Conversation, Epistemology and Norms

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Conversation, Epistemology and Norms"

Transcription

1 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms STEVEN DAVIS Abstract: It is obvious that a great many of the things that we know we know because we learn them in conversation with others, conversations in which it is the intention of our interlocutor to inform us of something. It might be thought that only assertoric acts are informative. I shall argue that there is a range of conversational interventions that have this characteristic, including speech acts, presuppositions and conversational implicatures. The main focus of the paper is a discussion of the different norms, both moral and epistemological, that entitle us to believe what we learn from conversations. I compare our entitlement to believe what we learn from conversation with our entitlements to believe what we learn from perception. In providing an account of our epistemic warrant for our knowledge gained in conversation with ours, I draw on the work of Tyler Burge (1993 and 1997). Relying on others is perhaps not metaphysically necessary for any possible rational being. But it is cognitively fundamental to beings at all like us. (Burge, 1993, p. 466) Successful communication entails understanding. We might even take understanding to be one of the necessary goals of individual participants in a conversation (Davis, pp ). With understanding comes knowledge, knowledge at least of what has been communicated. Much has been made of testimony as a primary source of knowledge. I shall try to show that other conversational interventions are similar sources of knowledge, presuppositions, implicatures, and other types of speech acts besides testimony, for example. I shall draw on the work of Tyler Burge in attempting to provide the grounds for our knowledge in such cases (1993 and 1997). Burge is primarily concerned with what he calls something that is presented as true (1993, p. 467). It is not clear that this applies to the full range of conversational interventions that I shall consider. 1 Part of my goal is to extend his theory to other conversational interventions. I shall, however, part company with Burge on several points. I shall not follow him in his defense of his views about beliefs acquired from others being a source of a priori knowledge or in his claim that the rationality I would like to thank Jonathan Berg, David Davies, Christopher Guaker, Jérôme Pelletier, the members of the Jean Nicod Institute, espcially François Recanati and Dan Sperber for help with this paper. Address for correspondence: Philosophy Department, Simon Fraser University, Burnaby, B.C. V5A 1S6. Canada. sdavis@sfu.ca 1 Although Burge explicitly includes within his range of presentation as true, presupposition and conversational implicature, it is not clear that Burge s account applies to the full range of conversational interventions, asking a question, for example, that can be a source of knowledge (Burge, 1993, p. 482 n. 20). Mind & Language, Vol. 17 No. 5 November 2002, pp , 108 Cowley Road, Oxford, OX4 1JF, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA.

2 514 S. Davis of the source of a conversational intervention alone can provide the epistemological grounding for conversational knowledge. 2 I shall argue that an appeal must also be made to the morality of the source. 3 Let us imagine a simple conversation in which Sam says to Alice, 1. There is a party tonight. If Alice understands what Sam said, she understands that, 2. Sam said that there is a party tonight. In this case, we can say that Sam has successfully communicated what he meant to Alice. In cases of successful communication, there is the possibility of belief arising out of understanding and knowledge arising out of the belief. In our simple example, Alice might come to know that there is a party tonight, because Sam told her that there is. But it does not follow from Alice s knowing what Sam communicated, that she believes what he said, nor does it follow from her believing that there is a party tonight that she knows that there is. This much should be obvious. Understanding that p does not imply believing that p and believing that p does not imply knowing that p. I wish to pose two questions. What are the grounds for our beliefs that arise through communication and what more has to be added to our having grounds for our beliefs for us to have knowledge? 4 The range of cases in which we have knowledge because a belief has been communicated to us goes well beyond the simple example in 1. Think about how we know many things that are the result of scientific investigation. It is not because we have done the experiments or constructed the theories, but because we have been told about the results of the experiments and the conclusions of the theories. Or consider what we know about the past, or about current events, plane crashes in the United States or tropical storms in India, for example. It is not because we witnessed the events, but because we were told about what happened or is happening. In these and similar cases, we take and are entitled to take the word of others as the unquestioned source for our knowledge (Burge, 1993, p. 485). This is not to suggest that in these and similar cases we might not have justification in addition to our having been told what is or has happened. We might see pictures of the events on television, 2 I do not take issue with Burge s claim that there are cases of communication that gives rise to a priori knowledge, although doubts have been raised (see Bezuidenhout, 1998). My concern is to examine the kinds of conversational interventions, other than testimony, that give rise to knowledge and to show what entitles us to this knowledge. 3 I shall part company with Burge on other points that I shall indicate as they arise in the course of my argument. 4 I shall refine the notion of grounds in what follows drawing on a distinction between justification and entitlement.

3 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 515 for example. Nor is this to suggest that the source of our knowledge might be other than its having been communicated to us. We might be the scientist who has done the experiments or constructed the theories. Of course, there are cases in which our prima facie entitlement can be overridden. If we ask someone the time who says 5:00 p.m., with a dazed look and without consulting his watch, we might not believe him. In addition, there are types of discourse in which we do not take the word of others as an unquestioned source of knowledge, when, for example, we are involved in heated political or philosophical debate, when a policeman grills a suspect, or when professors ask students questions (Burge, 1993, pp. 468 and 484). But in many of our normal transactions with others, whether in conversation or in something that we read, the word of others is what entitles us to our belief. 5 What then is the nature of this source that gives rise to knowledge? One view, advanced by C.A.J. Coady (1992), is that where others are the source of knowledge, the source is more specifically their testimony. Coady takes testimony to be a speech act that can be made explicit with a performative verb formula, I testify that or with I bear witness to the fact that or more simply with I tell you that (Coady, pp ). According to Coady, someone telling me the time would be testifying as to the time of day. Coady recognizes that testimony is usually associated with formal court proceedings and does not apply to normal talk exchanges. Despite this, he uses testimony for both what he calls formal testimony and natural testimony. Formal testimony is the testimony that occurs in court proceedings or similar institutionalized settings; natural testimony is what occurs in our normal conversations with others. I believe that even if we accept Coady s distinction, he has mischaracterized the range of conversational interventions that are a source of knowledge by assimilating all such interventions to speech acts. Undoubtedly Coady is right to point out that someone telling us something can be a source of knowledge. Suppose that Sam knows 1 to be true and communicates it to Alice. Further, suppose that she understands and believes what he said. Alice would know, thereby, that there is a party tonight, unless she had an overriding reason to doubt Sam s word. I shall call Sam s speech act a conversational intervention and the knowledge that Alice thereby gains conversational knowledge. 6 Let us accept Coady s claim that Sam s saying 5 In what follows, I shall concentrate my attention on speech and conversation, but I think that without undue distortion what I say about knowledge gained from others can be carried over to the written word. 6 There is a range of what might be considered to be conversational knowledge that I shall not consider here. For example, in understanding 1, Alice might come to know that Sam is speaking English or that he is referring to the evening of February 13, 2001 in uttering. I think that the second, but not the first can be accommodated in the account that I shall give of conversational knowledge, but I shall not take it up here. The first sort of knowledge does not turn on the hearer s understanding what has been said, but rather on her understanding something about the sentence uttered. It is the former sort of understanding and the knowledge that it can give rise to with which I am concerned here.

