CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ S METAPHYSICS

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ S METAPHYSICS"

Transcription

1 JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHICAL RESEARCH VOLUME 36, 2011 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ S METAPHYSICS JOHN WHIPPLE UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS AT CHICAGO ABSTRACT: This paper examines Leibniz s views on the theistic doctrine of continual creation and considers their implications for his theory of finite substance. Three main theses are defended: (1) that Leibniz takes the traditional account of continual creation to involve the literal re-creation of all things in a successive series of instantaneous states, (2) that a straightforward commitment to the traditional account would give rise to serious problems within Leibniz s theory of finite substance and his metaphysics more generally, and (3) that Leibniz does not straightforwardly affirm the continual creation doctrine, despite certain texts that initially seem to suggest otherwise. I also present a more speculative interpretive hypothesis about what Leibniz s considered view of creation might have been, namely that in a single act, God creates and conserves substances that are non-spatial and atemporal at the deepest level of reality. I. INTRODUCTION D iscussions of the doctrine of continual creation can be found in the writings of a number of early modern philosophers. 1 Descartes famously affirms the doctrine in a few short lines in the Meditations and the Principles of Philosophy lines that have given rise to a long-running debate over whether he is a temporal atomist. 2 The doctrine is also utilized by Malebranche (and a number of other figures) as an argument for occasionalism. 3 These are the two most famous appearances of the continual creation doctrine in the modern period, but they are not the only places it can be found. One can also find it in the writings of Leibniz. He affirms the doctrine on a number of occasions; but his remarks have not received the

2 2 JOHN WHIPPLE attention they deserve in the secondary literature. 4 This is unfortunate, for a careful analysis of Leibniz s view on continual creation takes one to the very heart of his mature metaphysics. 5 Leibniz s affirmations of the continual creation doctrine raise two immediate questions. First, how does he think the doctrine has been traditionally affirmed; and second, is Leibniz straightforwardly committed to the traditional doctrine? I shall argue that the answer to the first question, roughly stated, is that he takes the traditional doctrine to maintain that God literally re-creates the world in a successive series of instantaneous states. With respect to the second question, there are several texts in which Leibniz seems to straightforwardly commit himself to the traditional doctrine. This has led several prominent commentators to claim that Leibniz is in fact committed to an instantaneous account of creation. They concede that this account initially seems to be at odds with certain aspects of Leibniz s metaphysics, but they argue that the tensions are only apparent. 6 I shall argue that this interpretive verdict is incorrect. Once all of the problems associated with the traditional doctrine have been carefully elaborated, it will become clear that the traditional doctrine simply cannot be reconciled with Leibniz s views on the endurance and activity of finite substances, inter alia. This does not imply that Leibniz s mature metaphysics suffers from severe internal inconsistencies, however. I shall also argue that Leibniz does not straightforwardly affirm the continual creation doctrine, that is, he does not take it to provide a metaphysically rigorous description of God s creative activity. Although he is willing to affirm the doctrine in some sense, he does not think that God literally re-creates the world in a successive series of instantaneous states. These important interpretive results give rise to an additional question: in exactly what non-literal sense is Leibniz willing to affirm the continual creation doctrine? Unfortunately, Leibniz does not provide a fully explicit answer to this question. I do think, however, that it is possible to formulate a plausible interpretive hypothesis about his considered view on the matter. In the final section of the paper I suggest that Leibniz is willing to affirm the continual creation doctrine because it provides an acceptable way of conceptualizing the dependence of creatures on God at the level of appearances. His deep metaphysical view of creation is quite different: in a single act, God creates and conserves substances that are strictly non-spatial and atemporal. Although Leibniz does not explicitly affirm this account of creation I shall argue that central features of his metaphysics point in its direction. The interpretive hypothesis also serves to elucidate a number of Leibniz s terse comments on the continual creation doctrine and the duration of finite substances, among other things. One thing that counts in favor of the interpretive hypothesis I present concerning Leibniz s considered view on creation is that it nicely compliments the interpretive results of the earlier sections of this paper. I want to emphasize, however, that the earlier interpretive results and the interpretive hypothesis of the final section are logically independent. The earlier results are significant in their own right and do

3 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 3 not depend on the more speculative interpretive hypothesis that I present in the final section of the paper. II. THE DOCTRINE OF CONTINUAL CREATION: THREE PROBLEMS In keeping with standard Christian doctrine, Leibniz holds that all finite substances depend on God for their existence. This dependence does not merely consist in the fact that God creates them, but also in the fact that God conserves them in their continued existence. Leibniz does not think that the conservation of a substance differs intrinsically from its creation, and so affirms an account of conservation that equates it with continual creation. Here are some characteristic remarks from two of Leibniz s most famous essays: [1] It is quite true that, speaking with metaphysical rigor, there is no real influence of one created substance on another, and that all things, with all their reality, are continually produced [continuellement produites] by the power of God. (New System of Nature; G 4, 483; AG, 143) [2] God alone is the primitive unity or the first simple substance; all created or derivative monads are products, and are generated, so to speak [pour ainsi dire], by continual fulgurations [fulgurations continuelles] of the divinity from moment to moment. (Mon 47, G 6, 614; AG, 219) These texts show that Leibniz is willing to affirm continual creation, but they do not reveal how the doctrine is to be understood in its specifics. 7 One important question to consider is whether the doctrine implies that the world literally comes into existence in a series of distinct states. Leibniz s talk in text [2] of continual fulgurations of the divinity from moment to moment suggests an affirmative answer to this question, though he does qualify his remarks with a pour ainsi dire. A more explicit affirmation of this position occurs in an oft-cited letter to Electress Sophie. 8 Before quoting from the letter, however, a few words should be said about its context. In late 1705 Leibniz s correspondence with the Electress took an excursion into matters metaphysical. The occasion for this excursion was the publication of a book on geometry by the Duke of Bourgogne, an extract of which Leibniz had read in the Journal des Savants. In the extract the Duke touched upon one of Leibniz s favorite subjects the notion of unity to which he raised the following objection: Here is our argument... reduced to strange extremes. Geometry shows us the divisibility of matter to infinity, and we find at the same time that it is composed of indivisibles (31 October 1705, HK, 148). After reminiscing about previous discussions with Queen Sophie Charlotte (the daughter of the Electress) on the subject, Leibniz proceeds to resolve the Duke s puzzle by noting that the actual division of matter does not at all prevent matter from being composed [composée] of simple and indivisible substances, since the multitude of these substances or of these unities is infinite (HK, ). 9 In the remainder of the letter Leibniz makes additional remarks on matter, composition, continuity, and several related

