed and not in the fruit. Be not one whose motive for action is the hope of reward. Let not thy life be spent in inaction. Steadfast in devotion, perform thy duty, abandon all thought of the consequence, and make the event equal, whether it terminate in good or evil. The doctrine of Sánkhya Yoga that Krishna teaches includes the idea that by following the dictates of our duty, without question, everything will work out right in the end. So we need not think of consequences, and shrink from doing our duty because of anticipated pleasure or pain, good or evil. This is part of a larger view of human life that is explained in the Gita. According to this view we are all, in reality, invisible and immortal souls, who are connected to virtually worthless bodies. For this reason, Arjuna s killing his relatives in battle, or their killing him, will have no effect on what is real. The warriors on both sides are expected to do their duties, and if they do, then in the end all will be equal, come what may. That is the meaning of those two lines of advice from Krishna: Make pleasure and pain, gain and loss, victory and defeat, the same and make the event equal. All that is under our control in life is whether we do our duty or not. The consequences of what we do are not under our control. The ethics of deontology makes us subject to praise and blame only for what we can control, only for doing our duty. If things go awry once we do our duty, that cannot be our fault. Often, as in the example of the Gita, deontological theories suggest that some higher power can be relied on to make everything equal for those who do their duty. What may appear to us as a bad consequence of doing our duty will be, in the end, offset by some good we are presently unable to recognize. Not all deontological theories are like this, however. Kantian Ethics Late in the 18 th century, the German philosopher Immanuel Kant ( ) provided what seems still to be the most complete and non-religious development of deontology. For this reason, the moral theory he explained is today often equated with deontology itself. That is, when people think of deontology they inevitably think of Kantian ethics, even though Kant never used the term deontology. It was not invented until about twenty years after his death. When we use a phrase like Kantian Ethics to refer to a theory in ethics, this is comparable to the way scientists use Newtonian Physics to refer to a theory in physics. Sometimes, the theories that philosophers and scientists introduce are so unique and revolutionary that their names become permanently associated with them. We do not expect a deontological theory to tell us merely the tautology that we ought to do our duty. We expect such a theory to provide one or more principles that express what our duties are; and we expect it to explain why those principles are correct. Kant understood these expectations very well. At the beginning, he emphasized the classic doctrine of deontology that our moral duties are expected to be done for their own 2

3 sake, and not for any good consequences. From only this assumption, he reasoned, it is possible to learn what our duties are. It is possible to derive one basic principle, in the form of a command, that expresses all of our duties. Here are five steps that more or less represent Kant s thinking. First, duty for duty s sake. If we are expected to do our duty for its own sake, then this tells us that our duties cannot be based at all on any of the good consequences of our actions as the utilitarians thought. Second, desires and feelings cannot determine duties. The consequences of doing our duty could interest us only because of our feelings of pleasures or pains, or only because of our desires. So this tells us that since our duties cannot be based on good consequences, they cannot be based on our feelings or desires. Third, duties determined by reason. The only thing left, once feelings and desires are ruled out, is intellect, or reason. Everyone understands that some actions are reasonable, while others are unreasonable; and everyone understands that an action s being reasonable recommends it, and that an action s being unreasonable is a recommendation against it. Fourth, reason s universality. Whenever we are led to a conclusion by reasoning, we can always expect everyone else to follow our line of reasoning, and agree. We are led to conclusions by reasoning in geometry and algebra, for example. So the same should be true about reasoning in ethics. Reasoning is universal meaning that everyone can be expected to follow a line of reasoning; and, if it is sound, they will be forced to accept the truth of its conclusion. Fifth, duties based on universality. Since moral duties must be based in reason, reason s universality is the clue to discovering what our duties are. If a way of acting cannot be adopted universally, by everyone, then it is not right. The Categorical Imperative The basic moral principle of Kant s deontological ethics, which is based on the preceding five steps of his thinking, is a command called the categorical imperative. There is a technical reason why that name is appropriate in his theory; but here is not the place to go into that. This is what Kant s categorical imperative says: Statement of the Categorical Imperative Act only on the maxim that you can will to become a universal law. The principle of the categorical imperative is offered as a summary of all our moral duties. Kant s thinking was that if people always follow this command in their actions, then they will always do their duty, their actions will always be right; and any action can be identified as wrong if its maxim cannot become a universal law. What is a maxim? For reasons related to the history of philosophy, Kant believed that everyone would understand what he meant by the term, maxim. But people today do not readily understand this. The way the word is used today bears only a faint resemblance to what Kant meant. Today a maxim is something like a rule of thumb, or motto to live by. If one person adheres to a certain maxim, this does not mean that others do. So for this reason maxims are thought of along the lines of personal policies. Never let an insult go unavenged, might be someone s maxim; someone else might have as one of her maxims: Always look before you leap. As Kant understood the idea of a maxim, as employed in his categorical imperative, it would be possible to form a maxim for every one of a person s actions. The difference between the actions of animals and of human beings is that human beings can always explain why they are doing what 3