4 516 S. Davis what he said is a case of testimony. 7 Testimony does not exhaust the range of conversational interventions that are a source of conversational knowledge. Other speech acts should be included. Warnings, predictions, etc. are, as well, sources of knowledge. We can divide speech acts, such as assertions, warnings, predictions, etc. into their force and propositional content (Searle, 1969, p. 31). 8 In these sorts of acts, the knowledge is knowledge of the content of the speech acts. In addition, speech acts can give rise to knowledge not only of their propositional contents, but also of their felicity conditions. Suppose that Sam promises Alice to be at the party and she understands that he has done so. Alice would thereby come to know that Sam has placed himself under a prima facie obligation to be there. In addition, she would know that he believed that she wanted him to be there. Or take another case. Suppose that Sam congratulates Alice for arranging the party and she understands that he has congratulated her. Alice would thereby come to know that Sam believes that she has arranged the party and that he thinks that is a good thing for her to have done so. I can come to know something not only because I understand the speech acts performed, but also because I understand what is conversationally implied. Suppose Alice arrives one hour late for an appointment and Sam archly says, 3. Thanks for being on time. In so saying Sam implies that Alice is late for their appointment and that he is somewhat miffed by her lateness. Moreover, if Alice understands and believes what Sam implies and Sam knows what he implies to be true, she comes to know that she was late for their appointment and that her being late upset Sam, if she did not know it already or does not have any overriding reason not to believe what Sam implies. How does Alice come to know this? She does not know it because Sam has told her, but because he conversationally implied it. So we can add conversational implicatures to speech acts as a source of knowledge from our conversations with others. Speech acts and conversational implicatures, however, do not exhaust the conversational interventions that are a source of knowledge. We should also include presupposition. Consider: 7 I think that Coady is mistaken in characterizing Sam s speech act as testimony. The reason for the mistake lies in Coady s analysis of testimony, the details of which I do not have the space to consider here (Coady, 1992, p. 42). 8 According to Searle, all speech acts can be divided into force and content. For example, if someone were to ask the question, Is John coming to the party? the resulting act can be divided into the propositional content [John is coming to the party] and the force, a question. But in this case, a hearer understanding the question would not come to know that John is coming to the party. So it is only a subset of speech acts that can give rise to knowledge of their propositional content.

5 4. Fred has stopped drinking. Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 517 If Sam knows 4 to be true and he communicates it to Alice and she believes it, Alice would thereby come to know that Fred had been drinking, although Sam did not tell her that Fred had been drinking. Rather, in saying that Fred had stopped drinking, Sam presupposed that Fred had been drinking, something that Alice can come to know if she understands what Sam said. These three cases do not fully capture the range of conversational interventions that can give rise to knowledge. Suppose that Sam is talking to Alice about his recent divorce from Ann. To indicate how he feels he wanly says, 5. I still miss her. Alice can thereby come to know how Sam feels about his divorce, but it is not knowledge that can be encapsulated propositionally (Sperber and Wilson, 1995, pp ). There is nothing that Sam can tell her that would sum up how he feels or that Alice can say that encapsulates her knowledge of how he feels. Nevertheless, Alice knows something that she did not know before Sam talked to her about his divorce and she knows this because he expressed how he feels by saying 5. This case is similar to 3 in that Sam has conversationally implied how he feels, but dissimilar in that what is conveyed is not propositional. Hence, Alice s knowing how Sam feels about his divorce, although not propositional knowledge, should not be excluded from what people can come to know by a conversational intervention. It is, however, not necessary to expand the list of conversational interventions, since in this case Sam s indicating to Alice how he feels about his divorce can be subsumed under conversational implicature. What this shows is that some conversational implicatures are not propositional. To sum up, we have three kinds of conversational interventions as sources of conversational knowledge, speech acts, conversational implicatures and presuppositions. Conversational knowledge, then, is knowledge that arises from the understanding of a conversational intervention. Not all knowledge we have that involves conversational interventions is conversational knowledge. There are two sorts of cases that I would like to distinguish from the examples above. In the first, the hearer draws on knowledge that he already has and uses it in conjunction with his understanding of a conversational intervention to draw an inference that provides him with further knowledge (Coady, 1992, p. 51). Sam and Alice are chatting about a party that was held last night and Sam, knowing 6 to be true, says, 6. Everyone at the party was drunk. Suppose that she believes what Sam said and she knows that,

6 518 S. Davis 7. Fred was at the party. From this and 6, she deduces that Fred was drunk. So Alice comes to know, 8. Fred was drunk at the party last night. Sam s saying 6 is in part the source of Alice s knowledge, but the epistemic warrant for Alice s knowledge of 8 is different from what I have called conversational knowledge. In these examples, Alice s entitlement to believe what she does rests on her understanding of Sam s conversational interventions. In coming to know 8 part of what entitles Alice to her belief is that Sam told her 6, but also on her being warranted to believe that Fred was at the party, a belief the warrant for which might not have arisen through a conversational intervention. Suppose that her entitlement is grounded in her having seen him go into the party. On this assumption, her knowledge of 8 contrasts with her knowledge of 1. In the latter example, the entitlement is that Sam told her; in the former example, it is Sam s telling her 6 and her perceptual belief that she saw Fred go into the party. What 1 5 have in common and what differentiates them from this case is that the entitlement to the belief is Alice s understanding that Sam Ø s that p, where Ø is a placeholder for a conversational intervention. 9 So we can say that conversational knowledge is that knowledge the sole warrant for which is the understanding of a conversational intervention. Had Alice s knowledge of 7 come from a conversational source, then it might appear that this example should be classified with 1 5. There is, however, one additional element involved here. From her knowledge of 6 and 7 Alice draws an inference to 8 and this inference is part of the warrant for her knowledge. Consequently, I shall exclude from the class of conversational knowledge knowledge obtained by drawing conclusions from premises, the knowledge of which is gained by conversational interventions. 10 The reason for excluding these sorts of cases is that if they were included in the class of conversational knowledge, so too would mathematical knowledge that depends on proofs using premises learned from others. But such knowledge is not justified solely by our understanding conversational interventions, but by the proofs we give. Thus, such knowledge falls outside the class of conversational knowledge. It might be claimed that our conversational knowledge is inferential and thus, our entitlement rests not only on our understanding 9 The example in 5 does not fit the form here, since Alice s entitlement is her understanding how Sam felt. But what Alice understands does not have the form ø-ed that p. This case could be included here, but it complicates the discussion unduly and it is not necessary for my purposes. See Sperber and Wilson for further discussion (pp ). 10 This is meant to exclude, for example, Alice s knowing that someone at the party was drunk, a conclusion she draws from 6.