4 4 JOHN WHIPPLE topics. These remarks have been taken by some commentators to provide us with crucial insights into the structure of Leibniz s metaphysics. 10 Towards the end of the letter Leibniz affirms the continual creation doctrine in the following way: [3] The duration of things, or the multitude of momentaneous states, is the accumulation [l amas] of an infinity of bursts [eclats] of the divinity, of which each one at each instant is a creation or reproduction of all things, there not at all being a continuous passage [passage continuel], to speak properly, from one state to the next. (HK, 154) Three things should be noted about this text. First, it says that the conservation of the world consists in its literally being re-created in a successive series of distinct instantaneous states. Second, it says that the transition between successive states is not at all continuous, which suggests that there are metaphysical gaps of some sort between successive states. Third, Leibniz takes this account of divine creation and conservation to be a traditional one. In the sentence immediately following text [3] he says that this identification of conservation with continual creation is a celebrated truth of theologians and Christian philosophers (HK, 154). A number of additional texts that I shall present in subsequent sections of this paper will confirm that Leibniz takes this to be an accurate characterization of the continual creation doctrine as it has been traditionally affirmed (particularly by the Cartesians). 11 I shall refer to it as the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. 12 On first reading, text [3] suggests that Leibniz himself is willing to straightforwardly affirm the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. One of the central theses I will be defending in this paper is that this in not in fact the case. Before making that argument, however, it will be useful to note several serious problems that a straightforward affirmation of the Traditional Account would raise in the context of Leibniz s philosophical system. In order to properly formulate the first two problems, some background on Leibniz s theory of finite substance must be provided. 13 Leibniz consistently and frequently affirms that finite substances are active beings, and that they are active in virtue of possessing an internal force or power. In the De Volder correspondence, for example, he writes: What I take to be the indivisible or complete monad is the substance endowed with primitive power, active and passive, like the I or something similar (20 June 1703, G 2, 251; AG, 176). A substance is active because it has an internal force, but what exactly does its activity consist in? The answer to this question can be discerned in Leibniz s thesis that created substances exhibit spontaneity. A substance is said to be spontaneous or active if everything must arise for it from its own depths (New System of Nature, G 4, 484; AG, 143). By everything Leibniz means all of a substance s modifications or states. These modifications, often called appearances or expressions, are a substance s successive perceptual states. To say that these perceptual states arise from a substance s own depths is to say that they are produced or caused by the substance s internal force. The doctrine of spontaneity is of a piece with Leibniz s denial of inter-substantial causation. No

5 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 5 finite substance needs to cause a change in the modifications of any other finite substance, for all of the modifications of each substance are caused or produced by the substance itself. 14 We can now formulate the first (and most obvious) problem associated with the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. Leibniz characterizes finite substances as essentially active, but it is not clear how the Traditional Account could leave any room, as it were, for this purported activity. Leibniz frequently claims that God creates every finite substance with an internal force, which produces everything that will ever happen to it in an orderly way. But on its face text [3] seems to be saying that the only thing that happens to a substance is that it is created and re-created ex-nihilo in a series of successive states. The production of each state would appear to result directly from God s creative activity, not from the substance s primitive force of action. I shall refer to this as the Problem of Activity. The Problem of Activity has received a fair amount of attention in the secondary literature. 15 It is crucial to recognize, however, that it is not the only problem that the doctrine of continual creation raises within Leibniz s metaphysics. Another problem, which is at least as serious as the Problem of Activity, I shall term the Problem of Endurance. This problem arises because of the way that Leibniz characterizes the transition between created states in text [3]. He writes that to speak properly there is not at all a continuous passage from one state to the next. This seems to imply that that there is a metaphysical gap, of some sort, separating each state from its succeeding state. But if this is correct, then nothing that is created at one instant could endure, strictly speaking, to the next instant a conclusion that seems to undermine the very possibility of an ontology of enduring substances. 16 Leibniz is fond of saying that monads can only begin by creation and end by annihilation (Monadology 6, G 6, 607; AG, 213). The account of creation presented in text [3] appears to take this idea to the extreme, implying that substances are created and annihilated at every instant. 17 The third problem associated with the Cartesian Account of Creation is related to Leibniz s view on time. The Traditional Account implies that the history of the world consists in a series of instantaneous states. But such a conception of the created world seems to resolve time into instants. In the Theodicy Leibniz notes this apparent implication: [4] This dogma [continual creation] appears to resolve time into moments, whereas others regard moments and points as mere modalities of the continuum, that is, as extremities of the parts that can be assigned to it, and not as constituent parts. (T, 384, emphasis Leibniz) This apparent implication poses a significant problem for Leibniz because he is one of the others who denies that instants are constituent parts of time. According to Leibniz, time is a continuous quantity that lacks actual parts; it is not composed of instants. 18 This is the Problem of Time, the solution of which would involve showing how Leibniz could simultaneously embrace the doctrine of continual creation and deny that time is composed of instants.

6 6 JOHN WHIPPLE In 1708 Leibniz tells his correspondent Bartholomew Des Bosses, My views certainly are connected with each other in such a way that no link can be removed without the chain being broken (October 1708, G 2, ). The results of the present section might lead one to draw a different conclusion, however, for it is difficult to see how the link of continual creation fits together with other links in Leibniz s metaphysical chain, particularly his account of finite substance and his account of time. Can the doctrine of continual creation be rendered consistent with the fundamental tenets of Leibniz s metaphysics, or must we conclude that some of his central metaphysical doctrines are ultimately incompatible? III. TIME, DURATION, AND CONTINUITY The aim of this section is to discuss one possible solution to the Problem of Time a solution that is based on an important distinction Leibniz draws between time and duration. In order to do this, Leibniz s thought on the famed labyrinth of the continuum will have to be engaged. Recent scholarship has shown that continuity is a very important subject in Leibniz s philosophy. 19 The details of his analysis of the various problems and issues pertaining to continuity are a matter of scholarly controversy, however, and full treatment of them far exceeds the scope of this paper. For our purposes we need only focus on largely uncontroversial features of Leibniz s analysis. A brief discussion of these features will show that Leibniz s views on continuity do not bode well for a straightforward commitment to the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. Although there is a way in which the Problem of Time might be solved without rejecting the Traditional Account, this solution would have implications that Leibniz could not accept. The discussion as a whole will underscore just how problematic it would be for Leibniz to straightforwardly affirm the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. Leibniz typically draws the distinction between time and duration in tandem with an analogous distinction between space and extension. One place he draws these distinctions is in the correspondence with De Volder. In his 30 June 1704 letter Leibniz quotes two of De Volder s claims: I conceive innumerable properties of mathematical body that are very evident, and I conceive of the mathematical body as existing and inhering in nothing else (G 2, ; AG, 179). Leibniz concedes the first claim but rejects the second, noting: [5] If by the mathematical body [corpus mathematicum] you mean space, it must be compared with time; if you mean extension, it must be compared with duration. Indeed, space is only the order of existing for possibles that exist simultaneously, just as time is the order of existing for possibles that exist successively. And the state or series of things relates to time just as the physical body relates to space. Body and the series of things [series rerum] add motion to space and to time, that is, they add action and passion and their source [principium]. (G 2, 269; AG, 179, emphasis Leibniz) In this passage Leibniz claims that De Volder fails to take account of the distinction between extension and space. De Volder s corpus mathematicum is nothing other

