Causal Counterfactuals and Impossible Worlds

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Causal Counterfactuals and Impossible Worlds"

Transcription

1 Causal Counterfactuals and Impossible Worlds Daniel Nolan There seem to be tight connections between claims about what caused what, and many claims about what would have happened if things had been otherwise. A special, but important, case of these are the connections between causal structure and what would have been different had things been different. A lot of careful and ingenious work has gone into trying to articulate the connections between the two, though it is probably safe to say that no completely satisfactory account has yet emerged: or at the very least, those who are completely satisfied with an account of the connection between causation and counterfactuals are few, and disagree with each other about which is the completely satisfactory account. This paper is not directly in the service of either of the ambitious analytic projects of analysing causation in terms of the holding of certain counterfactuals, nor of analysing counterfactuals in terms of causal matters. It focuses instead on one of the traditional puzzles that connect the two that arise almost whatever one takes the connection between counterfactuals and causation to be. The puzzle has no neat label that I am aware of, but it arises in its clearest form when we consider counterfactuals involving antecedent states that involve a difference from the actual course of events at a particular time, and a consequent, at least in part involving a state somewhat later than the time of the antecedent difference. In the possible worlds framework, the puzzle is often put in terms of what other differences there in the relevant possible worlds where the antecedent is true. Do those worlds match ours with respect to nearly all their pasts until the time relevant to the antecedent? Do they require small miracles relative to the laws of the actual world? Is their causal structure the same except for an intervention on a state associated with the antecedent?... and so on. Let me label this problem the deviation problem to suggest that it concerns what deviations from actuality would be required for the antecedent to be true, in the class of counterfactuals of interest. In this paper I will propose a novel solution to the deviation problem. This solution will have several signal advantages over a number of the better-known proposed solutions to this problem, though it also incurs some distinctive costs. I am not sure, then, whether something like it will turn out to be the best solution, though I am sure it deserves a run for its money alongside its better-

2 2 known cousins. I will do so by presenting the puzzle and solution in a closest-worlds framework of the Stalnaker-Lewis variety: those familiar with alternative systems will likely be able to see easily enough how to fit the kind of positive proposal I offer into those approaches. After some remarks about the problem my solution is intended to solve, and the kinds of resources I will deploy to construct my version of the solution, I will argue for a number of desiderata for a solution that traditional approaches compromise, before presenting my solution and displaying that it can satisfy those desiderata. Finally, I will discuss some of the vices of the particular solution I offer, and while I do not intend to suggest this solution is without costs, I will have some things to say about why those vices may not be as great drawbacks as they might initially appear. 1. The Target The problem I wish to address in this paper is more specific than the general problem of the truthconditions of counterfactuals. It the narrower problem of offering a story about the truth-conditions of what I am calling causal counterfactuals. So it would be good to begin by being a bit more specific about which counterfactuals I have in mind. The counterfactuals I will pay attention to are those whose antecedents concern a specific one-off event or state, and their consequents deal with what happens after that event or state (or as a consequence of a failure of the antecedent event to influence the consequent). Furthermore, they are the non-backtracking counterfactuals of this sort. A backtracker, intuitively, is a counterfactual that invites us to consider what would have had to be different in the causal ancestry of an event if it were to have come about. How exactly to demarcate which counterfactuals are backtrackers is controversial, but see Lewis 1979 pp for the locus classicus of a characterisation of backtracking conditionals. The causal counterfactuals that are my focus here all come with an antecedent time. 1 Some counterfactual conditionals have antecedents that are about a relatively particular event: if I had set the fire alarm off at this morning, the fire service would have been here by In such cases, we can talk about a particular time associated with the antecedent: roughly, the time at which the situation described by the antecedent would have obtained. In the example, that time would be 1 Lewis 1979 introduces the idea of an antecedent time T A, though he characterizes it as the time the antecedent is about, which is not quite how I will characterize the notion I wish to use.

