Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Philosophical Arguments, Gary Gutting 4 May 2005

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Philosophical Arguments, Gary Gutting 4 May 2005"

Transcription

1 Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Philosophical Arguments, Gary Gutting 4 May 2005 Being that Can be Understood is (Not Simply) Language: How Rorty Misappropriates Gadamer Shortly before Hans-Georg Gadamer s death, Richard Rorty wrote a tribute piece on Gadamer s famous dictum, Being that can be understood is language, in which he claimed Gadamer as an ally in his quest to motivate a pragmatic account of truth. 1 Gadamer s hermeneutics, as he sees is, motivate us to abandon all ontological conceptions of essences and correspondence of our ideas with the way things really are, and instead to adopt a strictly nominalist account of the meanings in our language and practices. Gadamer has taught us, Rorty suggests, to move beyond the epistemological presumption that the basis of knowledge and understanding, the foundation of a just community, the character of moral discourse, and our conceptions of self and world refer to a Being beyond our language accessible through rationality, where this is supposed to be the intellectual capacity to bracket all prejudices and subjective conceptions that distort or hide true essences, or whatever might otherwise be the object of universal agreement and progress. [I]n a culture that took Gadamer s slogan to heart, Rorty suggests, rivalries between bishops and biologists, or poets and philosophers, or fuzzies and techies[ ]would not be thought of as controversies about who is in touch with reality and who is still behind the veil of appearances. They would be struggles to capture the imagination, to get other people to use one s vocabulary. 2 Gadamer s hermeneutics, then, enjoin us to see Being encompassing concepts like Truth, the Good, Essence, and so forth pragmatically, as entirely reducible to language; that is, it has no meaning outside the pragmatic use that it might put in service of our ends: Being does not transcend our language in any way, at least not in any way that makes the slightest 1 Richard Rorty (2004) Being that Can be Understood is Language. In Gadamer s Repercussions, Bruce Krajewski, ed. (Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press) See note 3 for an important qualification on the claimed Gadamer as an ally remark. 2 Ibid.,

2 sense to talk about. In this treatment of Rorty s and Gadamer s thought, I will argue that while he can take Gadamer s hermeneutics quite far in service of his position, in the final analysis one cannot engage in hermeneutics of a Gadamerian sort without maintaining a more robust conception of truth and Rorty allows. This will be both a criticism, then, of Rorty s appropriation of Gadamer, 3 but also an argument that Gadamer s reasons for a more robust conception of truth stand as a critique of Rorty s own position. The hermeneutical quest for understanding requires us to approach our subject matter with the initial presumption that what a text, a partner in dialogue, or any other subject of understanding brings before me is not simply a way of speaking, but a claim to truth that must be taken seriously. When we presume that language is more than a pragmatic coping mechanism but is the way that Being reveals itself to the understanding, then hermeneutics becomes an enterprise in legitimation, not simply justification. After explicating what we take to be the central arguments and claims in Rorty s position and the way he finds support in Gadamer s thought (section I), our argument will proceed by explicating the essential role of a conception of transcendent truth in Gadamer s hermeneutics centering in what Gadamer calls the fore-conception of completeness (II). Following this, we will see the implications of this in what Gadamer calls the classical (III), to Rorty s conceptions of ethics and politics, and for the relationship between the human and natural sciences (IV). We will conclude, finally, with some reflections on what Gadamer himself has said in discussion on Rorty in an interview shortly before his death (V). 3 To be fair to Rorty, at least the Rorty of (2004), he admits that he has not offered an account of the real essence of Gadamer s thought (which we presume to be a somewhat ironic statement, since Rorty would consider such a claim senseless anyway), or an account that he thinks Gadamer would necessarily endorse. Rather, he seems to see his project as a suggestion about how a few more horizons might be fused Gadamer s, his own, and those currently coming into use among analytic philosophers (28). So my previous remark that Rorty is claming Gadamer as an ally should be read with this qualification: not an ally in the sense that the essence of each of their thought is the same, but rather in the sense that a Rortian can find much that is useful in Gadamer s hermeneutics toward his or her own project. The criticism I will defend, then, is that Rorty does a disservice to Gadamer s thought by appropriating him for his own theory, when such a treatment denies one of the central and indispensable features of Gadamer s hermeneutics

3 I The central claims of Rorty s pragmatist position are that, first, truth, as the term normally functions in philosophical discourse, putatively refers to something that exists essentially as it is independent of any relation to the way that we conceive it. Put differently, it assumes that there are ways that things really are, to which we aspire our words and representations to match up or correspond. Second, he argues that we have been misled to suppose that the purpose of rational thought and discourse is to get at these essences. Rather, such seeing of essences is a senseless endeavor: essences are no more than our modes of conception, and have no externality or objectivity to them. The demise of logical empiricism and the rejection of the Cartesian rationality, as well as the arguments of Dewey and James, Quine and Wittgenstein, Heidegger and Derrida, have all impressed upon us the absurdity in the supposition that we could get outside our own linguistic conceptions to things themselves, to see if they match up. The truth is not something we could ever attain, therefore we should not suppose that this is ever what we aim at in the sciences, philosophy, or any other field of inquiry and discourse. Third, there is a perfectly sensible alternative to this epistemological conception, namely one in which all of our ways of talking are pragmatically related to the goals that we happen to have; that is, they are simply coping mechanisms for finding our way about in the world. Once we disavow all ambitions to find universal justification of knowledge claims, to apodictic metaphysical truths, to get in touch with ontological reality, and so forth, any of the terms once in the service of these claims are put to a different use within the limitations of pragmatic discourse, if they have any such use; otherwise, we jettison them. Inquiry and discourse thus become means of finding new and interesting ways of saying things, of coping. This pragmatic program avoids the absurdities of the alternative truth-oriented projects, but actually better serves the ends that many of the proponents of these conceptual systems share: control and manipulation of the natural world, - 3 -

4 building inclusivist democratic communities, even ends such as love and friendship. Or so Rorty maintains. Two applications of Rorty s pragmatist program have received particularly substantial criticism in the last few decades: the application to democratic politics and to the relationship of the natural sciences and the human sciences. In each case, Rorty has encountered objections by those who share much of the critique of modernist rationality, but refuse to draw the same ultimate conclusions about truth and language that he does. I will argue in section IV that Gadamer is in this camp as well with, but to prepare the ground we will till the soil of Rorty s thoughts on these issues and how he responds to some of his critics. In the first case, Rorty argues that the democratic ideal of a just society founded on a conception of individuals as free and equal has traditionally found its grounds and justification in the presumption that all rational beings desire truth, that this truth is universal, and that this truth is attainable in the sense of correspondence to reality. 4 If this is so if there is a universal truth that is the object of rationality then we can, in principle at least, base our public institutions and practices on principles of justice that all rational beings can agree to. In this way we can have a society in which justice transcends the particular prejudices, conceptions and values of its members. A similar story might be told, and is told, regarding morality: moral truths be they universal, apodictic, or both are just those rules and principles that the truth-oriented faculty of reason can attend to. Either way, underlying these philosophies, Rorty suggests, is a false contrast between truth and justification connected to a flawed conception of human rationality. Human rationality depends entirely upon the linguisticality of our concepts. We are all situated within webs of significance, and justification is a matter not of comparing the concepts within these webs to the external world, to supra-conceptual universal realities accessible 4 See Richard Rorty (2000), Universality and Truth, in Rorty and His Critics, ed. Robert Brandom (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing), 1-30, from which I have drawn much of the following discussion on his ethics and politics