7 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 7 than the Cartesian conception of extended substance, a conception that Leibniz regards as fundamentally confused. It confuses space something abstract and ideal, with what Leibniz variously calls extension, or bodies, and which he describes as determinate and real. Neither space nor bodies are substances, strictly speaking, although the latter are well-founded on monads. In his remarks to De Volder, Leibniz uses extension as a synonym for body. It is not quite as clear what duration is signifying in the passage. He writes that the state or series of things relates to time just as the physical body relates to space. Here duration is being identified with the series of things, but what, exactly, are the things in question? The analogy with extension/space suggests that the series of things are bodies considered insofar as they exist successively. However, in the next sentence Leibniz states that body and the series of things add motion to space and to time, that is, they add action and passion and their source [principium]. Given that monads are the ultimate principium of action and passion, the series of things should also signify monads insofar as they exist successively. If this is correct, then the extension/space duration/time distinctions are not perfectly analogous, for duration, but not extension, applies to both bodies and monads. 20 Our focus is on the distinction between duration and time, particularly as it applies to monads. Duration, Leibniz claims, is an attribute of monads. Text [5] suggests that the duration of a monad just is the monad insofar as it exists successively. Monads have their own duration, but they do not have their own time. There is only one time. It is something ideal, which is abstracted from durational things, and that serves to measure them. Leibniz thus speaks of time as the order of successive existences. He is also explicit in affirming that time is continuous. This is a characteristic of time that merits underscoring. One sure way to entangle oneself in the labyrinth of the continuum is to attempt to specify how something continuous could be composed out of actual parts. 21 One uncontroversial feature of Leibniz s analysis of continuity is his denial that there can be any such composition in continuous quantities. This means that time, as a continuous quantity, is not composed out of instants. Instants are merely limits or extremities, not actual parts of time. One can specify an interval of time, and regard that interval as a part of time. Indeed, Leibniz thinks that this can be done in an indefinite number of ways. But the whole of time is prior to any of these parts, which Leibniz characterizes as possible rather than actual. Time can be arbitrarily divided into such parts, but it is not composed out of them. Enough has been said about the distinction between time and duration to understand one way it might be employed to solve the Problem of Time. According to the Traditional Account of Continual Creation, every finite substance is re-created in a successive series of distinct instantaneous states. Given the distinction between duration and time, this would imply that a substance s duration is composed out of a series of instantaneous states, but it would not necessarily imply that time must be so composed. The latter implication could be avoided because time, unlike duration,

8 8 JOHN WHIPPLE is not an attribute of things; it is merely something ideal that is abstracted from durational things, and which serves to measure them. If these observations were supplemented with a complimentary account of abstraction, the Problem of Time could be solved within the strictures of the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. 22 Let us now turn our attention to the merits (or, rather, demerits) of the abovesketched solution to the Problem of Time. This solution would absolve Leibniz of a commitment to temporal atomism, but only at the price of a commitment to durational atomism. And it is not at all obvious that the latter commitment would be less problematic than the former within his philosophical system. In the first place, the account of durational atomism presented in text [3] affirms the existence of instantaneous perceptual states. However, such states should, on Leibniz s principles, be mere nothings. He is clear in affirming that the instant is not, properly speaking, a part of time. For... the whole and the part must be homogenous (3 April 1716 letter to Bourguet; G 3, 591). A part of time must involve an interval of some length or other (this is what makes it homogenous or of the same sort as the whole of time). Any part of time that one specifies is divisible into smaller parts, which themselves are divisible into smaller parts, and so on, ad infinitum. No matter how long this process of subdivision is continued, one will never arrive at an instant. Instants are merely termini of specified parts or limits towards which processes of subdivision can approach. 23 But if an instant is only a limit, then an instantaneous perceptual state should only be a limiting notion as well. To speak of such a state should be to speak of something ideal, not of something actual or real. 24 Leibniz explicitly draws this conclusion in an argument for the conclusion that there are no precise shapes in nature: Now I believe that what is only in a moment has no existence, since it begins and ends at the same time (FC, 245). 25 If a single instantaneous state could be nothing real, then neither could a series of such states. One can t get a something out of a series of nothings. This implies that if the duration of a monad were composed out of a series of momentary states, then the duration of a monad and presumably the monad itself would reduce to nothing. In other words, to suppose that the duration of a monad could be composed out of a series of instantaneous states would be to throw Leibniz back into the labyrinth of the continuum headlong. 26 Even if one were to suppose that the difficulty concerning instantaneous existence could be put to one side, one would still have to contend with Leibniz s assertion that a continuum cannot be composed out of actual parts. This means that if the duration of a substance were composed out of a series of instantaneous perceptual states (or a series of perceptual states of some duration or other), then the duration of a substance would be discontinuous. Durational atomism thus leads to the conclusion that substances do not endure, strictly speaking, beyond an instant (or a state of some duration or other). It is highly unlikely that Leibniz would accept this conclusion one that appears to undermine the possibility of an ontology of enduring substances. The solution to the Problem of Time under consideration thus appears to render the Problem of Endurance insoluble. And it is difficult to

9 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 9 see how a solution to the Problem of Activity could be provided in the absence of a solution to the Problem of Endurance. We seem driven to the conclusion, then, that this so-called solution to the Problem of Time would not allow Leibniz to successfully incorporate the Traditional Account of Continual Creation into his metaphysical system. If Leibniz straightforwardly affirms the Traditional Account, then the coherence of his metaphysics cannot be salvaged. 27 IV. CONTINUAL CREATION IN THE DE VOLDER CORRESPONDENCE The considerations set forth in 2 and 3 have shown that a straightforward commitment to the Traditional Account of Continual Creation would raise serious problems within Leibniz s metaphysics. Given these results, one must ask: does Leibniz take the text [3] discussion of continual creation to provide a literal account of God s creative activity? I am convinced that the answer to this question is no. In the next two sections I shall consider some of Leibniz s remarks that are explicitly critical of the Traditional Account. In this section I shall examine Leibniz s remarks on continual creation in the De Volder correspondence. In addition to revealing hostility to the Traditional Account, these texts will provide us with the materials for a more nuanced interpretation of text [3]. The doctrine of continual creation comes to the fore in some of the earliest letters in the De Volder correspondence. One of De Volder s initial questions concerned Leibniz s principle that there are no leaps in transitions. De Volder was sympathetic to this principle, but he hoped that Leibniz could provide an a priori demonstration of it. Leibniz responded as follows: [6] This is the axiom that I use no transition is made through a leap. I hold that this follows from the law of order and rests upon the same reason by which everyone knows that motion does not occur in a leap; that is, that a body can move from one place to another only through intervening positions. I admit that once we have assumed that the Author of things has willed continuity of motion, this itself will exclude the possibility of leaps. But how can we prove that he has willed this, except through experience or by reason of order? For since all things happen by the perpetual production of God, or, as they say [ut loquuntur], by continual creation [continua creatione], why could he not have transcreated [transcreare] a body, so to speak, from one place to another distant place, leaving behind a gap either in time or in space. (24 March/3 April 1699, G 2, 168; L, , emphasis Leibniz) From the point of view of the present study, Leibniz s remarks in text [6] initially seem rather troubling. Although the specifics of the doctrine of continual creation are not enumerated, Leibniz appears to be invoking the Traditional Account, and there are no clear indications that he would be hesitant in affirming it. His use of the locution as they say shows, in a rather vague way, that he regards continual creation as a frequently affirmed doctrine. But who are the they of whom Leibniz speaks? An answer to this question is provided in one of Leibniz s subsequent