7 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 519 conversational interventions. It could be argued, for example, that Alice s knowledge of 1 arises by inference from 2. Consequently, by ruling out inference as part of the warrant for conversational knowledge I have ruled out what I have given as paradigmatic examples of conversational knowledge. I shall return to this issue below. I have claimed that successful communication involves knowledge, knowledge of what is communicated. It would seem, then, that this knowledge should be included within conversational knowledge, since it clearly arises because of conversational interventions. I shall, however, exclude this knowledge from conversational knowledge. Let us consider an example of successful communication. In understanding what Sam means in uttering 1, Alice comes to know 2. Alice s knowing 2 does not imply her knowing 1. She might know the former without knowing the latter, since she might doubt that what Sam says is true. Hence, understanding that someone means that p does not entail knowing that p. 11 I shall restrict conversational knowledge to the knowledge that we have that is over and above the knowledge we have by understanding what someone means and is knowledge that we have that arises from this understanding. It might seem that from my discussion of conversational knowledge it is a necessary condition for someone to have it that he must be able to cite as his justification that he learned it from a conversational intervention. To put this point more precisely, it might seem that I am committed to the following thesis about conversational knowledge. 9. H has conversational knowledge of p only if were H asked how he knows that p, he would be able to provide as a justification for his belief that p that someone Ø-ed that p. Let us consider an example. 10. (a) Alice: Is Fred coming to the party? (b) Sam: He is. (c) Alice: How do you know? Did he tell you? (d) Sam: No. Betty told me. In the context of the conversation, Sam s saying that Fred is coming to the 11 Again, the example in 5 does not fit the required form. In this case, Alice means to indicate how she feels about her divorce, something that she can communicate to Sam. In addition, it does not fit the cases in which by understanding a speech act the hearer comes to know one of the felicity conditions of the speech act. For example, if Sam asks what time it is and Alice understands him, she can come to know that Sam wishes to know the time. I shall postpone full generality. At this point, it is not necessary, since as I shall show 9 and the related 12 are false.

8 520 S. Davis party implies that he knows that he is. On being queried about how he knows this, he gives as his justification for his belief that Betty told him. The question is whether being able to give justifications of this sort is necessary for someone to have conversational knowledge. I shall argue that it is not. There is an important distinction to be drawn between our being entitled to believe something and our being able to give a justification for our belief. To return to the example in 10, although Sam is able to say how he knows that Fred is coming to the party, his knowing that Fred is does not require him to be able to say how he knows this. Much of what we know we know, despite having forgotten the warrant for our knowledge (Burge, 1997, p. 38). Suppose that someone asks me about the construction materials of Kensington Palace. I say without hesitation, 11. It is built out of red brick. In this case, I have no memory of how I came to know this. Since I have been in London, I might well have seen the Palace and come to know 11 because of my perceptual experience. Equally as well, I might have read about it in a guidebook or someone might have told me. All trace of how I acquired the knowledge is lost to me. Suppose that I had been told 11 and it is this that was my warrant for 11, about both of which I have no recollection. All that I remember is 11. Despite having forgotten how I learned 11, it still qualifies as conversational knowledge, since my warrant is that someone told me. This conclusion might be resisted. It could be claimed that I do not have knowledge in this case, since I am not able to give a justification for what I know. I believe that if cases of this sort were excluded, then much of what is ordinarily taken to be knowledge would have to be ruled out as genuine knowledge. As I pointed above, most of what we know we learn from others conversational interventions. And I think a moment s reflection would reveal that in most cases of this sort we have forgotten the source of our knowledge, even that the source was a conversational intervention. There is another way to resist the conclusion that conversational knowledge does not require someone s being able to give a justification for his knowledge. The example above turns on my having forgotten the source of my knowledge, and hence, not being able currently to give a justification for my belief. This does not rule out, however, revising the requirement in 9 so that it applies to some time or other. We have, then, for 9: 12. H has conversational knowledge of p only if there is some time at which if H were asked how he knows that p, he would be able to provide as a justification for his belief that p that someone Ø-ed that p. The thought is that I have conversational knowledge of 11 only if at sometime or other I am able to say, if queried about how I know it, something like,

9 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms Someone told me that it was made of red brick. My current warrant for 11 would then be that in the past I was able to give a justification for my believing it and this justification is preserved as a causally connected tag to my belief, although I am not currently able to invoke it. This, however, seems implausible. There is a stage in the development of children when they have mastered a suitable enough amount of a language for them to have conversational knowledge without their having mastered the practice of being able to justify what they thereby know. We do not deny children knowledge because of their inability to give justifications for what they come to know through conversations. Imagine for a moment someone taking a hard line on this and claiming that if a child is not able to give a justification, then he has no knowledge in these cases. This would, I believe, rule out many clear examples of what we regard to be knowledge. I know, for example, that my name is Steven Davis, but I probably learned my name at an age at which I was unable to say, if asked then, how I know it. 12 Imagine further that in the intervening years, no one calls me Steven, but rather they use Sonny, a nickname. So there is no ongoing use of my name that would provide me with a warrant for my belief that my name is Steven Davis. 13 Let us suppose that someone were to deny that I then knew my name. It would follow from this that I do not now know my name, since currently, there is nothing I can say in answer to the question, How do you know it? and when I learned my name, there was nothing I could then say in answer to the question. What this shows is that someone s being able currently or in the past to give a justification for believing p is not a necessary condition for his conversational knowledge that p and hence, that 9 and 12 are false. Since there is a justification for my believing 11, this calls for a distinction to be made between my being able to give a justification and my having a justification. To distinguish the two I shall continue to use justification for the former, but following Burge, I shall call the latter entitlement (1993, p. 458). Before turning to a consideration of what entitles someone to believe what they understand, I would like to return to a question I raised earlier, namely, whether conversational knowledge is inferential. Let us assume that there is 12 Someone might think that this is a special kind of knowledge, knowledge of language, and it is different in kind from the sort of knowledge that I am considering. There is no reason, however, to think that my knowing that my name is Steven Davis or the knowledge that I have of anyone else s name is different in kind from the knowledge that we can have through conversation. 13 I have chosen an example from childhood, but I could have as well chosen knowledge that I have acquired as an adult through conversations. Much of this knowledge, I believe, is not mediated by my being aware of what sort of conversational intervention is the source of my knowledge. I might not pay any attention to how the beliefs are delivered to me. Was it a speech act? Or a conversational implicature? But to show there are such cases would take a psychological experiment and is not something that could be based merely on intuitions about conversations.

10 522 S. Davis an inference, albeit unconscious, from what I have been told to my believing 11. This is not sufficient, however, to show that my knowledge is inferential. What is required is that the inference must play a role in warranting the knowledge. So the question is not whether inference plays a role in delivering 11. For the sake of the argument, we shall assume that it does. It is whether the inference to 11 is part of its warrant. It does not follow from the fact that inference plays a role in delivering a belief that it serves to warrant the belief. Let us consider a similar case. Memory plays a role in long mathematical proofs. In a proof of this sort, the role that it plays is to preserve the various steps in the proof, but it does not serve to warrant the conclusion given the premises. It is the proof that provides the warrant (Burge, 1993, p. 463). In my believing, the inference does not play a warranting role; it is my understanding what I have been told about Kensington Palace that plays this role. 14 It might be thought that inference plays a warranting role in a hearer s knowing, for example, that someone who makes a promise places himself under a prima facie obligation or that someone who congratulates someone gives out that he thinks that the person he congratulates has done something commendable. In both these cases, I would argue that what is involved is understanding. For the hearer to understand that a speaker has made a promise he must understand that the speaker has placed himself under a prima facie obligation and for the hearer to understand that the speaker has congratulated someone he must understand that the speaker has given out that he thinks that the person he congratulated has done something commendable. Hence, in both cases understanding the speaker s conversational intervention involves understanding the felicity conditions that apply to the speech acts that the speaker performs. It might well be the case that in both instances inference is involved in the understanding. But it does not follow from this that the hearer makes an inference that is involved in his entitlement to believe that the speaker has placed himself under a prima facie obligation or that he gives out that he thinks that the person he has congratulated has done something commendable. I would now like to turn to what entitles us to rely on the word of others. I believe that comparing perceptual knowledge with conversational knowledge can illuminate what is required. Why can we rely on the deliverance of our senses for knowledge? Suppose that I believe that: 14. I see a cup. What entitles me to believe 14? It is because I am entitled to rely on the 14 This might seem to run counter to my claim above about children. But it doesn t. Children understand what is said to them without its being the case that they are able to say what they understand. What this shows is that the KK-principle is false, since there are cases in which children know what they told without their knowing that they know.