3 3 some period around 11am. Many other antecedents suggest a time in a much less explicit way. If I had skipped breakfast, I would have had more to eat at lunch suggests a time around my normal breakfast time, or perhaps my actual breakfast time. Not every counterfactual is associated in this way with a time, and it would be natural to extend the account given to cases where there are a number of salient times associated with an antecedent of a causal counterfactual, but I will restrict my discussion for tractability. For the purposes I want to use the notion, the antecedent time associated with a counterfactual will not always be the time the event associated with the antecedent would take place. It will often need to extend some relatively short time before that event. The motivating idea is that the antecedent time is the time at which a world where the antecedent occurs would have to rapidly become quite different from the actual world, so will typically involve difference from the actual world some time immediately before as the run up. (Were I to have turned off on the previous exit ramp, it would not be by a last minute swerve or by teleportation, but rather may well have been by getting into the correct lane, signalling a turn, etc.) So it seems better to say the antecedent time can include some period before the time of the event explicitly invoked by the antecedent. A tricky and unsolved problem is exactly how much of the run-up to the relevant event is best to include in the antecedent time. The puzzle about setting an antecedent time is unfinished business, but the details should not matter for current purposes. 2 The target problem, then, is the deviation problem for causal counterfactuals. What would be different were the antecedent of a causal counterfactual true? Or, to put it in the world terminology introduced below, what are the most relevantly similar worlds where the antecedent of such a counterfactual is true? The proposal to be offered will be straightforwardly generalisable in a number of ways, including to cases where antecedents have a number of natural antecedent times associated with them, to some counterfactuals with general antecedents, and even to counterfactuals where the states associated with the antecedent and consequent are non-causally related. But the interested reader can chart for herself how the proposal in this paper can be generalized, as even the relatively narrow range of counterfactuals I have picked out will give us quite enough fish to fry. 2 A general account will also need to say when an antecedent time ends, and may want to derive the fact that we treat the past differently from the future in causal counterfactual contexts from some more basic principle.

4 2. Resources 4 The most salient commitment of the approach to be used is to an apparatus of worlds, possible and impossible. Relying on accounts of counterfactual conditionals in terms of possible worlds has, by now, a long history, with the important papers of Stalnaker 1968, Stalnaker and Thomason 1970, and Lewis s influential 1973 book helping to make this approach to counterfactuals close to orthodox. I will adopt some of the details of Lewis s specific proposal. For the counterfactual A[]- >B to be true at a possible world w, B must be true at all the nearest worlds to w where A is true (and A[]->B is false otherwise). Lewis explains nearness in terms of similarity, and Lewis holds that which aspects of similarity are relevant is set by the context in which the sentence expressing A[]->B is produced. (I will have more to say about context, below.) In Lewis s framework a lot of the work in determining the truth-value of a counterfactual is done by the similarity measure on worlds. The dimensions of relevant similarity are not a matter of allthings-considered similarity (whatever that would be), but are rather a matter of similarity in relevant respects. Which are the relevant respects, and how they are weighted against each other, is then a central question for this account (and, given that the account says that relevant similarity is determined by context, a question that must be re-asked for each context of utterance). Lewis 1979 is his account of what he takes the relevant dimensions of similarity to be for causal counterfactuals, and while I will not be endorsing that account, it is an example of the kind of account that is needed. This paper will follow Lewis in appealing to comparisons of relevant similarity as part of the machinery for delivering truth-conditions of counterfactuals. Both Lewis s and Stalnaker s systems were constructed so that when the antecedent of a counterfactual was impossible, the counterfactual was automatically true. However, it does seem very natural to not treat counterfactuals with impossible antecedents all in the same way: these socalled counterpossible counterfactual conditionals seem to be usefully employed in logic, mathematics, metaphysics, and in many other areas (Nolan 1997). For convenience, I will refer to these conditionals simply as counterpossibles, though that label often has a wider application to all sorts of conditionals with impossible antecedents (including indicative conditionals, for example). The easiest way to incorporate counterpossibles into a worlds framework is to include impossible worlds as well as possible worlds in the account of truth-conditions of counterfactuals. Consider the conditional If 27x4 were 131, then 131 would be composite. Plausibly, of the impossibilities

5 5 where 27x4=131, the most relevantly similar to actuality are those where being the product of two whole numbers other than 1 or 0 is sufficient for being composite, and will treat that consequent as true. On the other hand, when evaluating If 27x4 were equal to 131, then 27x4 would be equal to 1310, then the same, or a very similar, 27x4=131 worlds seem most relevantly similar: and in none of those will 27x4=1310. That would be a gratuitous departure from actual mathematical truth, so the second counterpossible mentioned is false. A full account requires a story about what makes for relevant similarity between a possible and impossible world, of course. The particular example above may not strike everyone as convincing. But what is important is to notice that treating some impossible worlds as more relevantly similar to actuality than others is a natural way to extend the basic Lewis/Stalnaker semantics for counterfactuals. If we do so, we face a number of choices about how to understand these impossible worlds. One straightforward way to do so is to model them as sets of propositions: but to not insist that these sets are closed under logical consequence. Modelling worlds as arbitrary sets of propositions will give us possible worlds as well as impossible ones, but it should not matter exactly where we draw the possible/impossible line, except that I will assume that sets of propositions which are jointly inconsistent are associated with impossibilities. One distinction is particularly important to keep in mind when employing impossible worlds: the distinction between what is true according to an impossible world and what is true about an impossible world. (Something like this distinction is sometimes characterized as the distinction between what is true in a world versus what is true of a world, but that terminology can be more confusing.) An impossible world may not have true according to it that what happens is impossible, for example: it might represent that everything that happens in it is possible. It may not have true according to it that a contradiction is true, even if the proposition that roses are red, and also the proposition that roses are not red, are both true according to it. Suppose we model impossible worlds with sets of propositions, as above. One set can contain the proposition that there is a round square cupola, while also containing the proposition that everything which exists is possible. One set can contain the following three propositions: that roses are red, that roses are not red, and that no contradictions are true. Even though the first set contains a proposition that there is a round square cupola, and so it is true about that set that it represents that there is an impossible object, it is not true according to the set. The second set contains a contradiction, so it is true about