10 10 JOHN WHIPPLE letters. Responding to De Volder s complaint that he (De Volder) did not understand the notion of transcreation (or continual creation), Leibniz writes: [7] I added the hypothesis of transcreation for the sake of illustration, speaking philosophically and particularly like the Cartesians [imprimis cum Cartesianis], who say, with some ground [non male], that God creates all things continually. For them, therefore, moving a body is nothing but reproducing it in successively different places, and it would have to be shown that this reproduction cannot take place in leaps. Rather, this could not be shown without returning to the reason which I have proposed for the universal law of continuity. If you do not accept such a re-creation of things, however, the same thing must be said regardless of what the cause of motion may be. (G 2, 193; L, 521, emphasis added) This text makes it clear that the they spoken of in text [6] is the Cartesians. It is particularly interesting that Leibniz now says that he was speaking like the Cartesians in his earlier letter. He indicates that there is something correct about the continual creation doctrine by noting that the Cartesians affirm it non male. Leibniz proceeds to explain what motion consists in for them, namely transcreation, and subsequently claims that they would have to prove that re-production cannot take place in leaps. Leibniz argues that if De Volder does not accept such an account of transcreation, he still needs to prove that motion is continuous in nature, and this can only be done by means of the law of order. He states that: [8] Anyone who rejects continuity in things will say that motion in its essence is nothing but a succession of leaps through intervening intervals, which flow from the action of God and not from the nature of the thing moved, or which are recreations by God in separate places. His philosophizing will then be almost like that which would compound matter out of mere discrete points and would support this opinion on the ground of the labyrinthine difficulties which surround the nature of continuity, from which there do indeed follow, not the necessity of leaps, but some other things which are not usually well understood. (G 2, 193; L, 521) This text tells strongly against the idea that Leibniz is straightforwardly committed to the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. It suggests that persons who are committed to such a view must affirm (or at least are hard pressed to affirm) the discontinuity of motion, a position that is of a piece with the view that matter is compounded out of distinct points. As is well known, Leibniz unequivocally rejects this latter view as absurd. 28 The letters to De Volder do not reveal all the details of Leibniz s considered views on continual creation, but they are instructive. His remarks in texts [7] and [8] strongly suggest that he does not think that the Traditional Account of Continual Creation provides a literal description of God s creation and conservation of the world. The most important conclusion to note, however, is that in special contexts Leibniz is capable of baldly endorsing the Traditional Account even though his considered views on creation are more nuanced. This provides us with a powerful

11 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 11 interpretive tool for analyzing Leibniz s remarks on continual creation in text [3]. Perhaps this is another place where Leibniz is writing as if he is straightforwardly committed to the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. Leibniz does not come out and say that he is proceeding in this manner, and for this reason the interpretation I am suggesting might seem counterintuitive. But neither does Leibniz tell De Volder that he is speaking like the Cartesians in text [6]. If De Volder had not forced him to clarify his remarks on continual creation, text [6], like text [3], would appear to be an affirmation of the Traditional Account. If this interpretation is on the right track, one need not conclude that Leibniz is being disingenuous in the letter to Sophie, for he does endorse the doctrine of continual creation in some (yet to be specified) way. He might simply be omitting the fact that he does not straightforwardly affirm the Traditional Account of the doctrine. V. CONTINUAL CREATION AND THEISTIC PROOF In this section I shall consider whether an analysis of the duration of things can serve as an argument for the existence of God. I shall argue that Leibniz does not think that a theistic proof based on the duration of things is sound. If one were committed to the account of duration presupposed by the Traditional Account of Continual Creation, however, then one could infer the existence of God from the duration of things. The fact that Leibniz rejects this sort of argument provides powerful support for the thesis that he is not straightforwardly committed to the Traditional Account. Let us begin by considering Leibniz s comments on one of the theistic proofs that Descartes sets forth in the Principles of Philosophy. Here is Descartes argument: [9] The nature of time is such that its parts are not mutually dependent, and never coexist. Thus, from the fact that we now exist, it does not follow that we shall exist a moment from now, unless there is some cause the same cause which originally produced us which continually reproduces us, as it were, that is to say, which keeps us in existence. (AT 8A, 13; CSM1, 200) Leibniz does not think that this purported proof succeeds. His criticism (written in 1692) runs as follows: [10] From the fact that we now are, it follows that we will be in the next moment, unless there exists a reason for change. And so, unless it were established in some other way that we cannot even exist without the beneficence of God, nothing is established about the existence of God from our own duration; as if one part of this duration were entirely independent of another, which we cannot admit. (G 4, 360; L, 387) Leibniz rejects Descartes proof because it falsely assumes that the parts of our duration are entirely independent of each other. This, in turn, suggests that Leibniz would not straightforwardly accept the Traditional Account of Continual Creation, for if the duration of a substance consisted in a successive series of instantaneous states,

12 12 JOHN WHIPPLE as the Traditional Account requires, then each state would be entirely independent of every other state. Text [10] thus appears to be hostile to durational atomism. Leibniz does not fully elaborate his own positive account of duration in text [10], but he is perfectly clear in asserting that nothing is established about the existence of God from our own duration. This remark directly contradicts the account of duration presented in the 1705 letter to Sophie. In that letter, in the paragraph following text [3], he says that the analysis of the actual duration of things in time brings us demonstratively to the existence of God (HK, 155). What are we to make of this textual contradiction? Given that his remarks on the Principles were written more than a decade before the letter to Sophie, is it possible that Leibniz changed his mind on the merit of a theistic argument based on the duration of things? This is unlikely, for Leibniz reiterates his critique of Descartes proof in the Theodicy of After paraphrasing Descartes argument, he responds: One may answer that in fact it does not follow of necessity that, because I am, I shall be; but this follows naturally, nevertheless, that is, of itself, per se, if nothing prevents it (T, 383, emphasis Leibniz). The only difference between this remark and those made in his examination of the Principles is that now Leibniz distinguishes following of necessity from following naturally. The Cartesians assume that our continued existence does not follow in either of these two senses. Leibniz agrees that it does not follow in the former sense, but he thinks that it does follow in the latter sense. It will be crucial to determine how the notion of following naturally should be understood. Leibniz identifies it with the notion of following from the nature of a thing. A variant of the latter locution occurs in the next paragraph, where Leibniz briefly mentions a theistic proof provided by Erhard Weigel. This proof, which clearly presupposes durational atomism, does not differ in any substantial way from Descartes proof, and it elicits the same negative judgment: There would be need of a more exact proof if that is to be called a demonstration.... In particular it must be shown that the privilege of enduring more than a moment by its nature belongs to the necessary being alone (T, 384). Leibniz does not provide a fully articulated account of his views on duration or continual creation in the Theodicy, but we can infer several things about what his account of duration is not. It is not the view of Descartes, the Cartesians, and other philosophers and theologians, according to which the existence of God can be inferred directly from a consideration of the duration of things. This strongly suggests that Leibniz is not setting forth his considered account of duration in the letter to Sophie, where he presents the very theistic proof that is rejected in the comments on Descartes Principles and the Theodicy, which bracket it in date of composition. The driving consideration that leads Leibniz to reject this sort of theistic proof appears to be a rejection of durational atomism. If this is correct, then Leibniz does not take the Traditional Account of Continual Creation to provide a literal account of the duration of substances, for the Traditional Account presupposes that at least durational atomism is true (if not temporal atomism).