4 they are doing. When humans act deliberately, they can always think, or say, I m doing [this action] in order to bring about [this result]. To be slightly more informative they can add another bit of information, I m doing [this action] [in these circumstances] in order to bring about [this result]. This is what Kant had in mind in referring to a maxim. It is technically a three-part statement of action-explanation. A maxim rationalizes an action, meaning that it gives the reason why the action makes sense to the person doing it; and can make sense to others. What is a universal law? This is any law that everyone is expected to follow. Laws of nature are universal laws in this sense. Everyone can be expected to follow the law of gravity in fact, no one can fail to follow it. When in the categorical imperative Kant refers to a maxim s becoming a universal law, he has in mind something like its becoming a law of human nature. He is thinking of a maxim as if it is no longer a rule of action-explanation for a person, but a rule followed by all persons, everywhere, like the law of gravity. So if our duty is to act only on maxims that can become universal laws, this means that we can tell whether any action is right or wrong by thinking of its maxim as if it were everyone s maxim. The personal reference to I in the maxim is replaced by Everyone : Everyone does [this action] [in these circumstances] in order to bring about [this result]. A maxim s becoming a law of nature would mean not only that we all observe that law, but also that we all know we all observe it. So it turns out that, for some maxims, everyone s acting that way, while also knowing that everyone acts that way, makes no sense. That is the precise indication of an action s wrongness. Kant s most well understood example of an action shown to be wrong by the categorical imperative is a lying promise. Suppose a man is desperately in need of money, and comes up with the plan to borrow the money he needs, and to assure the lender that he will pay it back, even though he knows he will not be able to. Here is Kant s explanation of the case. Lying Promise Example [T]he maxim of his action would be as follows: When I believe myself to be in need of money, I will borrow money and promise to repay it, although I know I shall never do so... [He] then puts the question: How would it be if my maxim became a universal law? He immediately sees that it could never hold a universal law of [human] nature. For the universality of a law which says that anyone who believes himself to be in need could promise what he pleased with the intention of not fulfilling it would make the promise itself, and the end to be accomplished by it, impossible; no one would believe what was promised to him but would only laugh at any such assertion. Kant s categorical imperative says, in short, that we can tell whether actions are right by asking, What if everyone acted that way? If everyone s acting that way is impossible, or cannot bring about the result the action would be intended to achieve, then acting that way is not right. Kant believed that every action type that we already know to be wrong, lying, cheating, killing, etc., will fail the universalization test of the categorical imperative, and that is precisely why it is wrong. For actions about which we are not so confident, he believed, all we need to do is apply the categorical imperative test to their maxims, and we ll have the answer. The Golden Rule Kant knew the moral principle that many today call the golden rule roughly: Always treat others in ways you would want them to 4

5 treat you. This statement, in the form of an imperative, seems to capture much of what Kant had in mind with the categorical imperative, and it is much simpler. For example, since you would not want anyone to borrow money from you when they know they cannot pay it back, this shows why it would be wrong for you to act that way. Kant did not favor the golden rule, however. Although its simplicity is a point in its favor, it turns out to be too simple. One of the problems with the golden rule, he pointed out, is that there are many circumstances in which people should not adopt the attitude of equal treatment recommended by that rule. Sometimes, because of their relationships, people ought to treat others in ways they would not want to be treated. Kant gave the example of a judge sentencing a convicted criminal. The judge should do what is right, and not be lenient in sentencing, even though, if she were the criminal, she would want a light sentence. Another example involves helping people in need. Some people feel they are independent and self-reliant, or at least they aspire to live that way. They would not welcome anyone s helping them, even if they were in a desperate situation they would want to rely on their own wits and skills. So by the golden rule, it would be wrong for people with this attitude to help anyone else. But that does not seem like a correct result. If they know of others who needed their help, and would like to receive it, then it seems they should be permitted to help them. An additional problem Kant recognized with the golden rule is that it is about treating other people, only. It does not provide any guidance for how we ought to treat ourselves; and he thought that some of our moral duties do address the treatment of ourselves. For example, Kant had some ideas about circumstances in which suicide would be wrong. He also supposed that people ought, morally, to develop their natural talents. He thought it would wrong for someone, like a mathematical prodigy, to choose to squander his time and energies on trivial things like playing solitaire, or memorizing names in a phonebook. He thought also that servility is wrong, which is allowing yourself to be used by others, however they please. Servility shows a lack of self-respect. Treating others as you prefer to be treated is important for morality, Kant thought. But most important is equal respect for yourself and for others. One of Kant s great ideas was that because they are rational, all human beings deserve a basic level of respect for their dignity. There are wrong ways to treat other human beings, even wrong ways to treat yourself, because of human dignity. Respecting human dignity means refusing to act against human beings in these ways, no matter what the consequences may be for overall happiness. This is the fundamental insight behind the modern idea of human rights. Are Consequences Always Irrelevant? If a deontological theory like Kant s tells us that the rightness of actions never has anything to do with their consequences, then, to most people, that seems like a problem. Perhaps, if we believe in a grand doctrine like Sánkhya Yoga, as taught by Krishna, we can feel comfortable about ignoring the consequence of our actions completely. But a lot of people do not. So it looks like Kant s theory of the categorical imperative will have a problem when the consequences of doing the right thing turn out to be seriously bad. A famous objection arose for Kant s theory along these lines, not long after he explained it. The Case of the Inquiring Murderer. Is it always wrong to lie, even if by doing so you 5