11 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 523 deliverance of my senses. I am so entitled because there is a reliable causal connection between the way the world is and belief formation mediated by our sensory apparatus, a causal connection about which I might well be totally unaware. Not only might I not know this, but also everyone in my community might be ignorant about the causal connection and about the operations of our perceptual apparatus. This was certainly the case early on in human history and is still the case, I imagine, for most people. Lack of such knowledge is no impediment to having perceptual knowledge. Our ancestors, although they lacked such information, surely had perceptual knowledge. This is analogous to conversational knowledge. To have conversational knowledge, one need not be in a position, I shall argue, to know what the grounds are for our conversational knowledge. In the case of perceptual knowledge, it is the reliability of a certain causal mechanism that provides the grounds for our knowledge, a causal mechanism about which we might be ignorant. As we shall see, in the case of conversational knowledge, it is not the reliability of a causal mechanism that grounds our knowledge, but the source of our conversational knowledge, a rational and moral source that I shall claim provides the grounding and about which we might be ignorant. It might be thought that the existence of a reliable causal connection between the way the world is that is delivered to us by sense experience and the formation of perceptual beliefs does not entitle us to these beliefs. Although we might well be entitled to rely on our senses, it does not follow that the seeming deliverance of the senses is free from the possibility of error (Burge, 1993, p. 470). There are, after all, hallucinations and illusions. But this has no bearing on our entitlements. To be entitled to rely on what we take to be sensory input, we do not have to rule out the possibility of error. For if this were necessary, given the range of skeptical arguments that have turned on this possibility, we would not have perceptual knowledge. All that is required is that there is no good reason to think that we are currently in error for us to be entitled to rely on what we take to be sensory experience. It is not that we have to have such a reason. Again, we do not have to assay the perceptual state that we are in and to rule out the possibility of error. Given a perceptual experience, our having knowledge of what it delivers is the default. Similarly, we have conversational knowledge despite the possibility of lying and insincerity, but we do not have to rule out that these possibilities obtain to have such knowledge. What this shows is that both our perceptual and conversational knowledge claims are defeasible, but that they are defeasible does not show that they are false. Entitlement to rely on the word of others is similar, although the grounds are not the reliability of some causal mechanism. Let us imagine that Moses goes up the mountain and instead of hearing God s voice, he meets someone on the mountain who introduces himself as Bill. Bill tells Moses that Israel is a land of milk and honey and that he should take his people there. Moses descends the mountain believing that:

12 524 S. Davis 15. Israel is a land of milk and honey. Is Moses entitled to believe this? It turns out that Bill is omniscient and a compulsive truth teller and thus, would not lie or mislead Moses. Let us suppose that Moses is ignorant of the talents of his source. It would seem that since Moses source is Bill, he is entitled to believe 15, although he does not know the nature of his source and thus, does not know that he is entitled to believe it. Of course, the example does not tell us about ordinary conversational interventions. Normally, our interlocutors are not omniscient and compulsive truth tellers. Let us weaken Bill s powers. Suppose that Bill is an honest man who is cognitively prudent. He would not tell anyone anything he did not believe for which he did not have good evidence. Bill tells Moses 15 and that it is true, but Moses does not know about Bill s virtues. Despite this, Moses believes what Bill tells him. In this case, Moses would be entitled to rely on what Bill told him without knowing that he is so entitled. Of course, Bill can make mistakes and even honest people can lie. If this were the case, Moses would not be entitled to believe what Bill tells him. But Moses does not have to rule out that this possibility obtains to be entitled to rely on what he has been told. So, we can say that Moses has a prima facie entitlement to believe what Bill tells him, an entitlement that can be overridden. The point of the examples is to show that if the source of a belief is of a certain sort, then we are entitled to the belief, even though we might be ignorant of the epistemic nature of the source. Let us suppose that S Ø s [p]. 16. If H understands that S Ø s [p] and thereby, comes to believe q, then H is prima facie entitled to believe q. 15 In 16, q is identical to p or is conceptually related to Ø-ing [p] gives sufficient conditions for entitlement to believe. Are they necessary as well? Let us change the case and imagine that Moses does not believe what he has been told; he thinks Bill is just an old fool. What would we say about Moses, if we knew that Bill was omniscient and a compulsive truth teller? I think we would say that Moses ought to have believed and that it was a mistake on his part not to believe it. It was, after all, someone who is omniscient and cannot prevent himself from telling the truth who told him. Hence, Moses was entitled to believe Bill. He has this entitlement even if he 15 Ø s [p] is meant to capture speech acts such as asking whether it is raining or congratulating someone for their fine performance. [p] then is a placeholder for whatever is the appropriate sentential complement for any Ø, where Ø is a placeholder for a conversational intervention type. 16 p and q are identical in the example that turns on 1 and 2 and they are conceptually related if in the same example, Alice were to come to know that Sam believes 1. In the latter case Sam s believing 1 is related conceptually to 2, since his believing 1 is a felicity condition for 2.

13 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 525 did not believe what he was told. This shows that although sufficient for entitlement, the conditions are not necessary does not capture the full range of beliefs to which we are entitled through conversational interventions. Let us consider the following case. Sam is a private in the army. Bill, who is not an officer and is not in any position to give Sam an order, is wearing an officer s uniform and he looks and acts like an officer. He says to Sam with an authoritative voice, 17. Sam, I order you to clean up the barracks. Sam has no reason not to think that Bill is not an officer; in fact, given the uniform, Bill s manner and his tone of voice, Sam takes 17 to be an order. Because of this, Sam comes to believe: 18. I am under an obligation to clean up the barracks. 18 Is he entitled to believe it? He is, if he is entitled to believe that Bill has ordered him to clean up the barracks. Given the way the situation is described, Sam is entitled to take Bill to have ordered him to clean up the barracks. Hence, he is entitled to believe that he is under an obligation to clean up the barracks. But since Bill is not in a position to order Sam to clean up the barracks, it is not the case that Sam understands that Bill has ordered him to clean up the barracks. For if Sam had understood that it was an order, it would have been an order. Hence, we can get by with a weaker condition than understanding. In our example, Sam only seemed to understand that Bill had ordered him to clean up the barracks. Given the circumstance, this entitles Sam to believe that Bill ordered him to clean up the barracks. This in turn entitles Sam to believe that he is under an obligation to clean up the barracks. Hence, Bill s seeming to understand that it was an order is sufficient for Bill to be entitled to believe that he is under an obligation to clean up the barracks. We can revise 16 to take account of this. 17 The example might seem to count against what Burge (1997, p. 45 n. 4.) calls The Acceptance Principle. A person is [a priori] entitled to accept a proposition that is [taken to be] presented as true and that is [seemingly] intelligible to him, unless there are stronger reasons not to do so (Brackets in original, ibid.). Whether the example counts against the Acceptance principle depends on how there are stronger reasons not to do so is construed. If it is sufficient for there to be stronger reasons that someone believes that there are, then we have a counter example to the Acceptance principle. But there is no counter example, if it is taken to mean that for there to be stronger reasons for not believing, the reasons must actually count against the truth of the belief. Although Moses believes that Bill is an old fool, he is in fact no such thing. Hence, what Moses believes is not a reason for his not being entitled to believe Notice that if in fact Bill were an officer, Sam would have conversational knowledge of 18.