13 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 13 VI. AN ALTERNATIVE ACCOUNT OF CREATION Let us pause to summarize the results of this paper thus far. First, I have argued that Leibniz takes the standard view of continual creation to involve the literal recreation of all things in a successive series of instantaneous states. Second, I have argued that a straightforward commitment to the Traditional Account would give rise to devastating inconsistencies within Leibniz s mature metaphysics. Third, I have provided nearly conclusive support for the thesis that Leibniz does not straightforwardly affirm the Traditional Account of Continual Creation. Although he does think that there is some truth to the doctrine, he does not think that God literally re-creates the world in a series of instantaneous states. These conclusions run counter to the assertions of several influential Leibniz commentators who have variously affirmed (1) that Leibniz did (at least relatively) straightforwardly affirm the continual creation doctrine, 29 (2) that such a commitment can be reconciled with the central tenets of Leibniz s metaphysics, 30 and (3) that Leibniz s 1705 letter to Sophie (which does display an account of continual creation that is in keeping with the Traditional Account) should be regarded as the locus classicus for his views on the labyrinth of the continuum and his metaphysics more generally. 31 These interpretive results naturally lead to additional questions: what is Leibniz s considered view on creation (and conservation), and in exactly what sense is he willing to affirm the continual creation doctrine? Leibniz does not directly address these questions. This could mean a number of different things. Leibniz might have been hesitant to reveal his considered view on these matters because he thought they would be too controversial, or too likely to be misunderstood. 32 Alternatively, he might not have had a fully worked out positive view in the first place. 33 Although neither of these (and other) possibilities can be conclusively established, I suspect that the former explanation is closer to the truth. Accordingly, in this concluding section of the paper I will be making two somewhat controversial assumptions: (a) that Leibniz is quite serious when he claims that his mature metaphysics is deeply systematic, and (b) that Leibniz does have a considered view on divine creation and conservation. I will present an account of what I think Leibniz s considered view is and present indirect evidence for it. The plausibility of this interpretive hypothesis will be determined (given the above-stated assumptions) by how well it coheres with Leibniz s theory of substance, his views on space and time, and his critical comments on the Traditional Account of Continual Creation, among other things. It will not be possible to complete all of these tasks in the present paper, of course. My more modest aim is to say enough about the interpretive hypothesis to show that it is worthy of further consideration. Before proceeding, let me be explicit about two things. First, the interpretive hypothesis that I explore in this section is admittedly more speculative than the interpretive theses that have been defended in the earlier sections of this paper. Second, the earlier results are independent of my interpretive hypothesis about Leibniz s considered view on creation. Some readers may be unwilling to grant assumptions (a) and (b). Others may grant me the assumptions but remain

14 14 JOHN WHIPPLE unconvinced of the plausibility of the interpretive hypothesis. In neither case would the results of the earlier sections be compromised. I am not the first Leibniz commentator to present an interpretive hypothesis concerning Leibniz s considered view on creation and conservation. 34 An interpretation set forth by French commentator Jaques Jalabert shares several key features with the interpretation that I incline towards. Jalabert approaches Leibniz s accounts of creation and finite substance by focusing on Leibniz s analysis of time. He (along with many other commentators) takes Leibniz to hold that finite substances are non-spatial and atemporal at the deepest level of metaphysical rigor. 35 If Leibniz is indeed an atemporalist, then what account of creation and conservation is he most likely committed to? A view according to which God creates and conserves nonspatial and atemporal substances in a single, miraculous, act. I shall refer to this reductive account of creation as the Strict Metaphysical Account of Creation. 36 Let us begin the exposition of the Strict Metaphysical Account by noting two related objections that might be raised against it. The first objection is that if God creates substances that are atemporal, then the finite substances composing the world could not change. But Leibniz clearly affirms that substances do change: I also take for granted that every created being, and consequently the created monad as well, is subject to change (Monadology 10, G 6, 608; AG, 214). The second objection is that the Strict Metaphysical Account would preclude monadic activity. As we have seen, monadic activity is closely related to monadic change. A substance is active if its successive states (or modifications) are self-produced. But if a substance never changed its state, then a forteriori it could not be the source of its successive states. In short, monadic activity seems to presuppose monadic change; if the latter does not occur, then neither does the former. The two objections to the Strict Metaphysical Account, then, are that it precludes change and activity, which are important features of Leibniz s metaphysics (worries of this sort have led a number of important Leibniz commentators to conclude that his commitment to atemporality conflicts with other features of his metaphysics). 37 The first thing to note about these objections is that they appear to assume that atemporality is incompatible with Leibnizian change and activity. It is not clear that this is a legitimate assumption. Leibniz defines change as an aggregate of contradictory states where one state follows from the other. 38 As Michael Futch has noted, this following from need not be interpreted temporally (though it often has been) (2008, 161). 39 Similarly, the following of a monad s series of states from its primitive force might also admit of a non-temporal interpretation. In support of the suggestion that activity does not necessarily entail temporality one can consider that God is an exemplar of a causally active being in the Leibnizian universe. 40 And God s activity is certainly not temporally conditioned. The initial point that I want to make, then, is that Leibnizian change and activity are not obviously incompatible with atemporality. Attributing an atemporal notion of change to Leibniz is not the only possible strategy for reconciling his remarks on change with the Strict Metaphysical Account

15 CONTINUAL CREATION AND FINITE SUBSTANCE IN LEIBNIZ 15 of Creation. Another possibility (the one that I will explore in the remainder of this paper) is that Leibniz s considered view on change is that it is a well-founded phenomenon. 41 In order to explain this interpretive strategy a few general comments must be made about Leibniz s ontology. The first point to recognize is that Leibniz s ontology countenances degrees of reality. This point is incontestable; the challenge is to determine exactly how the various degrees of reality are sorted out. Some recent commentators have argued that Leibniz s mature ontology is distinguishable into three levels or tiers : the monadic, the phenomenal, and the ideal. 42 The monadic level, which is constituted by monads, is the most real tier in the ontology. On the other end of the spectrum are ideal things, such as space and time. These entities are purely mental, and thereby possess the least reality in the ontology. The phenomenal level, in contrast, is positioned midway between the monadic and ideal levels. Bodies and motion are paradigmatic examples of things that are phenomenal; they are more real than ideal entities like space and time, but they are not fully real, that is, they do not comprise the metaphysical ground floor of Leibniz s ontology. They are more real than ideal entities because they are grounded or well-founded on monads. 43 One important thing to note here is that Leibniz sometimes simply refers to phenomenal entities as real. 44 This shows that the mere fact that Leibniz refers to change as real does not automatically imply that he takes it to be fully real. Recall that change is defined in terms of successive states. This implies that if successive states are (in a certain sense) phenomenal, change must be phenomenal as well. The question of whether successive states are phenomenal depends in part on how they are individuated. Leibniz does not say a great deal about the individuation of successive monadic states or about the precise structure of intra-substantial causation (as many commentators have noted). 45 He does, however, characterize successive states as limitations, and he says that substances produce modifications by changes in their limits. 46 Here is one way (admittedly an extrapolation from the texts) to understand these suggestive claims. A substance individuates a state by reflectively specifying temporal boundaries for an interval of its duration boundaries that consist in the preceding and succeeding states of the interval in question. By bounding or limiting the initial interval these states make it determinate. However, this would not make the initial state completely determinate, for complete determination could only be attained if the states that limit the initial interval were themselves determinate. This means that the states bounding the intervals that determine the initial interval must also be specified. But then the states bounding the intervals that determine the intervals that determine the initial interval must also be specified, and so on, ad infinitum. This suggests that a state is individuated to the extent that the series of states that bound it are specified, but that no state is ever rigorously individuated as this would require, per impossible, the specification of an infinite series of states. The regress of determination involved in the individuation of monadic states is in keeping with the thesis that successive states are only distinguished at the level