5 through some pure rational reflection, or to pure transcendental intuitions stripped of prejudices. Rather, justification is a matter of relating these concepts to one another according to certain contextually-determined justificatory standards. Following this, the advocates of a contrast between truth and justification take the obvious fact that my beliefs may not be justified in all possible contexts of inquiry to mean that I may have justified beliefs that are not true. That is to say, there is a presumed fact of the matter apart from the contingencies of my linguistic context to which my beliefs may or may not correspond; given the limitations of our present background knowledge, modes of discourse, theories of justification, prejudices, etc., I may have a belief meets certain (contingent) standards for justification, but may not satisfy that correspondence to which I aspire. Rorty considers this contrast to be nonsensical. For one thing, how could I know that my belief is not only justified but also true? If I claim that a belief is true, then I claim that it is eminently justified, that no standards of justification will ever come along to challenge this. But how could I possibly know this? Perhaps because I can somehow see a reality distinct from the grounds of justification? Whatever we might consider this seeing to be, it would only be further grounds for justification. At any rate, this language of seeing reality is just a circumscriptive way of moving about within our linguistic horizons, not transcending them as the term implies. Rorty s basic argument, then, is that all we do or can aspire to is to broaden our context of justification for our beliefs to include more people, more traditions of inquiry, etc.; adding some further element of truth that we also want our beliefs to aspire to is absurd: we can only aspire to that which is attainable. Since nothing more than justification is attainable, then aspiring towards truth should not be taken to mean anything more than aspiring towards further justification, which is, as we have said, bringing others within our linguistic horizons. More precisely, Rorty argues that the only way in which we should use the concept truth in a different sense than justification is a cautionary one. When we say something like, - 5 -

6 this belief may be justified, but it still may not be true, what we should mean is, this belief may be justified here, now, but there may be other contexts in which it is not justified. 5 Any further use of truth as that which transcends all contexts of justification, which would encompass terms like universal, necessary, unconditional and so forth, since they putatively refer to a reality beyond the reach of our horizons, have no use in political or moral theory and practice, or indeed any theory or practice whatever (save perhaps logic and mathematics, which I will leave aside here). Critics such as Habermas agree that claims to justification are dependent on the norms embedded in the context of our linguistic practices, but that if we reduce validity claims to justification we have undermined the emancipatory possibilities of democratic societies. 6 We cannot ground the claim that racism, sexism, homophobia and the like are not only unjustified, they would be unjust unjustified in themselves even if the norms and concepts of a particular context would seem to provide a justification for these practices and beliefs. When we make a claim like, not only is racism unjustified it s wrong, period, Rorty would take this to mean, and I am willing to defend this claim against anyone anywhere; Habermas, on the other hand, thinks that this should mean something like, even if a society managed to convince everyone that it is justified, they would still be wrong. There is a truth, a fact of the matter about who we are as human beings that preludes racist attitudes and practices, a truth that transcends the contingences of a particular society s norms and conceptions. This is what we are referring to when we claim that racism is wrong, period. Rorty simply responds by reiterating that such a claim only has meaning if this fact of the 5 Rorty often speaks of this as future contexts of justification, but I think this is a bit misleading. All that I think he means by that is to say that there may be contexts in which we attempt to justify our beliefs but fail (which would obviously be in the future to the one doing the justifying). But future contexts in which justification fails can connote an Enlightenment conception of progress which would be unfriendly to his position. That is, someone might take this to imply that our context of justification is better than previous ones but not as good as future ones. But Rorty would point out that this only makes sense when we talk about better with respect to some ideal context in which justification and truth are coextensive, rather like the picture Habermas has in mind. To avoid misunderstandings, then, Rorty should forego future contexts of justification in favor of other or different. 6 See especially Richard Rorty s Pragmatic Turn, in Rorty and His Critics, ed. Robert Brandom (Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing),

7 matter is something to which we can have access beyond our norms and conceptions i.e., beyond the capacities for justification. Without such access, the claim remains empty, and we should instead seek to convince others to adopt our point of view on race relations. There s simply no point in saying, I think racism is wrong for these reasons and I think racism is wrong is true. At best it is akin to the foot stamp (a la Arthur Fine); but most likely it is either empty or misleading. A somewhat different but ultimately related argument leads Rorty to conclude that there is no fundamental split between the methodology of the human sciences (Geisteswissenschaften) and the natural sciences (Naturwissenschaften). The heyday of logical empiricism found philosophers arguing that human behavior is subsumable under the methodologies, laws and formal languages that scientists use to uncover the secrets of the natural world, thus giving rise to such Geisteswissenschaften schools as behaviorism and rational choice theory. Critics came from all sides, but most important for our purposes were those who followed in the Dilthyian and especially the Heideggerian tradition, who maintained that since the subjects of the Geisteswissenschaften are beings embedded in a world of values and meanings internal to their thought and behavior an embeddedness shared also by the scientist objectification of a sort that would reduce them to objects of analysis like rocks and cells to which we might apply a deductive-nomological model of explanation cannot be done without destroying the very meaning of the phenomena they wish to explain. Since the subjects of the human sciences speak to us, their utterances must be interpreted. Thus, the human sciences must be hermeneutical in a way the natural science methodologies cannot be, and so there must be a fundamental disunity between the sciences. Rorty reclaims the unity not through a return to the positivist foundations, of course, but by his own take on the universality of hermeneutics: the Naturwissenschaften are just as hermeneutical as the Geisteswissenschaften, and the disunity claim presupposes that the - 7 -

8 former are still concerned with the knowledge of some external reality. 7 In the post-kuhnian theoretical landscape the claim of scientific realism to a language that is value-free and thus corresponds to empirical reality is replaced by the recognition that the language natural scientists is just as theory-laden, just as constituted within a web of meanings as that of the social scientists. So the fact that the objects of the social sciences are constituted within a web of conceptual interrelations does not set them apart from the objects of the natural sciences. Moreover, the point made by the disunity proponents that the subjects of the human sciences talk back, in a sense, ultimately makes no difference from Rorty s point of view. What the subjects actually say would only be relevant if there was a truth that coincided with what the person says. But since interpretation is not concerned with this, then it ultimately makes no difference whether the human scientist describes her subject matter in her own language or that of the subject. It may make a difference in practice, to be sure, since it might be more pragmatically useful to use the subject s own language to explain what they do; but it does not make a difference to whether or not the human scientist is giving the true interpretation or explanation. And finally there is no sense in appealing to a difference in essence between natural subjects and human subjects: without the language of realist metaphysics, we can no longer appeal different essences as a ground of the distinction. Thus there is no fundamental difference between what the Geisteswissenschaften do as opposed to the Naturwissenschaften if we take the Rortian position that hermeneutics dispenses with the relevance of a truth beyond our language. The previous discussions sought to give a sense of how Rorty s rejection of truth as correspondence to something that transcends our language bears upon his views on morality and politics on one hand, and in the unity of the sciences debate on the other. In each case a critical point is that the ways we understand ourselves, our world and our practices revolve around language: they begin in the linguistically embedded concepts, norms and modes of 7 See his (1980), Reply to Dreyfus and Taylor (The Review of Metaphysics volume 34:1, no. 133) and his Method, Science, and Social Hope, in The Canadian Journal of Philosophy, D 81; 16:

9 discourse, and only develop as we tie together the various things previously said in new and perspicuous ways. 8 He calls this sort of practice a fusing of horizons (Horizontverschmelzung), a term by which he betrays his affinity for Gadamerian language. Indeed the reading that he gives to Gadamer s slogan, Being that can be understood is language, in the article of the same title as well as elsewhere, 9 suffuses the ideas above with hermeneutical glosses. Once we realize that the notions of real essence and of truth-ascorrespondence stand or fall together [ ] Gadamer s slogan gives us a way of sweeping both aside. [ ] It is a suggestion about how to redescribe the process we call increasing our understanding. 10 Again, in this process, the struggle to understand is a struggle to develop more pragmatically useful languages, to redescribe what another person says to me or I to her in a way that allows us to reach agreement, and ultimately to find new and better ways of coping with the world; it is not to understand a thing (Sache) better, understood as something separated from us by an abyss. 11 This way of conceiving the object of our understanding holds onto the metaphysical dross that we should think of Gadamer as throwing out. The Gadamerian conception of the Sache, according to Rorty, is forever up for grabs, forever to be reimagined and redescribed in the course of an endless conversation. 12 If Rorty is right, that the Sache is not to be thought of as something transcendent that has pertinence to our hermeneutical practices, then the process of understanding, of redescribing and Horizontverschmelzung, is not a question of whether the relations expressed in a new vocabulary are really there, as the metaphysician asks; rather, the Gadamerian will as only whether they can be woven together with the relations captured by previous vocabularies in a helpful way Rorty (2004) 24 9 See especially Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979), p Rorty (2004) Ibid Ibid. 13 Ibid

10 II So we have seen that Rorty reads and appropriates the Gadamerian language as basically supporting the pragmatist position on truth and objectivity outlined above. Before we sort out the wheat from the chaff, however, and offer up a critique of Rorty from the Gadamerian perspective, we will briefly examine the development of the history of hermeneutics as Gadamer recounts it in Truth and Method, 14 paying particular attention, naturally, to the first of the title characters. Gadamer reckons Schleiermacher to be the first to really bring hermeneutics out from under the confines of Biblical studies into a broader concern with understanding and interpretation in general. Yet he did this by giving a somewhat radical twist on Biblical hermeneutics. Schleiermacher addresses that problematic by insisting on the centrality of the personal encounter with scripture letting the text address the individual believer as if it was written specifically to him. The goal was to discover the faith experience that produced this text, amounting to a sort of divination process whereby the interpreter makes the text intelligible by a re-creation of the creative act. 15 This characteristically Romantic move involves a bracketing of the truth element in favor of the pure understanding of a singular experience the experience of life thus marking a break from the Hegelian concern with Absolute Reason becoming transparent to itself. However, he maintains Hegelian residues by suggesting that hermeneutics essentially aims to understand a writer better than he understood himself, 16 perhaps by revealing what had been unconscious in the original producer. For Schleiermacher (unlike Hegel), this is ultimately an understanding not of the Absolute Truth or even the subject matter itself (pace the Rationalists and Empiricists) but of 14 Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (henceforth TM), 2 nd rev. ed., trans. Joel Weissheimer and Donald G. Marshall (NY: Continuum, 2004). 15 TM TM 192. Gadamer notes that the idea of understanding better than the author was present in Kant and Fichte as well, but in their writings it carried the sense of having a greater clarity into the content of the author s insights themselves. This ideal, Gadamer notes, has occupied philosophy for ages before Kant, so Schleiermacher can be seen as offering a rather radical sort of take on this idea compared with his predecessors

11 the creative expression; indeed, the claim to understand better is only possible because of the independence of hermeneutics from the knowledge of such things themselves. This has to do with the inherent freedom in a creative expression, indeed a kind of divine productivity, 17 which he saw as rising above the content of the text itself. Schleiermacher s influence on Gadamer included the broadening of hermeneutics beyond Biblical or even textual interpretation to the more general mode of interpreting other people and the world, as well as acknowledging the limitations of rationality in interpretation, and the turn to life. Gadamer s critique of Schleiermacher centers, though, on the problem of historical understanding. He argues that the ideal of con-geniality (recreating the experience of the author, getting into his mind) ignores the differences of interpretive frameworks whenever there is historical distance (which Gadamer will extend to any distance at all: cultural, linguistic, etc.). 18 In questioning the Romantic ideal, however, Gadamer does not reject their basic critique of Hegel; that is, human finitude precludes a return to the notion of the Absolute Truth as the object of shared or superior understanding. However, in a move critical for our purposes, neither will Gadamer with not accept the bracketing or subordination of truth in understanding to the pure creative expression. We must see the hermeneutical life as one that is finite and historically conditioned, and yet in spite of or more precisely, because of this it must nevertheless approaches the subject matter with a presumption that what it says is true, part of what Gadamer calls the foreconception of completeness. The discussion of what this is and how it helps us address Rorty s concerns, however, needs to be preceded by a brief turn to Dilthey, in whom the emphasis on the historical effect takes shape, but in whom Gadamer also sees all the dilemmas of historicism brought out. Dilthey sought the structure of historical understanding in life, in collective lived experience. This involved a transference of Hegel s Geist from the level of a mental, rational construct to the concrete i.e., to the lived. In this way he also goes beyond 17 TM See TM 297-8,

12 Schleiermacher s mind knowing mind, which retains inherent individualism and idealism. Dilthey emphasized the continuity or homogeneity of historian and history in the shared lived experience of history: the history which the historian attempts to understand is one in which he himself participates. Gadamer s main criticisms, though, have to do with Dilthey s insistence on developing a methodology of historical science. Indeed, Gadamer finds in this a lingering remnant of Cartesianism: the methodological enterprise still presupposes that the historicist can stand outside or beyond the subject-matter, from which he forms and applies the methodology hence historicism s dilemma. Understanding, Gadamer maintains, is to be thought of less as a subjective act than as participating in an event of a tradition, a process of transmission in which past and present are constantly mediated. This is what must be validated by hermeneutic theory, which is far too dominated by the idea of a procedure, a method. 19 This statement reveals two more aspects of Gadamer s hermeneutics that will be crucial later on, especially as we address the unity of the sciences issue. First, the deemphasis on methodology aligns him with those who reject the positivist construal of the unity of the sciences, and, more generally, those who take methodology as a means to knowledge of things-in-themselves. The second point, however, is that he is quick to point out that this entails a rejection of a subject-centered hermeneutics which takes insufficient account of the conception of history as a narrative in which we participate as we attempt understand it. When seen in the light of further details of his hermeneutics, this will entail a concern to preserve and refine the truths of these traditions in which we participate. To move on, we have already seen that Gadamer s critique of Schleiermacher involved the neglect of historical distance, and Dilthey s problem involved the neglect of historical effect. The problem, then, is more fundamental: hermeneutics cannot begin in the detached subjectivity; rather, following Heidegger, hermeneutics begins in Dasein s fundamental facticity, which is to say that it cannot begin with any assumptions about the sort 19 TM 290, his emphasis