6 can prevent someone from murdering a friend of yours? Suppose someone has threatened to kill your friend, Megan; and suppose she comes to your house to hide. You invite her in, and let her hide upstairs. But not long afterwards, you hear the doorbell ring. It is the man who wants to murder Megan, and he is asking whether she is hiding in your house. Now if you want to protect her, you would answer that she is not in your house, and add, perhaps, that you think she is out of town. But saying these things would be lying. The categorical imperative tells us that if it were a universal law that everyone lies in order to protect their friends lives, then, as in the lying-promise example, no one would believe what you would say in this situation. So the categorical imperative seems to say that lying to protect Megan is wrong. You could instead try to avoid lying by changing the subject, or by evading the question in some other way. But then the man would know that, because you are not giving the simple yes or no answer he is looking for, you are hiding something or in this case, someone. So it seems that your options are to lie, to tell the truth, or to do neither, and by your odd behavior convey the truthful answer to the murderer. Things don t look good for Megan, if you are not willing to lie. This case, and many variations on the same idea, has posed one of the most serious stumbling blocks to acceptance of Kant s theory. This case makes it seem that actions consequences must matter after all. It makes it seem that we cannot seriously believe that lying must always be wrong, as the categorical imperative seems to say. Not surprisingly, act utilitarians think that the case of the inquiring murder shows the superiority of their theory to Kant s. They would say that of course the lie is right, considering the fatal consequences of not lying. So does the case of the inquiring murderer refute deontology? Some philosophers have thought that it only defeat s Kant s version of deontology. They have thought that other types of deontology can be developed, which do not say we must always tell the truth, no matter the circumstances. Prima Facie Duties In the 1930s, an English philosopher named W. D. Ross developed a deontological theory that deals somewhat differently with hard cases like the case of the inquiring murderer. His key idea was that duties like truth-telling are only prima facie. In Latin, this means first face. The idea is that lying is wrong in the abstract, but in concrete circumstances, like the case of the inquiring murderer, lying might be right. So, in a sense, Ross s theory of prima facie duties say that truth-telling is one of our basic duties, but there can be exceptions to it. Ross would not want to be classified as any kind of utilitarian, however. He did not think that exceptions to prima facie duties are based on utility. He did not think, in other words, that it would be right to tell a lie if the result is the greatest happiness for the greatest number. As a deontologist, Ross theorized that we have a whole set of prima facie duties, and truth-telling is one among them. If we are in a situation where truth-telling is called for, and no other prima facie duty applies in the situation, then in that situation we ought to tell the truth. It would be wrong not to do so. But if there may ever be another duty present also, like a duty keep a promise, or a duty to protect someone from harm each of which would be a prima facie duty then whether we should tell the truth or not depends on what Ross would call the stringency of the other duties. In the case of the inquiring murder he would say that 6

7 the duty to protect your friend is more stringent, or more compelling, than the duty to tell the truth; so in that circumstance, that is the duty that we should fulfill. Most people think that this is the correct response to that case. Ross would put it technically like this: the prima facie duty that is most stringent for the situation in this case the duty to protect your friend, Megan is the actual duty for the situation. We ought always to do our actual duty; and we determine what our actual duty is by comparing the set of prima facie duties that apply in any situation. We do not calculate the utilities of our alternative actions. Rather, we settle on what seems actually right by first considering all that seems prima facie right. Evidence for Prima Facie Duties In thinking about the practice of promising, Ross noticed a part of that practice that utilitarians have difficulty explaining. All of us recognize that sometimes we cannot keep promises we have made, and we have good reasons why we cannot. Ross s example is this: suppose you have agreed to meet someone at 3:00, for some trivial purpose. And on your way to the meeting you come across someone in distress, and in need of your help. Here you have a duty to keep your promise, but also a duty to help someone the duty to be a good Samaritan. A utilitarian might say that depending on the happiness at stake the happiness of everyone affected it could be right to help the person, even if it means breaking your promise to meet at 3:00. Ross would agree that this could be right. But what he noticed is this. The duty of promise-keeping does not simply vanish because helping the person in need is right. The duty is thought to remain; because when you next see the person you agreed to meet, you ought to apologize. This is something the utilitarian seems unable explain. Suppose that if you had kept the promise, you would have done something wrong. The utilitarian would think that keeping the promise would have been wrong if helping the person in distress would have produced greater utility. But then when you next see that person, why, according to the utilitarian, should you have to apologize? Are you expected to say, I m sorry for not meeting you at 3:00, which would have been the wrong thing for me to do? As the utilitarian must see it, your duty to keep the promise vanished from the scene with the appearance of another action that would lead to greater utility so no apology should be expected you actually did not have a duty to keep the promise. This does not seem like the correct explanation, however. It seems rather that even though it can sometimes be right to break a promise, the fact of the promise leaves something like a moral residue. The broken promise continues demanding to be addressed, so to speak. Ross thought that the idea of promising s being a prima facie duty explains this very well. For promisekeeping, and for many other duties besides, when they are not the most stringent duties in our circumstances and so not our actual duties they will not be cancelled so much as dimmed, or blurred. They can still require that we act in certain ways, even if we can no longer act in the ways they would have required, if they were our actual duties. So a prima facie duty of promise-keeping can require that we apologize if we are unable to keep a promise like meeting someone at 3:00, because some other duty came up that was more stringent. 7

8 Knowing by Intuition In listing our prima facie duties, Ross s theory provides a set of moral principles. He did not claim that this list is complete, but he thought that it at least seemed to capture what most people think morality requires of us. List of prima facie duties 1. Duties depending on one s prior actions: a. Duty of fidelity (promise-keeping) b. Duty of reparation (restitution) 2. Duty of gratitude 3. Duty of justice 4. Duty of beneficence (doing good for others) 5. Duty of self-improvement 6. Duty of non-maleficence (not harming) But how do we know these principles are correct? How do we know these action types really are our duties, even if they are only prima facie duties? Ross answered that we know this by what he calls intuition. This is a way of knowing something without perceiving it with our senses. He thought it is self-evident that justice and beneficence and non-maleficence are among our duties. He could of course count on everyone s agreeing with him that they are; but most philosophers have not found his answer to be very satisfactory. One reason it has seemed unsatisfactory is that Ross s theory presents a number of moral principles indicating the specific duties we have. It emphasizes, also, that these duties can conflict. In some circumstances, one duty tells us to act one way, and another duty tells us to act differently. Saying that we all know our prima facie duties by intuition does not help us decide which are our actual duties. It may be selfevident to everyone that we have a prima facie duty to keep promises, and a prima facie duty to help people in distress, but it is not self-evident, in any situation, which one would be our actual duty. This is not selfevident, because people sometimes disagree over which duty is actual; and they could not disagree if this were self-evident any more than they could disagree over the sum of 2+2. Ross said that we do not know our actual duties by intuition; we only know our prima facie duties that way. The fact is, he admitted, that when prima facie duties conflict, we really cannot know what our actual duties are. We can all agree that we ought to tell the truth, and that we ought to prevent murders if we can. But according to Ross and this part is a little strange we can never be certain, in any circumstance, that preventing a murder is a more stringent duty than telling the truth. Perhaps that seems like a better result than provided by Kant s theory, which seems to tell us that we can be certain that telling the truth is always more stringent. But most philosophers have hoped to do better. Most expect a moral theory to provide a way to tell what our actual duties would be, in any situation. It should be expected to help us see not only what moral principles are correct, but also, if more than one can apply to a given situation, which one takes priority. Chapter Summary The central focus of deontological moral theories is on the idea of duty, or on what ought to be done. Theories like this invoke a kind of military model, where moral principles are like commands from a higher authority that must be obeyed no matter what. That is, it does not matter what consequences may be expected from doing our duty. We act rightly by doing our duties, and wrongly by not doing them. Two of the most highly regarded deontological theories have been provided by Immanuel Kant, in the 18 th century, and by Sir David Ross, in the 20 th century. Kant 8