16 16 JOHN WHIPPLE of phenomena. It implies that the monad as a completely determinate and nonaggregated whole is ontologically and conceptually prior to its reflectively specified successive states. It is conceptually prior because the only way to conceive a state is by conceiving it as a limitation of the prior whole. It is ontologically prior because if the monad did not exist as a determinate whole it would not be possible to reflectively specify a state or a series of states. According to this analysis, any state that is specified follows from the substance (or, equivalently, it follows from the substance s nature or primitive force ), and all of a substance s states can be said to arise from its own depths. One might observe that the analysis provided above does not strictly imply that the successive states of a monad are phenomenal. At most the analysis (if correct) shows that finite substances are only capable of individuating successive states at the level of phenomena. Surely it does not rule out the possibility that successive states are individuated from the perspective of divine omniscience. 47 I concede that this is a possibility. Nevertheless, I do not think that successive states are individuated at the deepest level of metaphysical rigor. To see why this is so a distinction must be drawn between a monad s successive states and its détail. Leibniz frequently claims that monads involve a plurality of modifications or internal détail; he also claims that each substance involves a series of successive states. 48 But what is the relation between a substance s détail and its successive states? One might think that a monad s successive states and its détail are one and the same, but I believe that Leibniz is working with a subtle distinction here. In virtue of its expression or representation of all of the other substances in the world (the expression thesis as it is called in the secondary literature), each monad possesses détail. 49 This détail is something that the monad possesses from the perspective of divine omniscience (i.e., sub specie aeternitatis). The successive states of a monad, on the other hand, have temporal boundaries, which are distinguished only at the level of phenomena. Such boundaries are not perceived from the perspective of divine omniscience. This does not mean that successive states are not real, for the temporal boundaries that are reflectively specified limit or carve up a monad s détail. There is thus a foundation in reality for any state or series of states that is reflectively specified at the level of phenomena. In other words, the reality of a state consists in the détail that it confusedly contains (the détail is the representational content of the state). But again, no state is more than a well-founded phenomenon because the boundaries that limit the détail exist only at the phenomenal level (a monad s détail is not carved up at the deepest level of reality). 50 The interpretation that I have been sketching emphasizes the notion of reflective individuation. This might lead one to ask the following question: do all monads reflectively individuate states, or is this something that is done only by spirits? The answer to this question, I believe, is that only spirits reflectively individuate states. This is because reflective individuation is a form of apperception, and Leibniz holds that only spirits apperceive. 51 One might worry that this is a conclusion that Leibniz could not admit, however, for it seems to entail that animal souls and entelechies

Space and Time in Leibniz s Early Metaphysics 1. Timothy Crockett, Marquette University

Space and Time in Leibniz s Early Metaphysics 1. Timothy Crockett, Marquette University Space and Time in Leibniz s Early Metaphysics 1 Timothy Crockett, Marquette University Abstract In this paper I challenge the common view that early in his career (1679-1695) Leibniz held that space and

More information

Leibniz on Divine Concurrence

Leibniz on Divine Concurrence Philosophy Compass 5/10 (2010): 865 879, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2010.00331.x Leibniz on Divine Concurrence John Whipple* University of Illinois at Chicago Abstract In this paper I examine G. W. Leibniz s

More information

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument

Time 1867 words Principles of Philosophy God cosmological argument Time 1867 words In the Scholastic tradition, time is distinguished from duration. Whereas duration is an attribute of things, time is the measure of motion, that is, a mathematical quantity measuring the

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics

Class 11 - February 23 Leibniz, Monadology and Discourse on Metaphysics Philosophy 203: History of Modern Western Philosophy Spring 2010 Tuesdays, Thursdays: 9am - 10:15am Hamilton College Russell Marcus rmarcus1@hamilton.edu I. Minds, bodies, and pre-established harmony Class

More information

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON THE MONADOLOGY GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON I. The Two Great Laws (#31-37): true and possibly false. A. The Law of Non-Contradiction: ~(p & ~p) No statement is both true and false. 1. The

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

1/8. Leibniz on Force

1/8. Leibniz on Force 1/8 Leibniz on Force Last time we looked at the ways in which Leibniz provided a critical response to Descartes Principles of Philosophy and this week we are going to see two of the principal consequences

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

LEIBNITZ. Monadology

LEIBNITZ. Monadology LEIBNITZ Explain and discuss Leibnitz s Theory of Monads. Discuss Leibnitz s Theory of Monads. How are the Monads related to each other? What does Leibnitz understand by monad? Explain his theory of monadology.

More information

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies in Nihil Sine Ratione: Mensch, Natur und Technik im Wirken von G. W. Leibniz ed. H. Poser (2001), 720-27. Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies Page 720 I It is

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel)

Reading Questions for Phil , Fall 2013 (Daniel) 1 Reading Questions for Phil 412.200, Fall 2013 (Daniel) Class Two: Descartes Meditations I & II (Aug. 28) For Descartes, why can t knowledge gained through sense experience be trusted as the basis of

More information

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz

First Truths. G. W. Leibniz Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text.

More information

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion)

Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Review Tutorial (A Whirlwind Tour of Metaphysics, Epistemology and Philosophy of Religion) Arguably, the main task of philosophy is to seek the truth. We seek genuine knowledge. This is why epistemology

More information

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible?

Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Is the Existence of the Best Possible World Logically Impossible? Anders Kraal ABSTRACT: Since the 1960s an increasing number of philosophers have endorsed the thesis that there can be no such thing as

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

1/8. The Third Analogy

1/8. The Third Analogy 1/8 The Third Analogy Kant s Third Analogy can be seen as a response to the theories of causal interaction provided by Leibniz and Malebranche. In the first edition the principle is entitled a principle

More information

On Force in Cartesian Physics

On Force in Cartesian Physics On Force in Cartesian Physics John Byron Manchak June 28, 2007 Abstract There does not seem to be a consistent way to ground the concept of force in Cartesian first principles. In this paper, I examine

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central

In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central TWO PROBLEMS WITH SPINOZA S ARGUMENT FOR SUBSTANCE MONISM LAURA ANGELINA DELGADO * In Part I of the ETHICS, Spinoza presents his central metaphysical thesis that there is only one substance in the universe.