13 of being that Dasein is conscious, rational, historical, and so forth. For Heidegger the Being that is given to this Dasein is temporality, which for Gadamer will, along with Dasein s finitude, provide the conditions for the possibility of understanding. Gadamer inherits from Heidegger the tripartite scheme of understanding, corresponding to the three modes of Dasein s temporality. 20 The first dimension of the scheme, fore-having (vorhabe), is the frame of reference from which hermeneutics proceeds: I interpret something into an existing structure of prejudices and preconceptions. Second, fore-sight (vorsicht) is the dimension where I apply my understanding in such a way that I recognize the object of understanding as an object of a certain sort: I see it in a certain way. The third dimension of understanding is the fore-conception (vorgrift), where I articulate it in such a way that can be understood or make sense to others. These three dimensions are involved in the hermeneutic circle : in terms of textual interpretation, understanding always begins from somewhere with certain prejudices and expectations as to the meaning of a text as a whole; we project these prejudices onto the text, but when the text does not validate our projections, we find that we have to return and revise our preunderstandings in light of what we find there. So hermeneutics is circular in the sense that it always moves from whole to part and back to whole again, never escaping our prejudices but never wholly bound to them either: our prejudices are able to be corrected in light of what we encounter in the text. For Gadamer, as we noted before, all the world is a text in this way; that is, all experience is hermeneutical. Like Husserl, Heidegger and Gadamer agree that our prejudices color our understandings such that so long as they are operative, we can never get to the essential reality of things. But unlike Husserl, they do not think that the solution is to bracket our prejudices so as make essences available before pure reflective intuition. Rather, all understanding must be structured by prejudices in some way for it to be possible at all; we can never attain a view from nowhere, or pretend to theorize from behind a veil of ignorance to find some neutral, 20 See especially 32 of Heidegger s Being and Time

14 universal common ground for knowledge. Understanding, then, can never be, for Gadamer, a matter of seeing things as they really are. To state the point a bit differently, the facticity of being-in-the-world means that our idea of understanding must recognize the finitude of Dasein. Dasein s finitude precludes the ability to step outside the conditionedness of lived experience to take a universalistic perspective on the world. The universalistic perspective and the grasping of what is real, eternal, or apodictic, the correspondence of our language and thought to what transcends it all of this requires Dasein to overcome its finitude and direct its mind to something beyond it. Yet for an essentially finite being, this is an absurdity. Dasein can no more transcend the limitations of its finitude than it can become something that it is not. Thus are the possibilities for understanding limited by finitude. Understanding can never be completed, as that which we may seek to understand will always lie beyond our finite capabilities, and thus any claim to a correspondence of what we understand to what is real or true or universal can never be validated. So far, then, our discussion of Gadamer s hermeneutics has tended to agree with much of Rorty s claims regarding it. He has agreed that understanding cannot involve escaping from one s horizons of meaning and significance, by seeing the essences of things, getting into another s mind, or discovering truths provided by the exercise of pure rationality. The methodology of Dilthey, moreover, Rorty also finds dubious, 21 for a method presumes to have a truth or essence as its goal. But this cannot be attained unless the historian can somehow detach himself from his own biases to objectively apply the methodology and examine the reality that one finds there. Instead, they both seem to agree that our finitude and the inescapability of the hermeneutical circle mean that hermeneutics cannot be a method to arrive a truth-as-correspondence, to break free, as it were, from the circle of understanding, which leads to the universality of the hermeneutical problem. Rorty concludes from this, 21 Rorty (1980)

15 again, that the best we can do is to find new and useful ways of speaking, attempting to fuse our horizons with those of our partners in discourse if that helps; but given the confines of the hermeneutical circle, it no longer makes any sense to ask if our interpretations are right, our language capture the way things are, if there is a truth beyond the circle of understanding that I or the text bring to the conversation. I suggest, however, that in coming to these conclusions Rorty has misunderstood the nature of the hermeneutical circle, at least as Gadamer sees it. The consequences of finitude and historical effect, and the rejection of truth-ascorrespondence by Gadamer do not entirely dissolve the importance of truth, as we saw in his critique of Schleiermacher s truth-bracketing hermeneutics; and in fact it necessitates that we maintain a central role for it. This idea gets articulated in what we briefly alluded to earlier as the fore-conception of completeness. Contrary to a hermeneutics in which we always approach a text with the suspicion that something in its meaning is hidden from us, and contrary to Schleiermacher s hermeneutics which is no longer about content but about expression, the fore-conception of completeness assumes that what the text says that which confronts us directly is complete, and we initially project meaning with this presumption. That is to say, we project a meaning on the text as a whole based on what we encounter in its parts. Uncovering hidden meanings, trying to recreate the mind of the author these only take place when on the basis of the projections the presumption of completeness proves mistaken i.e., the text is not intelligible. 22 We then return to the parts and see them in a different way, and from there return to the whole the hermeneutical circle, once again. But Gadamer goes on to emphasize that the initial presumption regards the content as complete not merely internally that is, not simply as internally coherent; that is, not only does the reader assume an immanent unity of meaning, but his understanding is likewise guided by the 22 TM 294, my emphasis

16 constant transcendent expectations of meaning that proceed from the relation to the truth of what is being said. 23 Here we have the first substantial indication that Gadamer distances himself from Rorty. In Rorty s perspective, for instance, it would make little sense to make a distinction between the content of what is said as opinion and content that is true, in the sense that the latter transcends opinion. And yet Gadamer maintains, on the contrary: It is only when the attempt to accept what is said as true fails that we try to understand the text, psychologically or historically, as another s opinion. The prejudice of completeness, then, implies not only this formal element that a text should completely express its meaning but also that what it says should be the complete truth. 24 I hope to show that this prejudice of truth is about, in an interesting and relevant way, a reality that transcends our conceptions, language, and modes of justification viz., it is more like those conceptions of truth that Rorty thinks should be rejected than his own (merely) cautionary conception. The difference between Gadamer and Rorty, I suggest, largely comes down to a difference between a conception of truth that we attain versus a conception of truth that affects us. To explain: Rorty thinks that for considerations of truth to be relevant to our theories and practices, it must be something that we would in principle be able to rationally achieve; put differently, to say that a theory or practice should be concerned with truth is to say that it is supposed to enable us to attain positive correspondence of our ideas, representations, beliefs, linguistic terms, or whatever, to this reality. Of course, since Rorty thinks that this correspondence is not possible, nor does that matter, truth is not a relevant notion beyond the weak cautionary gloss he gives to that term. Gadamer, on the other hand, agrees that this positive achievement of correspondence is not possible, but does think it makes a difference. This is because the relevance of truth is not, as Rorty thinks, limited to something with which we can bring ourselves into correspondence. Rather truth is something that affects us; as Edward Tingley says, quoting Gadamer, the miracle of 23 TM TM