9 assumed that all of our moral duties can be captured by one simple moral principle expressed in what he called the categorical imperative. His idea was basically that our duty is to act only in ways that could become laws of (human) nature that is, ways in which everyone else could be expected to act, in the same circumstances. So, to oversimplify just a bit, lying would be wrong because if everyone was a liar, then no one would believe what anyone says, and thus there would be no point to lying. Kant s categorical imperative resembles the principle of the golden rule ; but there are cases where the two principles differ. A difficult problem that Kant s theory has had to face is that the categorical imperative seems to say that lying would be wrong, even in order to save someone s life. This is something that act utilitarians point to as a great advantage of their theory, over deontological theories like Kant s. For it seems obvious that telling a lie in order to save a life would bring about greater happiness, at least some of the time. According to Ross s version of deontology, moral duties like the duty not to lie are only prima facie duties. This means that circumstances can present more than one duty, in conflict, and then the most stringent among them would be the actual duty for the circumstances. For example, it is a prima facie duty not to lie, and it is a prima facie duty to help people in need, especially if you can save their lives. If it should happen that you can save someone s life by telling a lie, then saving the life is probably what Ross would call the actual duty in the circumstance. This would not be because it would produce greater happiness, but simply because, in this case, the duty to save the life is more stringent. A problem looming for Ross s theory, is that it can be hard to tell which prima facie duty is more stringent than another. In fact, Ross himself thought that we probably cannot ever be certain about this. Where We Go from Here Suppose it were possible somehow to combine utilitarian interests in bringing about good results, with the deontological emphasis on duty. Such a combination might yield the best of both worlds. The next chapter presents a family of theories that combines an interest in overall happiness, like utilitarianism, with a command structure like deontology. It resembles rule utilitarianism in some ways, but not in other ways. It can also resemble cultural relativism, because it presents morality as arising from some of the basic requirements for living in society. It is called the social contract theory, and it suggests that morality is based on a fundamental agreement that people would make for living together peacefully in society. The basic assumption of this type of theory is that human beings are overall happier living together in social settings, provided they submit themselves to some basic social rules, as duties. So moral principles can be expressed as social duties, and the benefits of social life can be expected to result from people s adhering to their duties in society especially duties like justice, or fairness. Of the three families of philosophical theories, utilitarianism, deontology and social contract, the contract theory seems like the most advantageous theoretical model for ethics especially for the part of ethics dealing with human rights. Works Cited The Bhagavad Gita: with an English Translation, Explanatory Notes and an Examination of Its Doctrines (London: The Christian Literature Society for India, 1899). 9

10 Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. Lewis White Beck (New York: Macmillan, 1990). 39. Terms Introduced Duty: in ethics, an action that ought, morally, to be done; it can also be our moral duty not to act in certain ways, like lying. Deontology is the moral theory, or family of moral theories, that emphasizes duties. Categorical Imperative: in the ethical theory of Immanuel Kant ( ), the basic principle that can tell us what our moral duties are, expressed as a command. Though Kant provided different versions of this principle, it basically says: Act only on maxims that can become universal laws. Maxims: in Kant s ethics, these are personal rules or principles that people follow in acting. Although people may not be conscious of their maxims when they act, their maxims express the reason or rationale behind their actions. For example, someone s maxim might be: When I stayed up late the night before, and there is not an exam in my early class the next day, I ll skip the class in order to catch up on my sleep. Some people act on that maxim very frequently. Universality, or Universal law: in Kant s ethics, a maxim is treated as a universal law when it is supposed that everyone would act on the maxim. If everyone cannot act on a maxim having become a universal law, then, by the categorical imperative, anyone s acting on that maxim is morally wrong it is everyone s duty not to act that way. Maxims that involve lying are a good example of this, since if everyone expects everyone else always to lie, then no one ever believes what anyone says. The Golden Rule: In one formulation: Always treat others in ways you would want them to treat you (see also Terms Introduced in Chapter 1). The golden rule is a deontological moral principle it is not assumed to be correct because of any overall good consequences of acting that way. Kant s categorical imperative resembles the golden rule in some respects, but not in others. For example, in Kant s theory, moral principles can apply to actions that affect only ourselves; but the golden rule is about actions that affect others, only. Prima Facie Duties: in Latin, prima facie means something like first face, or upon first appearance. In W. D. Ross s deontological theory, some action types are prima facie duties, such a promise-keeping. This means that we ought to keep our promises, but there can be circumstances where we also ought to do something else. Prima facie duties are sometimes called conditional duties. Actual Duty: in Ross s theory, the prima facie duty that is most stringent in the circumstances. Actual duties are sometimes called absolute duties. Intuition: in Ross s theory, this is how we know the set of our prima facie duties. Things we know by intuition are said to be self-evident. 10

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions

Suppose... Kant. The Good Will. Kant Three Propositions Suppose.... Kant You are a good swimmer and one day at the beach you notice someone who is drowning offshore. Consider the following three scenarios. Which one would Kant says exhibits a good will? Even