More information

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979)

Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979) Primitive Thisness and Primitive Identity by Robert Merrihew Adams (1979) Is the world and are all possible worlds constituted by purely qualitative facts, or does thisness hold a place beside suchness

More information

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII

Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII. Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS. Book VII Vol 2 Bk 7 Outline p 486 BOOK VII Substance, Essence and Definition CONTENTS Book VII Lesson 1. The Primacy of Substance. Its Priority to Accidents Lesson 2. Substance as Form, as Matter, and as Body.

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington

Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington Yitzhak Y. Melamed, Spinoza s Metaphysics: Substance and Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013, xxii + 232 p. Reviewed by Colin Marshall, University of Washington I n his important new study of

More information

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible )

Introduction. I. Proof of the Minor Premise ( All reality is completely intelligible ) Philosophical Proof of God: Derived from Principles in Bernard Lonergan s Insight May 2014 Robert J. Spitzer, S.J., Ph.D. Magis Center of Reason and Faith Lonergan s proof may be stated as follows: Introduction

More information

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God

1/8. Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God 1/8 Descartes 3: Proofs of the Existence of God Descartes opens the Third Meditation by reminding himself that nothing that is purely sensory is reliable. The one thing that is certain is the cogito. He

More information

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza by Erich Schaeffer A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies

1/6. The Resolution of the Antinomies 1/6 The Resolution of the Antinomies Kant provides us with the resolutions of the antinomies in order, starting with the first and ending with the fourth. The first antinomy, as we recall, concerned the

More information

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God

Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God Comments on Leibniz and Pantheism by Robert Adams for The Twelfth Annual NYU Conference on Issues in Modern Philosophy: God Jeffrey McDonough jkmcdon@fas.harvard.edu Professor Adams s paper on Leibniz

More information

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation

Cartesian Aseity in the Third Meditation University of Utah Abstract: In his Mediations, Descartes introduces a notion of divine aseity that, given some other commitments about causation and knowledge of the divine, must be different than the

More information

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 5 27 www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings Eric Watkins Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego,

More information

The cosmological argument (continued)

The cosmological argument (continued) The cosmological argument (continued) Remember that last time we arrived at the following interpretation of Aquinas second way: Aquinas 2nd way 1. At least one thing has been caused to come into existence.

More information

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which

Lecture 3. I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which 1 Lecture 3 I argued in the previous lecture for a relationist solution to Frege's puzzle, one which posits a semantic difference between the pairs of names 'Cicero', 'Cicero' and 'Cicero', 'Tully' even

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD

HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD HUME, CAUSATION AND TWO ARGUMENTS CONCERNING GOD JASON MEGILL Carroll College Abstract. In Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, Hume (1779/1993) appeals to his account of causation (among other things)

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Leibniz on mind-body causation and Pre-Established Harmony. 1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Oriel College, Oxford

Leibniz on mind-body causation and Pre-Established Harmony. 1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Oriel College, Oxford Leibniz on mind-body causation and Pre-Established Harmony. 1 Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Oriel College, Oxford Causation was an important topic of philosophical reflection during the 17th Century. This

More information

Trinity & contradiction

Trinity & contradiction Trinity & contradiction Today we ll discuss one of the most distinctive, and philosophically most problematic, Christian doctrines: the doctrine of the Trinity. It is tempting to see the doctrine of the

More information

Leibniz as Idealist. (Don Rutherford, UCSD) (for the 2005 Central APA, with comments by Dan Garber)

Leibniz as Idealist. (Don Rutherford, UCSD) (for the 2005 Central APA, with comments by Dan Garber) Leibniz as Idealist (Don Rutherford, UCSD) (for the 2005 Central APA, with comments by Dan Garber) Leibniz has long been held to be an idealist. 1 Minimally, this involves the claim that, in his late writings

More information

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against

BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG. Wes Morriston. In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against Forthcoming in Faith and Philosophy BEGINNINGLESS PAST AND ENDLESS FUTURE: REPLY TO CRAIG Wes Morriston In a recent paper, I claimed that if a familiar line of argument against the possibility of a beginningless

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things:

Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge. In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: Lonergan on General Transcendent Knowledge In General Transcendent Knowledge, Chapter 19 of Insight, Lonergan does several things: 1-3--He provides a radical reinterpretation of the meaning of transcendence

More information

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between

A Complex Eternity. One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between Dan Sheffler A Complex Eternity One of the central issues in the philosophy of religion is the relationship between God and time. In the contemporary discussion, the issue is framed between the two opposing

More information

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies

Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies Contemporary Theology I: Hegel to Death of God Theologies ST503 LESSON 16 of 24 John S. Feinberg, Ph.D. Experience: Professor of Biblical and Systematic Theology, Trinity Evangelical Divinity School. At

More information

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature

1/10. Descartes Laws of Nature 1/10 Descartes Laws of Nature Having traced some of the essential elements of his view of knowledge in the first part of the Principles of Philosophy Descartes turns, in the second part, to a discussion

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon

New Aristotelianism, Routledge, 2012), in which he expanded upon Powers, Essentialism and Agency: A Reply to Alexander Bird Ruth Porter Groff, Saint Louis University AUB Conference, April 28-29, 2016 1. Here s the backstory. A couple of years ago my friend Alexander

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

The Structure of Leibnizian Simple Substances John Whipple a a

The Structure of Leibnizian Simple Substances John Whipple a a This article was downloaded by: [University of Illinois Chicago] On: 13 March 2011 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 931209011] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England

More information

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University

a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University a0rxh/ On Van Inwagen s Argument Against the Doctrine of Arbitrary Undetached Parts WESLEY H. BRONSON Princeton University Imagine you are looking at a pen. It has a blue ink cartridge inside, along with

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

Presupposition, Aggregation, and Leibniz s Argument for a Plurality of Substances* Richard T. W. Arthur, McMaster University

Presupposition, Aggregation, and Leibniz s Argument for a Plurality of Substances* Richard T. W. Arthur, McMaster University Presupposition, Aggregation, and Leibniz s Argument for a Plurality of Substances* Richard T. W. Arthur, McMaster University Abstract This paper consists in a study of Leibniz s argument for the infinite

More information

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions.

Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions. Replies to Michael Kremer Since Michael so neatly summarized his objections in the form of three questions, all I need to do now is to answer these questions. First, is existence really not essential by

More information

On Unity and Simple Substance in Leibniz. Samuel Levey, Dartmouth College

On Unity and Simple Substance in Leibniz. Samuel Levey, Dartmouth College On Unity and Simple Substance in Leibniz Samuel Levey, Dartmouth College Abstract What is Leibniz s argument for simple substances? I propose that it is an extension of his prior argument for incorporeal

More information

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard

Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Man and the Presence of Evil in Christian and Platonic Doctrine by Philip Sherrard Source: Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 2, No.1. World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com OF the

More information

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion

Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion Quaerens Deum: The Liberty Undergraduate Journal for Philosophy of Religion Volume 1 Issue 1 Volume 1, Issue 1 (Spring 2015) Article 4 April 2015 Infinity and Beyond James M. Derflinger II Liberty University,

More information

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE

CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE FILOZOFIA Roč. 67, 2012, č. 4 CARTESIAN IDEA OF GOD AS THE INFINITE KSENIJA PUŠKARIĆ, Department of Philosophy, Saint Louis University, USA PUŠKARIĆ, K.: Cartesian Idea of God as the Infinite FILOZOFIA

More information

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Elwes PART I: CONCERNING GOD DEFINITIONS (1) By that which is self-caused

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p.