17 language [is] the miracle of a presence that asserts its own truth in being understood. We are talking about the great experience in which what is reveals itself. 25 There s a difference in directionality involved in these two conceptions the one Rorty rejects and the one Gadamer endorses. Rorty rejects a conception in which the truth stands passively outside of us, and we have to direct ourselves towards it; Gadamer endorses a conception in which the truth outside of us is active, directing itself towards us; hermeneutics is thus an openness to the ways in which the truth might reveal itself. This, as we will see, is crucial to hermeneutics: without maintaining a robust conception of a transcendent truth, the foreconception of completeness changes its meaning, as does the central requirement of openness, and thus hermeneutics itself. III We will flesh out and defend these claims by first looking at one way in which this conception of truth makes a difference specifically to textual hermeneutics through the phenomenon that Gadamer calls the Classical; 26 this application of the role of truth in hermeneutics should clarify it in such a way that we can see how it makes a difference to the critique of Rorty s position on ethics and politics and to the unity of the sciences. The concept of the classical brings together the critiques of Schleiermacher s neglect of historical effect as well as the critique of historicism s emphasis on methodology in a way that acknowledges Rorty s concerns but also responds to them in this alternative way that we have been exploring. The classical, in Gadamer s sense, does not refer just to a particular period of aesthetic history, nor a particular literary style. They are neither texts that we approach nostalgically in such a way that we try to re-experience the thought and spirit of a by-gone age, endeavoring towards a kind of self-forgetting and unconcern with a truth beyond the experience of con-geniality with the past. This is the Romantic nostalgia that Schleiermacher succumbs to. Nor are they texts that exemplify a literary or artistic style, 25 Gadamer and the Light of the Word, First Things 139 (Jan 2004): See TM for Gadamer s treatment of this subject

18 models of a kind of methodology that we could in principle reproduce. Again, this latter position would be a concern not with the content of what is said through these texts, rather the manner in which the classical artists expressed their values, norms and ideas. Gadamer instead sees the classical as a phenomenon wherein a text incorporates a kind of perennial truth 27 that survives the contingencies of historical distance. As Gadamer explains, it epitomizes a general characteristic of historical being: preservation amid the ruins of time The classical preserves itself precisely because it is significant in itself and interprets itself; i.e., it speaks in such a way that it is not a statement about what is past rather, it says something to the present as if it were said specifically to it. 28 The classical claims an authority to speak to us regardless of whether we want to hear it; i.e., regardless of what use its words might have to our purposes or the prejudices and norms of the audience to which it speaks. In this way it resists reduction to linguistic convention or to the proclamations of historical criticism: the binding power of the validity that is preserved and handed down precedes all historical reflection and continues in it. 29 We have been concerned here to explicate what it would mean for transcendent truth to reveal itself once we ve rid ourselves of the possibility of correspondence. The classical, as something raised above the vicissitudes of changing times and changing tastes shows us something of this: When we call something classical, there is a consciousness of something enduring, of significance that cannot be lost and that is independent of all the circumstances of time a kind of timeless present that is contemporaneous with every other present. 30 Its importance lies both in revealing that there is something transcendent that can bring itself to bear on our understanding by overcoming the limitations of language and historical effect, as well as impressing upon us the importance of a hermeneutics that opens itself up to this 27 TM TM TM TM

19 truth, not in order to passively observe it, seeing it as it is in itself, but rather allowing it to speak and transform our horizons. More generally, what this means is that through the presumption of truth we open ourselves up hermeneutically to the transformative effect that this truth can have on our prejudices, and thus our understanding. To be sure, this prejudice does not entail that we can fully recognize the content of the text as the truth; such a claim would lapse back in a correspondence claim that cannot be substantiated. Nevertheless, neither does this concession entail that the truth is irrelevant to our understandings; rather it is the openness to the truth of what being said that allows that which transcends our capabilities to draw us closer to itself through the conversation with the text in this case, the conversation with the classical. Through the notion of the presumption of truth and the discussion of the classical, we have already seen that Gadamer holds to a notion of truth that is more than just a set of descriptions. In this way, understanding and by extension, the concern to justify our beliefs and values must be open to the effect of something beyond the norms of justification (for assertions and for actions) we find about us. However, in an earlier writing from which the foregoing quote was taken, 31 Rorty maintains that this very concern with something outside of sets of descriptions is self-deceptive. So if I am right that the presumption of truth and the example of the classical reveal that Gadamer is indeed concerned with this something more, then it seems that Rorty s appropriation of Gadamer misses something rather central to his hermeneutics. We will now see how this leads to different attitudes regarding the debates in ethics and politics and those of the social sciences. IV As a preliminary remark, we should remember that one of the lessons taken from Schleiermacher s hermeneutics as well as Dilthey and Heidegger was the broadening of the problem of hermeneutics beyond textual interpretation. Indeed, the whole world is a text 31 Rorty (1979)

20 in Gadamer s thought, but perhaps the most important text is the voice of the other person. With this in mind, recall Rorty s argument that the most we can attain in our ethical or political life is justification, which is a sort of coherence or agreement based on received linguistic meanings, norms, and modes of discourse. It would thus be nonsensical and fruitless to ask whether the ethical or political values and conceptions that I or a person I may disagree with bring to the table are true : the most they could possibly be is justified, but that would depend on one or the other of us in the disagreement convincing the other to see things in a certain way. The truth, here, is just an empty concept devoid of pragmatic utility beyond its cautionary use. Gadamer, as we have seen, thinks, rather, that we do have to approach the text with a presumption that it has something true to say to us. There are two ways in which this will challenge Rorty s position. First, the notion of the Sache will no longer be forever up for grabs, as we quoted Rorty at the end of section I. According to Gadamer, Rorty s sense of nominalism gives us too much control over meanings. We have to allow that there is in the Sache a power to constrain us and to overcome the vicissitudes of changing times and changing tastes, as in the truth that the Classical brings down to us. But this can only be so if there is being or reality to meanings, values, and the other objects of ethical and political discourse. To be sure, Rorty does seem to allow for a sort of constraining power of the external world : although understanding is always of objects under a description, he admits, the causal powers of objects to hurt or help us are unaffected by the way they are described. 32 The causal power of the world can certainly affect our ability to cope through language, and so constrain this language, especially as it has to do with the world in which we move about. But Rorty would not think that this has anything to do with our concepts corresponding to the world or, along the same lines, that we seek to bring our language closer to reality. It seems, for him, more of a linguistic natural selection. Moreover, this would 32 Rorty (2004)

21 not seem to have anything to do with values, norms, meanings or anything contaminated with metaphysical dross : it s not a truth that is affecting our abilities to cope though our language and concepts. But for Gadamer, we must enter the ethical or political dialogue not simply with the intention of finding better ways to cope with the world, but with the expectation that there are normative truths that my prejudices and assumptions have distorted, which the partner in the dialogue brings to me, truths that transcend mere getting by. We see in the classical these normative truths thrusting themselves upon us even as history and culture finds its own coping mechanisms, through the paradigm changes within the sciences, through the different ways in which cultures may even try to subvert or reduce them. And so it is the concern of the hermeneutically engaged consciousness to open ourselves and allow them to speak into our own horizons. Unlike Habermas, however, the task is not to distinguish the ethical in which norms and values are bound up in our horizons and prejudices, from the moral in which rationality seeks to uncover these universals which can form the foundation for a conception of justice. Rorty is right to point to the absurdity and impossibility of this uncovering method. But while Habermas, in his critiques of Gadamer, worries that the latter claim will make the critique of prejudices underlying racism and homophobia, for instance, a matter of domination, the non-racists attempting to impose their ideologies on the racists and homosexuals without any transcendent justification for their critique, Gadamer could retort that through this hermeneutical openness to truth, the truth of value and humanity that the homosexual or person of a different race brings to bear will (hopefully) thwart the racist or homophobic projections I may make out of my prejudices. 33 Thus, the real menace to ethics and politics lies on the extremes: the presumption that truth and the grounds of justification 33 To be sure, this may sound a bit naïve and idealistic. However, I think that Habermas is right to be concerned that the alternative seems to risk domination, and that if we can avoid this risk while having rejected Habermas own solution, then the naïve and idealistic is at least worth pursing. In the end, perhaps it comes across as naïve and idealistic simply because much the history of ethical and political discourse has itself been operating under a false ideal. In the end, though, a Gadamerian could maintain that at the more local level, these sorts of prejudices are affected all the time, and that s where broader change must begin