More information

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to:

Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS CHAPTER OBJECTIVES. After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: Chapter 3 PHILOSOPHICAL ETHICS AND BUSINESS MGT604 CHAPTER OBJECTIVES After exploring this chapter, you will be able to: 1. Explain the ethical framework of utilitarianism. 2. Describe how utilitarian

More information

Philosophy 1100: Ethics

Philosophy 1100: Ethics Philosophy 1100: Ethics Topic 7: Ross Theory of Prima Facie Duties 1. Something all our theories have had in common 2. W.D. Ross 3. The Concept of a Prima Facie Duty 4. Ross List of Prima Facie Duties

More information

W.D. Ross ( )

W.D. Ross ( ) W.D. Ross (1877-1971) British philosopher Translator or Aristotle Defends a pluralist theory of morality in his now-classic book The Right and the Good (1930) Big idea: prima facie duties Prima Facie Duties

More information

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill)

KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) KANTIAN ETHICS (Dan Gaskill) German philosopher Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was an opponent of utilitarianism. Basic Summary: Kant, unlike Mill, believed that certain types of actions (including murder,

More information

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS

DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS DEONTOLOGICAL ETHICS In ethical theories, if we mainly focus on the action itself, then we use deontological ethics (also known as deontology or duty ethics). In duty ethics, an action is morally right

More information

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed.

-- did you get a message welcoming you to the cours reflector? If not, please correct what s needed. 1 -- did you get a message welcoming you to the coursemail reflector? If not, please correct what s needed. 2 -- don t use secondary material from the web, as its quality is variable; cf. Wikipedia. Check

More information

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3

Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3 Critical Reasoning and Moral theory day 3 CS 340 Fall 2015 Ethics and Moral Theories Differences of opinion based caused by different value set Deontology Virtue Religious and Divine Command Utilitarian

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6

SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 SUMMARIES AND TEST QUESTIONS UNIT 6 Textbook: Louis P. Pojman, Editor. Philosophy: The quest for truth. New York: Oxford University Press, 2006. ISBN-10: 0199697310; ISBN-13: 9780199697311 (6th Edition)

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics

Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics Chapter 2 Reasoning about Ethics TRUE/FALSE 1. The statement "nearly all Americans believe that individual liberty should be respected" is a normative claim. F This is a statement about people's beliefs;

More information

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons

Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons Kant, Deontology, & Respect for Persons Some Possibly Helpful Terminology Normative moral theories can be categorized according to whether the theory is primarily focused on judgments of value or judgments

More information

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I Participation Quiz Pick an answer between A E at random. What answer (A E) do you think will have been selected most frequently in the previous poll? Recap: Unworkable

More information

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions

Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Florida Philosophical Review Volume X, Issue 1, Summer 2010 75 Deontology, Rationality, and Agent-Centered Restrictions Brandon Hogan, University of Pittsburgh I. Introduction Deontological ethical theories

More information

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics

Lecture 12 Deontology. Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics Lecture 12 Deontology Onora O Neill A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics 1 Agenda 1. Immanuel Kant 2. Deontology 3. Hypothetical vs. Categorical Imperatives 4. Formula of the End in Itself 5. Maxims and

More information

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert

Take Home Exam #2. PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert PHI 1700: Global Ethics Prof. Lauren R. Alpert Name: Date: Take Home Exam #2 Instructions (Read Before Proceeding!) Material for this exam is from class sessions 8-15. Matching and fill-in-the-blank questions

More information

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life

24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life MIT OpenCourseWare http://ocw.mit.edu 24.02 Moral Problems and the Good Life Fall 2008 For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: http://ocw.mit.edu/terms. Three Moral Theories

More information

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics

A Categorical Imperative. An Introduction to Deontological Ethics A Categorical Imperative An Introduction to Deontological Ethics Better Consequences, Better Action? More specifically, the better the consequences the better the action from a moral point of view? Compare:

More information

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics.

Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. PHI 110 Lecture 29 1 Hello again. Today we re gonna continue our discussions of Kant s ethics. Last time we talked about the good will and Kant defined the good will as the free rational will which acts

More information

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result.

Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be able to follow it and come to the same result. QUIZ 1 ETHICAL ISSUES IN MEDIA, BUSINESS AND SOCIETY WHAT IS ETHICS? Business ethics deals with values, facts, and arguments. Q2) The test of an ethical argument lies in the fact that others need to be

More information

Kant's Moral Philosophy

Kant's Moral Philosophy Kant's Moral Philosophy I. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (178.5)- Immanuel Kant A. Aims I. '7o seek out and establish the supreme principle of morality." a. To provide a rational basis for morality.

More information

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics.

Altruism. A selfless concern for other people purely for their own sake. Altruism is usually contrasted with selfishness or egoism in ethics. GLOSSARY OF ETHIC TERMS Absolutism. The belief that there is one and only one truth; those who espouse absolutism usually also believe that they know what this absolute truth is. In ethics, absolutism

More information

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder.

Download: Two clips from Star Trek. The needs of the many and The needs of the one found in Course Content Kant folder. TOPIC: Philosophy 1000 Lecture Introduction to Kant s deontology of Categorical Imperatives. KEY TERMS/ GOALS: Conformity with duty vs. motive from duty. Deontology. Kant s focus on agent s motives rather

More information

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT KANT S OBJECTIONS TO UTILITARIANISM: 1. Utilitarianism takes no account of integrity - the accidental act or one done with evil intent if promoting good ends

More information

The Pleasure Imperative

The Pleasure Imperative The Pleasure Imperative Utilitarianism, particularly the version espoused by John Stuart Mill, is probably the best known consequentialist normative ethical theory. Furthermore, it is probably the most

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Spring 2011 Russell Marcus Class 26 - April 27 Kantian Ethics Marcus, Introduction to Philosophy, Slide 1 Mill s Defense of Utilitarianism P People desire happiness.