On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear. Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p. Title On Finitism and the Beginning of the Universe: A Reply to Stephen Puryear Author(s) Loke, TEA Citation Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 2016, v. 94 n. 3, p. 591-595 Issued Date 2016 URL http://hdl.handle.net/10722/220687

More information

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction :

Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Aristotle on the Principle of Contradiction : Book Gamma of the Metaphysics Robert L. Latta Having argued that there is a science which studies being as being, Aristotle goes on to inquire, at the beginning

More information

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X

LOCKE STUDIES Vol ISSN: X LOCKE STUDIES Vol. 18 https://doi.org/10.5206/ls.2018.3525 ISSN: 2561-925X Submitted: 28 JUNE 2018 Published online: 30 JULY 2018 For more information, see this article s homepage. 2018. Nathan Rockwood

More information

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi

UNCORRECTED PROOF GOD AND TIME. The University of Mississippi phib_352.fm Page 66 Friday, November 5, 2004 7:54 PM GOD AND TIME NEIL A. MANSON The University of Mississippi This book contains a dozen new essays on old theological problems. 1 The editors have sorted

More information

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1

Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Bertrand Russell Proper Names, Adjectives and Verbs 1 Analysis 46 Philosophical grammar can shed light on philosophical questions. Grammatical differences can be used as a source of discovery and a guide

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation

The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation Reply to Cover Dennis Plaisted, University of Tennessee at Chattanooga The deepest and most formidable presentation to date of the reductionist interpretation ofleibniz's views on relations is surely to

More information

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind

The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind criticalthinking.org http://www.criticalthinking.org/pages/the-critical-mind-is-a-questioning-mind/481 The Critical Mind is A Questioning Mind Learning How to Ask Powerful, Probing Questions Introduction

More information

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the

Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Spinoza, the No Shared Attribute thesis, and the Principle of Sufficient Reason * Daniel Whiting This is a pre-print of an article whose final and definitive form is due to be published in the British

More information

1/13. Locke on Power

1/13. Locke on Power 1/13 Locke on Power Locke s chapter on power is the longest chapter of the Essay Concerning Human Understanding and its claims are amongst the most controversial and influential that Locke sets out in

More information

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES

THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES THE LEIBNIZ CLARKE DEBATES Background: Newton claims that God has to wind up the universe. His health The Dispute with Newton Newton s veiled and Crotes open attacks on the plenists The first letter to

More information

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists.

From the fact that I cannot think of God except as existing, it follows that existence is inseparable from God, and hence that he really exists. FIFTH MEDITATION The essence of material things, and the existence of God considered a second time We have seen that Descartes carefully distinguishes questions about a thing s existence from questions

More information

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement SPINOZA'S METHOD Donald Mangum The primary aim of this paper will be to provide the reader of Spinoza with a certain approach to the Ethics. The approach is designed to prevent what I believe to be certain

More information

Transcendence J. J. Valberg *

Transcendence J. J. Valberg * Journal of Philosophy of Life Vol.7, No.1 (July 2017):187-194 Transcendence J. J. Valberg * Abstract James Tartaglia in his book Philosophy in a Meaningless Life advances what he calls The Transcendent

More information

MATHEMATICAL ANTINOMIES.

MATHEMATICAL ANTINOMIES. Meeting of the Aristotelian Society at 21, Bedford Square, London, W.C. 1, on November 8th, 1954, at 7.30 p.m. PAPER READ BEFORE THE SOCIETY 1954-55. I.-KANT'S MATHEMATICAL ANTINOMIES. THE PRESIDENTIAL

More information

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi

The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi Kom, 2017, vol. VI (2) : 49 75 UDC: 113 Рази Ф. 28-172.2 Рази Ф. doi: 10.5937/kom1702049H Original scientific paper The Creation of the World in Time According to Fakhr al-razi Shiraz Husain Agha Faculty

More information

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome

obey the Christian tenet You Shall Love The Neighbour facilitates the individual to overcome In Works of Love, Søren Kierkegaard professes that (Christian) love is the bridge between the temporal and the eternal. 1 More specifically, he asserts that undertaking to unconditionally obey the Christian

More information

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview

1. Introduction Formal deductive logic Overview 1. Introduction 1.1. Formal deductive logic 1.1.0. Overview In this course we will study reasoning, but we will study only certain aspects of reasoning and study them only from one perspective. The special

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination

Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination MP_C13.qxd 11/23/06 2:29 AM Page 110 13 Duns Scotus on Divine Illumination [Article IV. Concerning Henry s Conclusion] In the fourth article I argue against the conclusion of [Henry s] view as follows:

More information

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent.

Stang (p. 34) deliberately treats non-actuality and nonexistence as equivalent. Author meets Critics: Nick Stang s Kant s Modal Metaphysics Kris McDaniel 11-5-17 1.Introduction It s customary to begin with praise for the author s book. And there is much to praise! Nick Stang has written

More information

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza Ryan Steed PHIL 2112 Professor Rebecca Car October 15, 2018 Steed 2 While both Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes espouse

More information

Divine Eternity and the Reduplicative Qua. are present to God or does God experience a succession of moments? Most philosophers agree

Divine Eternity and the Reduplicative Qua. are present to God or does God experience a succession of moments? Most philosophers agree Divine Eternity and the Reduplicative Qua Introduction One of the great polemics of Christian theism is how we ought to understand God s relationship to time. Is God timeless or temporal? Does God transcend

More information

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment

A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE. A Paper. Presented to. Dr. Douglas Blount. Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In Partial Fulfillment A CRITIQUE OF THE FREE WILL DEFENSE A Paper Presented to Dr. Douglas Blount Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for PHREL 4313 by Billy Marsh October 20,

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Let me state at the outset a basic point that will reappear again below with its justification. The title of this chapter (and many other discussions too) make it appear

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

15 Does God have a Nature?

15 Does God have a Nature? 15 Does God have a Nature? 15.1 Plantinga s Question So far I have argued for a theory of creation and the use of mathematical ways of thinking that help us to locate God. The question becomes how can

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence

From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Prequel for Section 4.2 of Defending the Correspondence Theory Published by PJP VII, 1 From Necessary Truth to Necessary Existence Abstract I introduce new details in an argument for necessarily existing

More information

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system

On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system On the epistemological status of mathematical objects in Plato s philosophical system Floris T. van Vugt University College Utrecht University, The Netherlands October 22, 2003 Abstract The main question

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7b The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7b The World Kant s metaphysics rested on identifying a kind of truth that Hume and other did not acknowledge. It is called A. synthetic a priori B. analytic a priori C.

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order

Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Ethics Demonstrated in Geometrical Order Benedict Spinoza Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added,

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University

Reply to Lorne Falkenstein RAE LANGTON. Edinburgh University indicates that Kant s reasons have nothing to do with those given in the Nova Dilucidatio argument. Spatio-temporal relations are not reducible to intrinsic properties of things in themselves because they

More information