22 must be rationally accessible by escaping one s prejudices, or that there are no ethical or political truths at all that can speak against our prejudices. If we accept Gadamer s road between these extremes, then truth is not simply that which can be justified in all contexts, for that still places too much of the burden on ourselves to effect that justification by manipulating our language or changing minds; rather, even in that ideal (and rather un-human) world of universal justification, it is still justification on the basis of prejudices, so we would still have to remain open to a transcendent truth that stands beyond them. Basically, Gadamer s position regarding these issues takes the Aristotelian concept of phronesis, a kind of practical wisdom, to be vital. Through phronesis we are constantly mediating between the ethos in which are ethical and political attitudes are embedded, and the practical knowledge of how to act in a particular situation. But in Gadamer s thought, Aristotle must be read alongside Kant, who reminds us that the ethical phenomenon includes obligation that is not reducible to inclination. So phronesis must be open to the demands of the situation, a requirement unfulfilled if all that we have an eye towards is what is useful according to my own purposes. Regarding Rorty s position on the unity of the sciences, much has been said already that would agree with this analysis of truth in Gadamer. 34 The basic line in these critiques is not to contest the assertion that the natural sciences are just as interpretive as the human ones. The issue, that is, is not whether the positivists, though wrong about the objectivity of human sciences, were nevertheless right when it came to the possibility of an objective, non-theoryladen natural science. In fact, such a position is often what Rorty attributes to his critics: he assumes that they advocate the disunity of the sciences because the Geisteswissenschaften 34 See Georgia Warnke (1985), Hermeneutics and the Social Sciences: A Gadamerian Critique of Rorty, (Inquiry, 28, ); Hubert L. Dreyfus (1980), Holism and Hermeneutics (The Review of Metaphysics volume 34:1, no. 133); Charles Taylor (1980), Understanding in Human Science (The Review of Metaphysics volume 34:1, no.133) and Philosophy and Social Science in Philosophy and the Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers, Volume 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press, 1985), ; John D. Caputo (1983), The Thought of Being and the Conversation of Mankind: The Case of Heidegger and Rorty (Review of Metaphysics 36:

Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Gadamer and Charles Taylor, Fred Dallmayr, Fall April Gadamer s Hermeneutical Ethics: An Ethics of Life

Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Gadamer and Charles Taylor, Fred Dallmayr, Fall April Gadamer s Hermeneutical Ethics: An Ethics of Life Brad Thames Seminar Paper for Gadamer and Charles Taylor, Fred Dallmayr, Fall 2004. 27 April 2005 Gadamer s Hermeneutical Ethics: An Ethics of Life 1 One of the central threads that runs through Gadamer

More information

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4)

Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics. Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth. I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4) Reading/Study Guide: Rorty and his Critics Richard Rorty s Universality and Truth I. The Political Context: Truth and Democratic Politics (1-4) A. What does Rorty mean by democratic politics? (1) B. How

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair

FIRST STUDY. The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair FIRST STUDY The Existential Dialectical Basic Assumption of Kierkegaard s Analysis of Despair I 1. In recent decades, our understanding of the philosophy of philosophers such as Kant or Hegel has been

More information

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS

PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS PART FOUR: CATHOLIC HERMENEUTICS 367 368 INTRODUCTION TO PART FOUR The term Catholic hermeneutics refers to the understanding of Christianity within Roman Catholicism. It differs from the theory and practice

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld

UNITY OF KNOWLEDGE (IN TRANSDISCIPLINARY RESEARCH FOR SUSTAINABILITY) Vol. I - Philosophical Holism M.Esfeld PHILOSOPHICAL HOLISM M. Esfeld Department of Philosophy, University of Konstanz, Germany Keywords: atomism, confirmation, holism, inferential role semantics, meaning, monism, ontological dependence, rule-following,

More information

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5 Robert Stern Understanding Moral Obligation. Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012. 277 pages $90.00 (cloth ISBN 978 1 107 01207 3) In his thoroughly researched and tightly

More information

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism?

Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Has Nagel uncovered a form of idealism? Author: Terence Rajivan Edward, University of Manchester. Abstract. In the sixth chapter of The View from Nowhere, Thomas Nagel attempts to identify a form of idealism.

More information

Ayer and Quine on the a priori

Ayer and Quine on the a priori Ayer and Quine on the a priori November 23, 2004 1 The problem of a priori knowledge Ayer s book is a defense of a thoroughgoing empiricism, not only about what is required for a belief to be justified

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski

Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski J Agric Environ Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10806-016-9627-6 REVIEW PAPER Response to The Problem of the Question About Animal Ethics by Michal Piekarski Mark Coeckelbergh 1 David J. Gunkel 2 Accepted: 4 July

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1 Philosophy Courses-1 PHL 100/Introduction to Philosophy A course that examines the fundamentals of philosophical argument, analysis and reasoning, as applied to a series of issues in logic, epistemology,

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya

Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya Towards Richard Rorty s Critique on Transcendental Grounding of Human Rights by Dr. P.S. Sreevidya Abstract This article considers how the human rights theory established by US pragmatist Richard Rorty,

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is

- We might, now, wonder whether the resulting concept of justification is sufficiently strong. According to BonJour, apparent rational insight is BonJour I PHIL410 BonJour s Moderate Rationalism - BonJour develops and defends a moderate form of Rationalism. - Rationalism, generally (as used here), is the view according to which the primary tool

More information

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

xiv Truth Without Objectivity Introduction There is a certain approach to theorizing about language that is called truthconditional semantics. The underlying idea of truth-conditional semantics is often summarized as the idea that

More information

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary

Moral Objectivism. RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary Moral Objectivism RUSSELL CORNETT University of Calgary The possibility, let alone the actuality, of an objective morality has intrigued philosophers for well over two millennia. Though much discussed,

More information

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Descartes - ostensive task: to secure by ungainsayable rational means the orthodox doctrines of faith regarding the existence of God

More information

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary

Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary Critical Realism & Philosophy Webinar Ruth Groff August 5, 2015 Intro. The need for a philosophical vocabulary You don t have to become a philosopher, but just as philosophers should know their way around

More information

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University

On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University On Searle on Human Rights, Again! J. Angelo Corlett, San Diego State University With regard to my article Searle on Human Rights (Corlett 2016), I have been accused of misunderstanding John Searle s conception

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE

THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Diametros nr 29 (wrzesień 2011): 80-92 THE TWO-DIMENSIONAL ARGUMENT AGAINST MATERIALISM AND ITS SEMANTIC PREMISE Karol Polcyn 1. PRELIMINARIES Chalmers articulates his argument in terms of two-dimensional

More information

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613

Naturalized Epistemology. 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? Quine PY4613 Naturalized Epistemology Quine PY4613 1. What is naturalized Epistemology? a. How is it motivated? b. What are its doctrines? c. Naturalized Epistemology in the context of Quine s philosophy 2. Naturalized