14 526 S. Davis 19. If H seems to understand that S Ø s [p] and thereby, comes to believe q, thenh is prima facie entitled to believe q. 19 Applying 19 to the case under consideration yields, 20. If Sam seems to understand that Bill ordered him to clean up the barracks and Sam comes, thereby, to believe that he is under an obligation to clean up the barracks, then Sam is prima facie entitled to believe that he is under an obligation to clean up the barracks. There are then two steps in the argument that must be filled out before we can establish what it is in cases like this that entitles one to believe what one comes to believe through interlocution. 20 First, it must be established that, 21. If H seems to understand that S Ø s [p], then H is prima facie entitled to believe that S Ø s [p]. and second, that, 22. If H is prima facie entitled to believe that S Ø s [p], then H is prima facie entitled to believe that q. 21 Let us begin with 21. The question is what entitles us to go from seeming to understand that a conversational intervention is, for example, an assertion that p to being prima facie entitled to believe that it is an assertion that p. The grounds for the entitlement are the sort of grounds that we have for understanding what is conveyed to us by conversational interventions. These are not what are at issue here, since I have assumed as an epistemic starting point that we understand or seem to understand conversational interventions and that we are entitled to believe that we understand or seem to understand them. This is not to suggest that there is no epistemic problem, since there is an epistemic gap between what we seem to understand and our being entitled to rely on what we seem to understand. But I shall not try to bridge the gap here. 22 So the problem is to show that is true. I shall begin with an account of how assertions give us a prima facie entitlement to believe what is asserted, 19 The same qualification that applies to 16 applies here: q is identical to p or is conceptually related to Ø-ing [p]. Also, see footnote 14 above and 22 are not translations of 19. Rather, they are two principles that have to be established to substantiate our entitlement to our beliefs that arise because of conversational interventions. 21 See footnote See Burge 1993 and 1997 for a discussion of this issue.

15 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 527 relying in part on the work of Burge. 23 I shall then try to show how this account must be modified to apply to other conversational interventions. Consider 1 again. Sam says to Alice, 23. There is a party tonight. We shall assume that Alice is entitled to believe that Sam asserted and that she believes 23. What, then, is the connection between her being entitled to believe that Sam has asserted 23 and her being entitled to believe 23? The argument has two parts. First, there is a connection between someone s intelligibly asserting something and his being rational and his being rational and what he asserts being true. Second, someone who asserts something represents himself as telling the truth, that is, not lying. For this reason, he can be relied on to say what is true. Hence, the entitlement to believe what someone asserts will rest on an appeal to a prima facie presumption that the speaker is rational and moral. 25 Now for the details. Asserting is an act in which a speaker, in this case Sam, implies that he believes what he says. This is carried by one of the felicity conditions of the act, more particularly, its sincerity condition (Austin, 1962, pp ). Evidence for this is the oddness of saying, 24. There is party tonight, but I don t believe it. Hence, to assert that p is conventionally to imply that one believes that p. And to imply that one believes that p is to imply that one believes it to be true. So an assertion of p is a presentation of p as being true. Hence, an agent who asserts that p is presenting something as being true. Consequently, since Alice is prima facie entitled to believe that Sam has asserted something, she is prima facie entitled to believe that Sam has presented something as being true. Moreover, Alice has a prima facie understanding of what Sam said and thus, unless there are reasons to the contrary, she is entitled to rely on her prima facie understanding. Hence, Alice is entitled to take Sam to have intelligibly presented something as being true. The intelligible presentation of something 23 I part company with Burge in two respects. Unlike Burge, my interest is not in showing that there are a priori entitlements to believe some of what we come to believe through conversational interventions. In addition, I do not follow him in his claim that the sincerity of the interlocutor plays no fundamental role in prima facie entitlements to believe what is asserted. Burge s account can be found in his 1993 and I shall be neutral at this point about whether Alice only seems to understand that Sam asserted 23 or whether she has a genuine understanding. I have assumed that seeming to understand is sufficient for being entitled to believe that one understands. Clearly, if seeming to understanding yields entitlement, so too does genuine understanding. Moreover, genuine understanding, although required for Alice to know 23, is not necessary for her to be entitled to believe it. 25 Moral might be too strong. I consider this in what follows.

16 528 S. Davis as being true reveals two things that can be presumed about the speaker, the source of the presentation. The speaker can be presumed to be rational and moral, rational in that the intelligible presentation of something as being true, as Burge puts it, is a prima facie sign of rationality (Burge, 1993, p. 471) and moral in that the intelligible presentation of the speaker as believing what he says is a prima facie sign of his being moral. Let us assume that in seeming to understand Sam, not only is Alice entitled to believe that she has understood him, but that in fact she has understood his conversational intervention. So we shall assume that Sam has asserted 23. When we are finished our discussion, we shall unwind the assumption. Consequently, the question that we shall ask is: In what way is Sam s assertion of 23, his intelligible presentation of its being true, a sign of rationality? To answer this question, we shall look at the properties that Sam has, by virtue of his asserting 23. But first a bit about rationality. We are interested in Sam s rationality, since he is the source of Alice s belief. Rationality can be attributed to actions, abilities, capacities, dispositions, beliefs, intentions, agents, etc. There are interrelations among these. Let us look at the relationship between agent and action and the connection with rationality. There are two ways in which the rationality of the agent connects with an action. The first is that some actions require for their successful performance that the agent have various capacities and abilities that function properly. In turn, this requires that the agent be sensitive to certain norms, the sensitivity to which is partly constitutive of what it is to be rational. The second way in which actions are connected to the rationality of an agent is that the rationality of an agent is a function of the rationality of his dispositions to act and of his ability to apply these dispositions in particular situations. A disposition to act is rational, if it results in rational actions. Hence, an agent s being rational entails that when the agent performs a particular action, it will be rational. It might seem that this is obviously false, since agents who are rational can on occasion act irrationally. Certainly this is the case, but in so far as an agent acts irrationally he is not entirely rational, nor can the disposition from which such an act flows be entirely rational. But our interest is not to move downward from the rationality of an agent and his dispositions, but upward from the rationality of an action to the rationality of an agent. If an agent s act is rational, what does this say about the agent? I think that we can safely say that an agent s acting rationally in a particular situation is a sign that he has a disposition to act rational and hence, is a sign that he is rational. That an agent s acting rationally in a particular case is a sign for his being rational does not result in its being certain that he is rational, but as Burge puts it, it justifies a prima facie presumption that the agent is rational (1993, p. 476). Let us turn to Sam and his asserting 23. He has performed a speech act, containing a content, in a conversational context. The performance of the speech act indicates that he has a range of capacities, including his ability to make assertions, to enter into conversational exchanges, to apply a range of