More information

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2.

Philosophical Ethics. The nature of ethical analysis. Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2. Philosophical Ethics The nature of ethical analysis Discussion based on Johnson, Computer Ethics, Chapter 2. How to resolve ethical issues? censorship abortion affirmative action How do we defend our moral

More information

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1

Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 Common Morality: Deciding What to Do 1 By Bernard Gert (1934-2011) [Page 15] Analogy between Morality and Grammar Common morality is complex, but it is less complex than the grammar of a language. Just

More information

Journalists have a tremendous responsibility. Almost every day, we make

Journalists have a tremendous responsibility. Almost every day, we make Applied Ethics in Journalism A N I NTRODUCTION Patricia Ferrier Journalists have a tremendous responsibility. Almost every day, we make decisions that affect other people, decisions that might mean invading

More information

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2.

Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes. Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2. Kant The Grounding of the Metaphysics of Morals (excerpts) 1 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes Section IV: What is it worth? Reading IV.2 Kant s analysis of the good differs in scope from Aristotle s in two ways. In

More information

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017

Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017 Kantianism: Objections and Replies Keith Burgess-Jackson 12 March 2017 Kantianism (K): 1 For all acts x, x is right iff (i) the maxim of x is universalizable (i.e., the agent can will that the maxim of

More information

Foundations of Bioethics

Foundations of Bioethics introductory lectures in bioethics Foundations of Bioethics Paul Menzel Pacific Lutheran University (philosophy, emeritus) Visiting Professor of Bioethics, CUHK 17 October 2015 Centre for Bioethics, CUHK

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Categorical Imperative by. Kant Categorical Imperative by Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com Kant Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant (1724 1804)

More information

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT

Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT Deontology: Duty-Based Ethics IMMANUEL KANT A NOTE ON READING KANT Lord Macaulay once recorded in his diary a memorable attempt his first and apparently his last to read Kant s Critique: I received today

More information

PHIL 202: IV:

PHIL 202: IV: Draft of 3-6- 13 PHIL 202: Core Ethics; Winter 2013 Core Sequence in the History of Ethics, 2011-2013 IV: 19 th and 20 th Century Moral Philosophy David O. Brink Handout #9: W.D. Ross Like other members

More information

Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey

Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey Basics of Ethics CS 215 Denbigh Starkey 1. Introduction 1 2. Morality vs. ethics 1 3. Some ethical theories 3 a. Subjective relativism 3 b. Cultural relativism 3 c. Divine command theory 3 d. The golden

More information

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability Bayesian Probability Patrick Maher September 4, 2008 ABSTRACT. Bayesian decision theory is here construed as explicating a particular concept of rational choice and Bayesian probability is taken to be

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Deontological Ethics

Deontological Ethics Deontological Ethics From Jane Eyre, the end of Chapter XXVII: (Mr. Rochester is the first speaker) And what a distortion in your judgment, what a perversity in your ideas, is proved by your conduct! Is

More information

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Lecture 6 Workable Ethical Theories I Participation Quiz Pick an answer between A E at random. (thanks to Rodrigo for suggesting this quiz) Ethical Egoism Achievement of your happiness is the only moral

More information

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics)

Philosophical Ethics. Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism Deontology (Virtue Ethics) Consequentialism the value of an action (the action's moral worth, its rightness or wrongness) derives entirely from

More information

Kantian Deontology - Part Two

Kantian Deontology - Part Two Kantian Deontology - Part Two Immanuel Kant s Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals Nathan Kellen University of Connecticut October 1st, 2015 Table of Contents Hypothetical Categorical The Universal

More information

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies

Kantian Deontology. A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7. Paul Nicholls 13P Religious Studies A2 Ethics Revision Notes Page 1 of 7 Kantian Deontology Deontological (based on duty) ethical theory established by Emmanuel Kant in The Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. Part of the enlightenment

More information

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics Ethical Theories. Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018 Normative Ethics Ethical Theories Viola Schiaffonati October 4 th 2018 Overview (van de Poel and Royakkers 2011) 2 Ethical theories Relativism and absolutism Consequentialist approaches: utilitarianism

More information

the negative reason existential fallacy

the negative reason existential fallacy Mark Schroeder University of Southern California May 21, 2007 the negative reason existential fallacy 1 There is a very common form of argument in moral philosophy nowadays, and it goes like this: P1 It

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM

A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM 1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality

More information

Kant. Deontological Ethics

Kant. Deontological Ethics Kant 1 Deontological Ethics An action's moral value is determined by the nature of the action itself and the agent's motive DE contrasts with Utilitarianism which says that the goal or consequences of

More information

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action

Deontological Ethics. Kant. Rules for Kant. Right Action Deontological Ethics Kant An action's moral value is determined by the nature of the action itself and the agent's motive DE contrasts with Utilitarianism which says that the goal or consequences of an

More information

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical

Autonomous Machines Are Ethical Autonomous Machines Are Ethical John Hooker Carnegie Mellon University INFORMS 2017 1 Thesis Concepts of deontological ethics are ready-made for the age of AI. Philosophical concept of autonomy applies

More information

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1

In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1 1 Kant Review Dialogue 1 Micah Tillman 05 April, 2010, slightly revised 18 March, 2011 Tedrick: Hey Kant! In-Class Kant Review Dialogue 1 Why, hello there Fredward. Tedrick: It s Tedrick. Fredward is my

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

Is Morality Rational?