More information

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World

Think by Simon Blackburn. Chapter 7c The World Think by Simon Blackburn Chapter 7c The World Idealism Despite the power of Berkeley s critique, his resulting metaphysical view is highly problematic. Essentially, Berkeley concludes that there is no

More information

Heidegger Introduction

Heidegger Introduction Heidegger Introduction G. J. Mattey Spring, 2011 / Philosophy 151 Being and Time Being Published in 1927, under pressure Dedicated to Edmund Husserl Initially rejected as inadequate Now considered a seminal

More information

Philosophy Courses-1

Philosophy Courses-1 Philosophy Courses-1 PHL 100/Introduction to Philosophy A course that examines the fundamentals of philosophical argument, analysis and reasoning, as applied to a series of issues in logic, epistemology,

More information

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture

Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Introductory Kant Seminar Lecture Intentionality It is not unusual to begin a discussion of Kant with a brief review of some history of philosophy. What is perhaps less usual is to start with a review

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works

UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works UC Berkeley UC Berkeley Previously Published Works Title Disaggregating Structures as an Agenda for Critical Realism: A Reply to McAnulla Permalink https://escholarship.org/uc/item/4k27s891 Journal British

More information

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology

Philosophy of Science. Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophy of Science Ross Arnold, Summer 2014 Lakeside institute of Theology Philosophical Theology 1 (TH5) Aug. 15 Intro to Philosophical Theology; Logic Aug. 22 Truth & Epistemology Aug. 29 Metaphysics

More information

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori

Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori Ayer s linguistic theory of the a priori phil 43904 Jeff Speaks December 4, 2007 1 The problem of a priori knowledge....................... 1 2 Necessity and the a priori............................ 2

More information

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor,

Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn. Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Can Rationality Be Naturalistically Explained? Jeffrey Dunn Abstract: Dan Chiappe and John Vervaeke (1997) conclude their article, Fodor, Cherniak and the Naturalization of Rationality, with an argument

More information

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief

Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief Paul Livingston Jeffrey Barrett 22 August 2003 plivings@uci.edu jabarret@uci.edu Pure Pragmatics and the Transcendence of Belief Accuracy in the philosophical theory of rationality demands that we recognize

More information

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON Andrews University Seminary Studies, Vol. 47, No. 2, 217-240. Copyright 2009 Andrews University Press. INVESTIGATING THE PRESUPPOSITIONAL REALM OF BIBLICAL-THEOLOGICAL METHODOLOGY, PART II: CANALE ON REASON

More information

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement

Faults and Mathematical Disagreement 45 Faults and Mathematical Disagreement María Ponte ILCLI. University of the Basque Country mariaponteazca@gmail.com Abstract: My aim in this paper is to analyse the notion of mathematical disagreements

More information

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy

Qué es la filosofía? What is philosophy? Philosophy Philosophy PHILOSOPHY AS A WAY OF THINKING WHAT IS IT? WHO HAS IT? WHAT IS THE DIFFERENCE BETWEEN A WAY OF THINKING AND A DISCIPLINE? It is the propensity to seek out answers to the questions that we ask

More information

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to

Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method. Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to Haruyama 1 Justin Haruyama Bryan Smith HON 213 17 April 2008 Spinoza and the Axiomatic Method Ever since Euclid first laid out his geometry in the Elements, his axiomatic approach to geometry has been

More information

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A

MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A I Holistic Pragmatism and the Philosophy of Culture MY PURPOSE IN THIS BOOK IS TO PRESENT A philosophical discussion of the main elements of civilization or culture such as science, law, religion, politics,

More information

Habermas and Critical Thinking

Habermas and Critical Thinking 168 Ben Endres Columbia University In this paper, I propose to examine some of the implications of Jürgen Habermas s discourse ethics for critical thinking. Since the argument that Habermas presents is

More information

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack

Process Thought and Bridge Building: A Response to Stephen K. White. Kevin Schilbrack Archived version from NCDOCKS Institutional Repository http://libres.uncg.edu/ir/asu/ Schilbrack, Kevin.2011 Process Thought and Bridge-Building: A Response to Stephen K. White, Process Studies 40:2 (Fall-Winter

More information

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel

4/30/2010 cforum :: Moderator Control Panel FAQ Search Memberlist Usergroups Profile You have no new messages Log out [ perrysa ] cforum Forum Index -> The Religion & Culture Web Forum Split Topic Control Panel Using the form below you can split

More information

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis

ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis ABSTRACT of the Habilitation Thesis The focus on the problem of knowledge was in the very core of my researches even before my Ph.D thesis, therefore the investigation of Kant s philosophy in the process

More information

Naturalism and is Opponents

Naturalism and is Opponents Undergraduate Review Volume 6 Article 30 2010 Naturalism and is Opponents Joseph Spencer Follow this and additional works at: http://vc.bridgew.edu/undergrad_rev Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended

More information

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006

In Defense of Radical Empiricism. Joseph Benjamin Riegel. Chapel Hill 2006 In Defense of Radical Empiricism Joseph Benjamin Riegel A thesis submitted to the faculty of the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of

More information

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter

DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE. Graduate course and seminars for Fall Quarter DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, RIVERSIDE Graduate course and seminars for 2012-13 Fall Quarter PHIL 275, Andrews Reath First Year Proseminar in Value Theory [Tuesday, 3-6 PM] The seminar

More information

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Introduction I would like to begin by thanking Leslie MacAvoy for her attempt to revitalize the

More information

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill

Class #3 - Meinong and Mill Philosophy 308: The Language Revolution Fall 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Meinong and Mill 1. Meinongian Subsistence The work of the Moderns on language shows us a problem arising in

More information

1. FROM ORIENTALISM TO AQUINAS?: APPROACHING ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY FROM WITHIN THE WESTERN THOUGHT SPACE

1. FROM ORIENTALISM TO AQUINAS?: APPROACHING ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY FROM WITHIN THE WESTERN THOUGHT SPACE Comparative Philosophy Volume 3, No. 2 (2012): 41-46 Open Access / ISSN 2151-6014 www.comparativephilosophy.org CONSTRUCTIVE ENGAGEMENT DIALOGUE (2.5) THOUGHT-SPACES, SPIRITUAL PRACTICES AND THE TRANSFORMATIONS

More information

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge:

The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge: The Unbearable Lightness of Theory of Knowledge: Desert Mountain High School s Summer Reading in five easy steps! STEP ONE: Read these five pages important background about basic TOK concepts: Knowing

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable

Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable Wittgenstein on The Realm of Ineffable by Manoranjan Mallick and Vikram S. Sirola Abstract The paper attempts to delve into the distinction Wittgenstein makes between factual discourse and moral thoughts.