17 Conversation, Epistemology and Norms 529 concepts in expressing the content of the assertion and to use a range of expressions in a grammatically intelligible construction that are relevant to his making his assertion. To sum this up, we can say that in asserting 23, Sam exhibits speech act, conversational, conceptual and linguistic abilities and capacities. There are connections among these capacities and abilities. The ability to make assertions, and more generally, the ability to perform speech acts, has as a necessary component the ability to understand and use a range of concepts, since a speech act requires for its performance having the concept of the speech act performed, as well as the concepts that constitute the constituents of the content expressed. 26 In our example, Sam cannot assert 23 without having the concept of an assertion and the concepts that are constituents of the content of what is expressed by his utterance of 23. Moreover, in performing a speech act and expressing the content of the act, Sam must have the linguistic means to perform the act and to express the associated content. 27 Speech acts typically occur in conversational contexts. Sam must have the capacity to address his remark to Alice, to react appropriately if uptake is not evident, to recognize the relevance of various conversational responses to his assertion, for example, Alice s telling him that she already knows 23 or that the party was last night, etc. There is a connection between these abilities and rationality. Each of these abilities, speech act, conceptual, conversational and linguistic, involves the possibility of error. They require that Sam has the capacity to recognize the relevance of remarks to the effect that he has made a mistake and the disposition to make corrections when he has made a mistake. Take having concepts. Having a concept is necessarily linked with being able to recognize correct and incorrect applications of the concept. Consider having the concept of an assertion. This is connected to the ability to recognize as being relevant criticisms to the effect that what one has asserted is false or that there are no reasons for believing it. Being able to recognize mistakes and being disposed to make corrections of the mistakes so recognized are partly constitutive of rationality. Hence, in so far as he asserts 23, Sam can be taken to be rational. 26 It could be argued that children are able to make assertions but they do not have the concept of an assertion. Having such a concept, it might be claimed, is a higher order capacity that is displayed and is necessary in understanding various sorts of remarks that are directed to the speaker who makes an assertion, for example, a critical remark to the effect that what the speaker says is false. I think that if someone who makes a statement lacks the ability to see the relevance of this and similar remarks to what he has said, then it is not clear that he has made a statement. Imagine a child who insists that his truck is broken and when shown that it is not, still insists on saying Truck, broken, and he insists on saying this no matter what he is told or shown. We might then have doubts about whether he has the concept expressed by broken and thus, whether in uttering Truck broken, he has asserted anything. 27 I do not mean to imply a tight connection between linguistic abilities and ability to perform a speech act. It might be the case that Sam has speech difficulties in which he inverts words, but in certain contexts this might not prevent him from asserting something.

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

The Concept of Testimony

The Concept of Testimony Published in: Epistemology: Contexts, Values, Disagreement, Papers of the 34 th International Wittgenstein Symposium, ed. by Christoph Jäger and Winfried Löffler, Kirchberg am Wechsel: Austrian Ludwig

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren

KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST. Arnon Keren Abstracta SPECIAL ISSUE VI, pp. 33 46, 2012 KNOWLEDGE ON AFFECTIVE TRUST Arnon Keren Epistemologists of testimony widely agree on the fact that our reliance on other people's testimony is extensive. However,

More information

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011

Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011 Nested Testimony, Nested Probability, and a Defense of Testimonial Reductionism Benjamin Bayer September 2, 2011 In her book Learning from Words (2008), Jennifer Lackey argues for a dualist view of testimonial

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

TAKE MY WORD FOR IT: A NEW APPROACH TO THE PROBLEM OF SINCERITY IN THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY. Masters in Philosophy. Rhodes University.

TAKE MY WORD FOR IT: A NEW APPROACH TO THE PROBLEM OF SINCERITY IN THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY. Masters in Philosophy. Rhodes University. TAKE MY WORD FOR IT: A NEW APPROACH TO THE PROBLEM OF SINCERITY IN THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF TESTIMONY A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the of Masters in Philosophy Rhodes University

More information

The Social Character of Testimonial Knowledge

The Social Character of Testimonial Knowledge The Social Character of Testimonial Knowledge Introduction Through communication, we form beliefs about the world, its history, others and ourselves. A vast proportion of these beliefs we count as knowledge.

More information

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY

CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY 1 CONVENTIONALISM AND NORMATIVITY TORBEN SPAAK We have seen (in Section 3) that Hart objects to Austin s command theory of law, that it cannot account for the normativity of law, and that what is missing

More information

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience

A solution to the problem of hijacked experience A solution to the problem of hijacked experience Jill is not sure what Jack s current mood is, but she fears that he is angry with her. Then Jack steps into the room. Jill gets a good look at his face.

More information

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science + Business Media B.V. Acta anal. (2007) 22:267 279 DOI 10.1007/s12136-007-0012-y What Is Entitlement? Albert Casullo Received: 30 August 2007 / Accepted: 16 November 2007 / Published online: 28 December 2007 # Springer Science

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary

Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary Interest-Relativity and Testimony Jeremy Fantl, University of Calgary In her Testimony and Epistemic Risk: The Dependence Account, Karyn Freedman defends an interest-relative account of justified belief

More information

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords

Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords Oxford Scholarship Online Abstracts and Keywords ISBN 9780198802693 Title The Value of Rationality Author(s) Ralph Wedgwood Book abstract Book keywords Rationality is a central concept for epistemology,

More information

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW

DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 58, No. 231 April 2008 ISSN 0031 8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.512.x DEFEASIBLE A PRIORI JUSTIFICATION: A REPLY TO THUROW BY ALBERT CASULLO Joshua Thurow offers a

More information

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies

ON EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT. by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies. II Martin Davies by Crispin Wright and Martin Davies II Martin Davies EPISTEMIC ENTITLEMENT, WARRANT TRANSMISSION AND EASY KNOWLEDGE ABSTRACT Wright s account of sceptical arguments and his use of the idea of epistemic

More information

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version)

The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) The Many Problems of Memory Knowledge (Short Version) Prepared For: The 13 th Annual Jakobsen Conference Abstract: Michael Huemer attempts to answer the question of when S remembers that P, what kind of

More information

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING

INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING The Philosophical Quarterly Vol. 63, No. 253 October 2013 ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/1467-9213.12071 INTUITION AND CONSCIOUS REASONING BY OLE KOKSVIK This paper argues that, contrary to common opinion,

More information

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is:

The stated objective of Gloria Origgi s paper Epistemic Injustice and Epistemic Trust is: Trust and the Assessment of Credibility Paul Faulkner, University of Sheffield Faulkner, Paul. 2012. Trust and the Assessment of Credibility. Epistemic failings can be ethical failings. This insight is

More information

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI

ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI ALTERNATIVE SELF-DEFEAT ARGUMENTS: A REPLY TO MIZRAHI Michael HUEMER ABSTRACT: I address Moti Mizrahi s objections to my use of the Self-Defeat Argument for Phenomenal Conservatism (PC). Mizrahi contends

More information

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii)

the aim is to specify the structure of the world in the form of certain basic truths from which all truths can be derived. (xviii) PHIL 5983: Naturalness and Fundamentality Seminar Prof. Funkhouser Spring 2017 Week 8: Chalmers, Constructing the World Notes (Introduction, Chapters 1-2) Introduction * We are introduced to the ideas

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Skepticism and Internalism

Skepticism and Internalism Skepticism and Internalism John Greco Abstract: This paper explores a familiar skeptical problematic and considers some strategies for responding to it. Section 1 reconstructs and disambiguates the skeptical

More information

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000)

Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) Direct Realism and the Brain-in-a-Vat Argument by Michael Huemer (2000) One of the advantages traditionally claimed for direct realist theories of perception over indirect realist theories is that the

More information

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction

Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Introduction 24 Testimony and Moral Understanding Anthony T. Flood, Ph.D. Abstract: In this paper, I address Linda Zagzebski s analysis of the relation between moral testimony and understanding arguing that Aquinas

More information

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters

Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Reliabilism and the Problem of Defeaters Prof. Dr. Thomas Grundmann Philosophisches Seminar Universität zu Köln Albertus Magnus Platz 50923 Köln E-mail: thomas.grundmann@uni-koeln.de 4.454 words Reliabilism

More information

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION

SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION SUPPOSITIONAL REASONING AND PERCEPTUAL JUSTIFICATION Stewart COHEN ABSTRACT: James Van Cleve raises some objections to my attempt to solve the bootstrapping problem for what I call basic justification

More information

A Priori Bootstrapping

A Priori Bootstrapping A Priori Bootstrapping Ralph Wedgwood In this essay, I shall explore the problems that are raised by a certain traditional sceptical paradox. My conclusion, at the end of this essay, will be that the most

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument?

Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Epistemological Foundations for Koons Cosmological Argument? Koons (2008) argues for the very surprising conclusion that any exception to the principle of general causation [i.e., the principle that everything

More information

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol

COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS. Jessica BROWN University of Bristol Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (2005), xx yy. COMPARING CONTEXTUALISM AND INVARIANTISM ON THE CORRECTNESS OF CONTEXTUALIST INTUITIONS Jessica BROWN University of Bristol Summary Contextualism is motivated

More information

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason

Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Lost in Transmission: Testimonial Justification and Practical Reason Andrew Peet and Eli Pitcovski Abstract Transmission views of testimony hold that the epistemic state of a speaker can, in some robust

More information

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran

Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Deontological Perspectivism: A Reply to Lockie Hamid Vahid, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences, Tehran Abstract In his (2015) paper, Robert Lockie seeks to add a contextualized, relativist

More information

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM

Vol. II, No. 5, Reason, Truth and History, 127. LARS BERGSTRÖM Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. II, No. 5, 2002 L. Bergström, Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy 1 Putnam on the Fact-Value Dichotomy LARS BERGSTRÖM Stockholm University In Reason, Truth and History

More information

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules

NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION Constitutive Rules NOTES ON WILLIAMSON: CHAPTER 11 ASSERTION 11.1 Constitutive Rules Chapter 11 is not a general scrutiny of all of the norms governing assertion. Assertions may be subject to many different norms. Some norms

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

Do we have knowledge of the external world?

Do we have knowledge of the external world? Do we have knowledge of the external world? This book discusses the skeptical arguments presented in Descartes' Meditations 1 and 2, as well as how Descartes attempts to refute skepticism by building our

More information

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea.

World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Natural- ism , by Michael C. Rea. Book reviews World without Design: The Ontological Consequences of Naturalism, by Michael C. Rea. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004, viii + 245 pp., $24.95. This is a splendid book. Its ideas are bold and

More information

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester

Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions. David Braun. University of Rochester Cognitive Significance, Attitude Ascriptions, and Ways of Believing Propositions by David Braun University of Rochester Presented at the Pacific APA in San Francisco on March 31, 2001 1. Naive Russellianism

More information

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China

ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang. Changchun University, Changchun, China US-China Foreign Language, February 2015, Vol. 13, No. 2, 109-114 doi:10.17265/1539-8080/2015.02.004 D DAVID PUBLISHING Presupposition: How Discourse Coherence Is Conducted ZHANG Yan-qiu, CHEN Qiang Changchun

More information

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori

Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori Lingnan University Digital Commons @ Lingnan University Theses & Dissertations Department of Philosophy 2014 Is there a distinction between a priori and a posteriori Hiu Man CHAN Follow this and additional

More information

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract

Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence. Abstract Wittgenstein on the Fallacy of the Argument from Pretence Edoardo Zamuner Abstract This paper is concerned with the answer Wittgenstein gives to a specific version of the sceptical problem of other minds.

More information

Matthew Parrott. In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her

Matthew Parrott. In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her SELF-BLINDNESS AND RATIONAL SELF-AWARENESS Matthew Parrott In order for me become aware of another person's psychological states, I must observe her in some way. I must see what she is doing or listen

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Umeå University BIBLID [0873-626X (2013) 35; pp. 81-91] 1 Introduction You are going to Paul

More information

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism

McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism 48 McCLOSKEY ON RATIONAL ENDS: The Dilemma of Intuitionism T om R egan In his book, Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics,* Professor H. J. McCloskey sets forth an argument which he thinks shows that we know,

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY

PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY PHILOSOPHY 5340 EPISTEMOLOGY Michael Huemer, Skepticism and the Veil of Perception Chapter V. A Version of Foundationalism 1. A Principle of Foundational Justification 1. Mike's view is that there is a

More information

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification?

Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Philos Stud (2007) 134:19 24 DOI 10.1007/s11098-006-9016-5 ORIGINAL PAPER Is Klein an infinitist about doxastic justification? Michael Bergmann Published online: 7 March 2007 Ó Springer Science+Business

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas

INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE. David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas INTERPRETATION AND FIRST-PERSON AUTHORITY: DAVIDSON ON SELF-KNOWLEDGE David Beisecker University of Nevada, Las Vegas It is a curious feature of our linguistic and epistemic practices that assertions about

More information

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN

CONSCIOUSNESS, INTENTIONALITY AND CONCEPTS: REPLY TO NELKIN ----------------------------------------------------------------- PSYCHE: AN INTERDISCIPLINARY JOURNAL OF RESEARCH ON CONSCIOUSNESS ----------------------------------------------------------------- CONSCIOUSNESS,

More information

Evidential arguments from evil

Evidential arguments from evil International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 48: 1 10, 2000. 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 1 Evidential arguments from evil RICHARD OTTE University of California at Santa

More information

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM

THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM SKÉPSIS, ISSN 1981-4194, ANO VII, Nº 14, 2016, p. 33-39. THE SEMANTIC REALISM OF STROUD S RESPONSE TO AUSTIN S ARGUMENT AGAINST SCEPTICISM ALEXANDRE N. MACHADO Universidade Federal do Paraná (UFPR) Email:

More information

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION

STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION FILOZOFIA Roč. 66, 2011, č. 4 STEWART COHEN AND THE CONTEXTUALIST THEORY OF JUSTIFICATION AHMAD REZA HEMMATI MOGHADDAM, Institute for Research in Fundamental Sciences (IPM), School of Analytic Philosophy,

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY

WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY WHY WE REALLY CANNOT BELIEVE THE ERROR THEORY Bart Streumer b.streumer@rug.nl 29 June 2017 Forthcoming in Diego Machuca (ed.), Moral Skepticism: New Essays 1. Introduction According to the error theory,

More information

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS

CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS CRUCIAL TOPICS IN THE DEBATE ABOUT THE EXISTENCE OF EXTERNAL REASONS By MARANATHA JOY HAYES A THESIS PRESENTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF FLORIDA IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

The Assurance View of Testimony

The Assurance View of Testimony The Assurance View of Testimony Matthew Weiner University of Utah Abstract This essay critically examines the Assurance View of testimony as put forth by Angus Ross (1986) and Richard Moran (1999). The

More information

PHI 1700: Global Ethics

PHI 1700: Global Ethics PHI 1700: Global Ethics Session 3 February 11th, 2016 Harman, Ethics and Observation 1 (finishing up our All About Arguments discussion) A common theme linking many of the fallacies we covered is that

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh

Précis of Empiricism and Experience. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh Précis of Empiricism and Experience Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh My principal aim in the book is to understand the logical relationship of experience to knowledge. Say that I look out of my window

More information

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit

This is a collection of fourteen previously unpublished papers on the fit Published online at Essays in Philosophy 7 (2005) Murphy, Page 1 of 9 REVIEW OF NEW ESSAYS ON SEMANTIC EXTERNALISM AND SELF-KNOWLEDGE, ED. SUSANA NUCCETELLI. CAMBRIDGE, MA: THE MIT PRESS. 2003. 317 PAGES.