Is Morality Rational? PHILOSOPHY 431 Is Morality Rational? Topic #3 Betsy Spring 2010 Kant claims that violations of the categorical imperative are irrational acts. This paper discusses that claim. Page 2 of 6 In Groundwork

More information

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy

Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Benjamin Visscher Hole IV Phil 100, Intro to Philosophy Kantian Ethics I. Context II. The Good Will III. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation of Universal Law IV. The Categorical Imperative: Formulation

More information

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi

Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested. Syra Mehdi Aristotle's Theory of Friendship Tested Syra Mehdi Is friendship a more important value than honesty? To respond to the question, consider this scenario: two high school students, Jamie and Tyler, who

More information

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017

Computer Ethics. Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation. Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017 Normative Ethics and Normative Argumentation Viola Schiaffonati October 10 th 2017 Overview (van de Poel and Royakkers 2011) 2 Some essential concepts Ethical theories Relativism and absolutism Consequentialist

More information

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University.

David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in association with The Open University. Ethics Bites What s Wrong With Killing? David Edmonds This is Ethics Bites, with me David Edmonds. Warburton And me Warburton. David Ethics Bites is a series of interviews on applied ethics, produced in

More information

A primer of major ethical theories

A primer of major ethical theories Chapter 1 A primer of major ethical theories Our topic in this course is privacy. Hence we want to understand (i) what privacy is and also (ii) why we value it and how this value is reflected in our norms

More information

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions

Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Cabrillo College Claudia Close Honors Ethics Philosophy 10H Fall 2018 Honors Ethics Oral Presentations: Instructions Your initial presentation should be approximately 6-7 minutes and you should prepare

More information

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning

Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning Notes on Moore and Parker, Chapter 12: Moral, Legal and Aesthetic Reasoning The final chapter of Moore and Parker s text is devoted to how we might apply critical reasoning in certain philosophical contexts.

More information

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics

Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics Chapter 2: Reasoning about ethics 2012 Cengage Learning All Rights reserved Learning Outcomes LO 1 Explain how important moral reasoning is and how to apply it. LO 2 Explain the difference between facts

More information

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good?

Utilitarianism. But what is meant by intrinsically good and instrumentally good? Utilitarianism 1. What is Utilitarianism?: This is the theory of morality which says that the right action is always the one that best promotes the total amount of happiness in the world. Utilitarianism

More information

On Audi s Marriage of Ross and Kant. Thomas Hurka. University of Toronto

On Audi s Marriage of Ross and Kant. Thomas Hurka. University of Toronto On Audi s Marriage of Ross and Kant Thomas Hurka University of Toronto As its title suggests, Robert Audi s The Good in the Right 1 defends an intuitionist moral view like W.D. Ross s in The Right and

More information

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics

Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics Chapter 2 Normative Theories of Ethics MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. Consequentialism a. is best represented by Ross's theory of ethics. b. states that sometimes the consequences of our actions can be morally relevant.

More information

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard

The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard Philosophy of Religion The Role of Love in the Thought of Kant and Kierkegaard Daryl J. Wennemann Fontbonne College dwennema@fontbonne.edu ABSTRACT: Following Ronald Green's suggestion concerning Kierkegaard's

More information

The Right and the Good. W. D. Ross

The Right and the Good. W. D. Ross WHAT MAKES RIGHT ACTS RIGHT? The Right and the Good W. D. Ross II The real point at issue between hedonism and utilitarianism on the one hand and their opponents on the other is not whether 'right' means

More information

Introduction to Ethics

Introduction to Ethics Question 1: What is act-utilitarianism? Answer 1: Act-utilitarianism is a theory that is commonly presented in the writings of Jeremy Bentham and looks at the consequences of a specific act in determining

More information

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus

Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus Introduction to Philosophy Philosophy 110W Fall 2013 Russell Marcus Class 28 -Kantian Ethics Marcus, Introduction to Philosophy, Slide 1 The Good Will P It is impossible to conceive anything at all in

More information

Ethical non-naturalism

Ethical non-naturalism Michael Lacewing Ethical non-naturalism Ethical non-naturalism is usually understood as a form of cognitivist moral realism. So we first need to understand what cognitivism and moral realism is before

More information

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches

Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches Ethical Reasoning and the THSEB: A Primer for Coaches THSEB@utk.edu philosophy.utk.edu/ethics/index.php FOLLOW US! Twitter: @thseb_utk Instagram: thseb_utk Facebook: facebook.com/thsebutk Co-sponsored

More information

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena

Duty and Categorical Rules. Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena Duty and Categorical Rules Immanuel Kant Introduction to Ethics, PHIL 118 Professor Douglas Olena Preview This selection from Kant includes: The description of the Good Will The concept of Duty An introduction

More information

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley

Lecture 6 Kantianism. Based on slides 2011 Pearson Education, Inc. Publishing as Pearson Addison-Wesley Lecture 6 Kantianism Participation Quiz Pick an answer between A E at random. What answer (A E) do you think will have been selected most frequently in the previous poll? Recap: Unworkable Ethical Theories

More information

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1

The fact that some action, A, is part of a valuable and eligible pattern of action, P, is a reason to perform A. 1 The Common Structure of Kantianism and Act Consequentialism Christopher Woodard RoME 2009 1. My thesis is that Kantian ethics and Act Consequentialism share a common structure, since both can be well understood

More information

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE

CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE CHAPTER 2 Test Bank MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. A structured set of principles that defines what is moral is referred to as: a. a norm system b. an ethical system c. a morality guide d. a principled guide ANS:

More information

Two Ethical Principles

Two Ethical Principles OPEN 5 Two Ethical Principles Abstract: This chapter presents two ethical principles that are helpful in analyses of morally challenging situations at work. The principle of equality states that equal

More information

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance.

PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Part%I:%Challenges%to%Moral%Theory 1.%Relativism%and%Tolerance. Draftof8)27)12 PHIL%13:%Ethics;%Fall%2012% David%O.%Brink;%UCSD% Syllabus% Hereisalistoftopicsandreadings.Withinatopic,dothereadingsintheorderinwhich theyarelisted.readingsaredrawnfromthethreemaintexts

More information

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström

THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström From: Who Owns Our Genes?, Proceedings of an international conference, October 1999, Tallin, Estonia, The Nordic Committee on Bioethics, 2000. THE CONCEPT OF OWNERSHIP by Lars Bergström I shall be mainly

More information

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter One. Individual Subjectivism

World-Wide Ethics. Chapter One. Individual Subjectivism World-Wide Ethics Chapter One Individual Subjectivism To some people it seems very enlightened to think that in areas like morality, and in values generally, everyone must find their own truths. Most of

More information

Lecture 8. Ethics in Science

Lecture 8. Ethics in Science Lecture 8 Ethics in Science What is ethics? We can say it is a system for guiding our choices in different situations But it is not just rational choices. It is about situations where our conceptions of

More information

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics

Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics Soc Choice Welf (2010) 34:497 501 DOI 10.1007/s00355-009-0414-4 BOOK REVIEW Hugh LaFollette: The Practice of Ethics Blackwell, viii, 300 p. ISBN: 0-631-21945-5 Alex Voorhoeve Received: 28 June 2009 / Published

More information

Nonconsequentialism. from Intricate Ethics by Francis Kamm (2007) I. INTRODUCTION: DEFINITION AND ROOTS

Nonconsequentialism. from Intricate Ethics by Francis Kamm (2007) I. INTRODUCTION: DEFINITION AND ROOTS Nonconsequentialism from Intricate Ethics by Francis Kamm (2007) I. INTRODUCTION: DEFINITION AND ROOTS Nonconsequentialism is a type of normative ethical theory that denies that the rightness or wrongness

More information

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES

Ethics. PHIL 181 Spring 2018 SUMMARY OBJECTIVES Ethics PHIL 181 Spring 2018 Instructor: Dr. Stefano Giacchetti M/W 5.00-6.15 Office hours M/W 2-3 (by appointment) E-Mail: sgiacch@luc.edu SUMMARY Short Description: This course will investigate some of

More information

A Contractualist Reply

A Contractualist Reply A Contractualist Reply The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Scanlon, T. M. 2008. A Contractualist Reply.

More information

Duty Based Ethics. Ethics unit 3

Duty Based Ethics. Ethics unit 3 Duty Based Ethics Ethics unit 3 Divine command as a source of duty Stems from the monotheistic (Judeo/Christian/ Islamic) tradition An act is good if it is commanded by God, bad if it is forbidden by God.

More information

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals

Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals The Linacre Quarterly Volume 53 Number 1 Article 9 February 1986 Ethical Theory for Catholic Professionals James F. Drane Follow this and additional works at: http://epublications.marquette.edu/lnq Recommended

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 13 March 22 nd, 2016 O Neill, A Simplified Account of Kant s Ethics So far in this unit, we ve seen many different ways of judging right/wrong actions: Aristotle s virtue

More information

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract:

OPEN Moral Luck Abstract: OPEN 4 Moral Luck Abstract: The concept of moral luck appears to be an oxymoron, since it indicates that the right- or wrongness of a particular action can depend on the agent s good or bad luck. That

More information

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly *

Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Choosing Rationally and Choosing Correctly * Ralph Wedgwood 1 Two views of practical reason Suppose that you are faced with several different options (that is, several ways in which you might act in a

More information

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur

Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur Ethics Prof. Vineet Sahu Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology-Kanpur Module No. #01 Lecture No. #08 Deontological Theories Immanuel Kant Now, continuing to talk about,

More information

What makes right acts right? W.D. Ross on Duty and Moral Knowledge

What makes right acts right? W.D. Ross on Duty and Moral Knowledge What makes right acts right? W.D. Ross on Duty and Moral Knowledge What makes right acts right? Some background assumptions: Some acts are right and others wrong. They are not made wrong by subjective

More information

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1

A Review on What Is This Thing Called Ethics? by Christopher Bennett * ** 1 310 Book Review Book Review ISSN (Print) 1225-4924, ISSN (Online) 2508-3104 Catholic Theology and Thought, Vol. 79, July 2017 http://dx.doi.org/10.21731/ctat.2017.79.310 A Review on What Is This Thing

More information

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior

Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior Chapter 2 Determining Moral Behavior MULTIPLE CHOICE 1. A structured set of principles that defines what is moral is referred to as: a. a norm system b. an ethical system c. a morality guide d. a principled

More information

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction

Ethical Theories. A (Very) Brief Introduction Ethical Theories A (Very) Brief Introduction Last time, a definition Ethics: The discipline that deals with right and wrong, good and bad, especially with respect to human conduct. Well, for one thing,

More information

INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION

INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION INTELLECTUAL HUMILITY AND THE LIMITS OF CONCEPTUAL REPRESENTATION Thomas Hofweber Abstract: This paper investigates the connection of intellectual humility to a somewhat neglected form of a limitation

More information

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy,

Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient autonomy, Course Syllabus PHILOSOPHY 433 Instructor: Doran Smolkin, Ph. D. doran.smolkin@kpu.ca or doran.smolkin@ubc.ca Course Description: Is euthanasia morally permissible? What is the relationship between patient

More information

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries

Let us begin by first locating our fields in relation to other fields that study ethics. Consider the following taxonomy: Kinds of ethical inquiries ON NORMATIVE ETHICAL THEORIES: SOME BASICS From the dawn of philosophy, the question concerning the summum bonum, or, what is the same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has been accounted the

More information

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society.

The form of relativism that says that whether an agent s actions are right or wrong depends on the moral principles accepted in her own society. Glossary of Terms: Act-consequentialism Actual Duty Actual Value Agency Condition Agent Relativism Amoralist Appraisal Relativism A form of direct consequentialism according to which the rightness and

More information

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism

Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism Moral Philosophy : Utilitarianism Utilitarianism Utilitarianism is a moral theory that was developed by Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832) and John Stuart Mill (1806-1873). It is a teleological or consequentialist

More information