More information

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge

Holtzman Spring Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge Holtzman Spring 2000 Philosophy and the Integration of Knowledge What is synthetic or integrative thinking? Of course, to integrate is to bring together to unify, to tie together or connect, to make a

More information

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays

Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays Bernays Project: Text No. 26 Remarks on the philosophy of mathematics (1969) Paul Bernays (Bemerkungen zur Philosophie der Mathematik) Translation by: Dirk Schlimm Comments: With corrections by Charles

More information

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017

Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 Response to Gregory Floyd s Where Does Hermeneutics Lead? Brad Elliott Stone, Loyola Marymount University ACPA 2017 In his paper, Floyd offers a comparative presentation of hermeneutics as found in Heidegger

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

At the Frontiers of Reality

At the Frontiers of Reality At the Frontiers of Reality by Christophe Al-Saleh Do the objects that surround us continue to exist when our backs are turned? This is what we spontaneously believe. But what is the origin of this belief

More information

Follow this and additional works at: Part of the Philosophy Commons

Follow this and additional works at:   Part of the Philosophy Commons University of Notre Dame Australia ResearchOnline@ND Philosophy Conference Papers School of Philosophy 2005 Martin Heidegger s Path to an Aesthetic ετηος Angus Brook University of Notre Dame Australia,

More information

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,

In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Book Reviews 1 In Defense of Pure Reason: A Rationalist Account of A Priori Justification, by Laurence BonJour. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998. Pp. xiv + 232. H/b 37.50, $54.95, P/b 13.95,

More information

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn

Mohammad Reza Vaez Shahrestani. University of Bonn Philosophy Study, November 2017, Vol. 7, No. 11, 595-600 doi: 10.17265/2159-5313/2017.11.002 D DAVID PUBLISHING Defending Davidson s Anti-skepticism Argument: A Reply to Otavio Bueno Mohammad Reza Vaez

More information

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the

1/8. The Schematism. schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the 1/8 The Schematism I am going to distinguish between three types of schematism: the schema of empirical concepts, the schema of sensible concepts and the schema of pure concepts. Kant opens the discussion

More information

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica

Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica 1 Denis Seron. Review of: K. Mulligan, Wittgenstein et la philosophie austro-allemande (Paris: Vrin, 2012). Dialectica, Volume 70, Issue 1 (March 2016): 125 128. Wittgenstein is usually regarded at once

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference?

Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Res Cogitans Volume 3 Issue 1 Article 3 6-7-2012 Epistemology for Naturalists and Non-Naturalists: What s the Difference? Jason Poettcker University of Victoria Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

The Mormon Review. Books and culture from an LDS perspective. Recovering Truth: A Review of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method

The Mormon Review. Books and culture from an LDS perspective. Recovering Truth: A Review of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method Books and culture from an LDS perspective Recovering Truth: A Review of Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2 nd, revised ed, translation revised by Joel Weinsheimer

More information

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza

SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza SPINOZA S VERSION OF THE PSR: A Critique of Michael Della Rocca s Interpretation of Spinoza by Erich Schaeffer A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for

More information

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory

Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory Journal of Educational Measurement Spring 2013, Vol. 50, No. 1, pp. 110 114 Truth and Evidence in Validity Theory Denny Borsboom University of Amsterdam Keith A. Markus John Jay College of Criminal Justice

More information

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo

A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo A Brief History of Thinking about Thinking Thomas Lombardo "Education is nothing more nor less than learning to think." Peter Facione In this article I review the historical evolution of principles and

More information

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 1: Overview Welcome! Are you in the right place? PHIL 125 (Metaphysics) Overview of Today s Class 1. Us: Branden (Professor), Vanessa & Josh

More information

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following

Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Abstract The problem of rule-following Rule-Following and the Ontology of the Mind Michael Esfeld (published in Uwe Meixner and Peter Simons (eds.): Metaphysics in the Post-Metaphysical Age. Papers of the 22nd International Wittgenstein Symposium.

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between

The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian. Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between Lee Anne Detzel PHI 8338 Revised: November 1, 2004 The Middle Path: A Case for the Philosophical Theologian Leo Strauss roots the vitality of Western civilization in the ongoing conflict between philosophy

More information

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises

Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises Can A Priori Justified Belief Be Extended Through Deduction? Introduction It is often assumed that if one deduces some proposition p from some premises which one knows a priori, in a series of individually

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics

Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics Perspectival Methods in Metaphysics Mark Ressler February 24, 2012 Abstract There seems to be a difficulty in the practice of metaphysics, in that any methodology used in metaphysical study relies on certain

More information

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy

Canadian Society for Continental Philosophy Provided by the author(s) and NUI Galway in accordance with publisher policies. Please cite the published version when available. Title Steven Crowell - Normativity and Phenomenology in Husserl and Heidegger

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics

A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics A Logical Approach to Metametaphysics Daniel Durante Departamento de Filosofia UFRN durante10@gmail.com 3º Filomena - 2017 What we take as true commits us. Quine took advantage of this fact to introduce

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI?

WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Diametros nr 28 (czerwiec 2011): 1-7 WHAT DOES KRIPKE MEAN BY A PRIORI? Pierre Baumann In Naming and Necessity (1980), Kripke stressed the importance of distinguishing three different pairs of notions:

More information

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality

Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality Unit 3: Philosophy as Theoretical Rationality INTRODUCTORY TEXT. Perhaps the most unsettling thought many of us have, often quite early on in childhood, is that the whole world might be a dream; that the

More information

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics

Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics Abstract: Divisibility, Logic, Radical Empiricism, and Metaphysics We will explore the problem of the manner in which the world may be divided into parts, and how this affects the application of logic.

More information

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy

24.01 Classics of Western Philosophy 1 Plan: Kant Lecture #2: How are pure mathematics and pure natural science possible? 1. Review: Problem of Metaphysics 2. Kantian Commitments 3. Pure Mathematics 4. Transcendental Idealism 5. Pure Natural

More information

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University,

Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, The Negative Role of Empirical Stimulus in Theory Change: W. V. Quine and P. Feyerabend Jeu-Jenq Yuann Professor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy, National Taiwan University, 1 To all Participants

More information

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 2: S.A. Kripke, On Rules and Private Language 21 December 2011 The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages,

More information

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics

The Philosophy of Physics. Physics versus Metaphysics The Philosophy of Physics Lecture One Physics versus Metaphysics Rob Trueman rob.trueman@york.ac.uk University of York Preliminaries Physics versus Metaphysics Preliminaries What is Meta -physics? Metaphysics

More information

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Arthur Kok, Tilburg The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Kant conceives of experience as the synthesis of understanding and intuition. Hegel argues that because Kant is

More information

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules

Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism A Model Of For System Of Rules Positivism is a model of and for a system of rules, and its central notion of a single fundamental test for law forces us to miss the important standards that

More information

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp.

* Dalhousie Law School, LL.B. anticipated Interpretation and Legal Theory. Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. 330 Interpretation and Legal Theory Andrei Marmor Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992, 193 pp. Reviewed by Lawrence E. Thacker* Interpretation may be defined roughly as the process of determining the meaning

More information

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life

Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life Chapter 8 Cosmopolitan Theory and the Daily Pluralism of Life Tariq Ramadan D rawing on my own experience, I will try to connect the world of philosophy and academia with the world in which people live

More information

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science

Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Review of Constructive Empiricism: Epistemology and the Philosophy of Science Constructive Empiricism (CE) quickly became famous for its immunity from the most devastating criticisms that brought down

More information

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition:

It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: The Preface(s) to the Critique of Pure Reason It doesn t take long in reading the Critique before we are faced with interpretive challenges. Consider the very first sentence in the A edition: Human reason

More information

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The Physical World Author(s): Barry Stroud Source: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, Vol. 87 (1986-1987), pp. 263-277 Published by: Blackwell Publishing on behalf of The Aristotelian

More information