More information

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist

The Skeptic and the Dogmatist NOÛS 34:4 ~2000! 517 549 The Skeptic and the Dogmatist James Pryor Harvard University I Consider the skeptic about the external world. Let s straightaway concede to such a skeptic that perception gives

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Andreas Stokke andreas.stokke@gmail.com - published in Disputatio, V(35), 2013, 81-91 - 1

More information

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of

Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief. Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of Goldman on Knowledge as True Belief Alvin Goldman (2002a, 183) distinguishes the following four putative uses or senses of knowledge : (1) Knowledge = belief (2) Knowledge = institutionalized belief (3)

More information

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS

FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS FOUNDATIONALISM AND ARBITRARINESS by DANIEL HOWARD-SNYDER Abstract: Nonskeptical foundationalists say that there are basic beliefs. But, one might object, either there is a reason why basic beliefs are

More information

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony

On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony 700 arnon keren On the alleged perversity of the evidential view of testimony ARNON KEREN 1. My wife tells me that it s raining, and as a result, I now have a reason to believe that it s raining. But what

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY

THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY THINKING ANIMALS AND EPISTEMOLOGY by ANTHONY BRUECKNER AND CHRISTOPHER T. BUFORD Abstract: We consider one of Eric Olson s chief arguments for animalism about personal identity: the view that we are each

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge

Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Self-Evidence and A Priori Moral Knowledge Colorado State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2012) 33; pp. 459-467] Abstract According to rationalists about moral knowledge, some moral truths are knowable a

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613 Naturalized Epistemology Quine PY4613 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? a. How is it motivated? b. What are its doctrines? c. Naturalized Epistemology in the context of Quine s philosophy 2. Naturalized

More information

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason

Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXVII, No. 1, July 2003 Experience and Foundationalism in Audi s The Architecture of Reason WALTER SINNOTT-ARMSTRONG Dartmouth College Robert Audi s The Architecture

More information

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S

THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S THE NATURE OF NORMATIVITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LOGIC REBECCA V. MILLSOP S I. INTRODUCTION Immanuel Kant claims that logic is constitutive of thought: without [the laws of logic] we would not think at

More information

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction

Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Right-Making, Reference, and Reduction Kent State University BIBLID [0873-626X (2014) 39; pp. 139-145] Abstract The causal theory of reference (CTR) provides a well-articulated and widely-accepted account

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Constructing the World

Constructing the World Constructing the World Lecture 3: The Case for A Priori Scrutability David Chalmers Plan *1. Sentences vs Propositions 2. Apriority and A Priori Scrutability 3. Argument 1: Suspension of Judgment 4. Argument

More information

what makes reasons sufficient?

what makes reasons sufficient? Mark Schroeder University of Southern California August 2, 2010 what makes reasons sufficient? This paper addresses the question: what makes reasons sufficient? and offers the answer, being at least as

More information

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI

UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI DAVID HUNTER UNDERSTANDING, JUSTIFICATION AND THE A PRIORI (Received in revised form 28 November 1995) What I wish to consider here is how understanding something is related to the justification of beliefs

More information

Pragmatic Presupposition

Pragmatic Presupposition Pragmatic Presupposition Read: Stalnaker 1974 481: Pragmatic Presupposition 1 Presupposition vs. Assertion The Queen of England is bald. I presuppose that England has a unique queen, and assert that she

More information

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Lasersohn Comments on Lasersohn John MacFarlane September 29, 2006 I ll begin by saying a bit about Lasersohn s framework for relativist semantics and how it compares to the one I ve been recommending. I ll focus

More information

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs?

Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs? Who Has the Burden of Proof? Must the Christian Provide Adequate Reasons for Christian Beliefs? Issue: Who has the burden of proof the Christian believer or the atheist? Whose position requires supporting

More information

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to

Lucky to Know? the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take ourselves to Lucky to Know? The Problem Epistemology is the field of philosophy interested in principled answers to questions regarding the nature and extent of human knowledge and rational belief. We ordinarily take

More information

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS

Is there a good epistemological argument against platonism? DAVID LIGGINS [This is the penultimate draft of an article that appeared in Analysis 66.2 (April 2006), 135-41, available here by permission of Analysis, the Analysis Trust, and Blackwell Publishing. The definitive

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection.

Understanding Belief Reports. David Braun. In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. Appeared in Philosophical Review 105 (1998), pp. 555-595. Understanding Belief Reports David Braun In this paper, I defend a well-known theory of belief reports from an important objection. The theory

More information

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human

1 ReplytoMcGinnLong 21 December 2010 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn. In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human 1 Language and Society: Reply to McGinn By John R. Searle In his review of my book, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization, (Oxford University Press, 2010) in NYRB Nov 11, 2010. Colin

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism

PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism PHL340 Handout 8: Evaluating Dogmatism 1 Dogmatism Last class we looked at Jim Pryor s paper on dogmatism about perceptual justification (for background on the notion of justification, see the handout

More information

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters

Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2018 Pollock and Sturgeon on defeaters Albert

More information

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive?

Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Why Is Epistemic Evaluation Prescriptive? Kate Nolfi UNC Chapel Hill (Forthcoming in Inquiry, Special Issue on the Nature of Belief, edited by Susanna Siegel) Abstract Epistemic evaluation is often appropriately

More information

HUMAN TESTIMONY. Learning from other human beings cannot be equated to learning from things. The

HUMAN TESTIMONY. Learning from other human beings cannot be equated to learning from things. The HUMAN TESTIMONY Learning from other human beings cannot be equated to learning from things. The clouds indicate rain and thereby give us a basis for believing that it will rain but the statements of others

More information

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality.

the notion of modal personhood. I begin with a challenge to Kagan s assumptions about the metaphysics of identity and modality. On Modal Personism Shelly Kagan s essay on speciesism has the virtues characteristic of his work in general: insight, originality, clarity, cleverness, wit, intuitive plausibility, argumentative rigor,

More information

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286.

Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and. Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Pp. xvi, 286. Robert Audi, The Architecture of Reason: The Structure and Substance of Rationality. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2001. Pp. xvi, 286. Reviewed by Gilbert Harman Princeton University August 19, 2002

More information

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following,

More information

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL?

IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL? The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 54, No. 215 April 2004 ISSN 0031 8094 IS EVIDENCE NON-INFERENTIAL? BY ALEXANDER BIRD Evidence is often taken to be foundational, in that while other propositions may be

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information