6 6 the set that it is contradictory, but the proposition that a contradiction obtains is not true according to the set, understood as an impossible world (or a fragment of one). Alternative theories of impossible worlds will offer different ways of accounting for the according to/about distinction, but the illustration should suffice to indicate the distinction I have in mind. As well as worlds, possible and impossible, ordered by similarity in relevant respects, the account of causal counterfactuals I will develop shares with many such accounts a commitment to laws of nature rich enough to impose constraints on the evolution of the world in the respects we care about. I will try to stay relatively neutral on how to understand these laws of nature: in particular, as mentioned above, I will not take a stand here on whether some kind of Humean regularity account of laws of nature is sufficient, or whether something more metaphysically heavy-duty is required. I will presuppose for the rest of the paper that laws of nature are contingent, in the sense that they can vary from possible world to possible world. I do this in a concessive spirit, however: appeals to impossible worlds to evaluate causal counterfactuals are much more appealing if any rival laws of nature are impossible, and hold in no possible worlds at all. A resource that will be lurking in the background is the view that counterfactuals exhibit a certain amount of context sensitivity, here implemented by allowing that which standard of relevant similarity can vary from one context of utterance to another. This context variability of counterfactuals also makes a difference to how I am conceiving of this project. It is not the task of providing the truth-conditions of all counterfactuals whatsoever, nor of isolating some semantic ambiguity in conditional locutions so that one disambiguation is the causal one. It is to explain the truth-conditions of some uses of counterfactuals: perhaps many typical counterfactual utterances. I take it this context-sensitive approach to counterfactuals is in the spirit of Lewis s (see Lewis 1979 pp 33-35), but not in the spirit of everyone who offers closest-world analyses of counterfactual conditionals: Bennett 2003 does not allow for contextual variability, for example. 3. Desiderata for a Solution Given a closest-world approach to counterfactual conditionals, a solution to the deviation problem will be the specification of some conditions on relevant similarity. This specification will ensure the most relevantly similar worlds when evaluating a causal counterfactual are ones that are not gratuitously different from ours, and line up with correct counterfactual judgements. That is, when

7 7 the causal counterfactual A []-> B is true, the most relevantly similar worlds according to which A is true are ones that have B true according to them as well; and when A[]->B is false, this condition will not obtain. There are three plausible desiderata for this solution that are each supported by plausible argument. They appear to be jointly inconsistent if we want to get the intuitive truth-values for ordinary causal counterfactuals, and so solutions to the deviation problem in the literature give up on one or more of them. In this section I will outline and defend each of these desiderata, before explaining in the next section how we can maintain all three in a solution to the deviation problem. 3.1 The Same Laws of Nature, and No Counterfactual Miracles When considering a counterfactual situation, we initially assume the same fundamental principles of nature are at work. There are at least two reasons to think that we do this: one is that we freely employ stable generalisations about what leads to what when reasoning about whether things being a certain way at the antecedent time leads to the consequent obtaining. (Hmm, the weight would have been here, so the scales would have moved to here, so that would have tripped the lever.) The second reason is that, for the kind of antecedents found in causal counterfactuals, if it had been that A then the laws of nature would have been different to the actual laws of nature rarely sounds like an appealing counterfactual. That suggests that for most of these antecedents, the relevantly similar worlds where they are true are not one where the laws of nature differ from the actual ones. For that matter, Even if it had been that A, the laws of nature would have been the same also normally sounds fine, if a little odd to utter we tend to take for granted that various differences would not have resulted in different laws of nature. Perhaps despite these observations, the laws of nature at such counterfactual worlds need not be exactly the same. Even if they are not exactly the same, presumably they should not be too arbitrarily different that would violate the motivating idea of similarity in relevant respects, at least insofar as we are concerned with laws that affect the influence (or not) of the antecedent event on the state associated with the consequent. Despite this initial appeal, a number of authors have endorsed the option that the nearby worlds where the antecedent obtains vary with respect to the laws. Terminology for these deviations from actual laws of nature introduced by Lewis labels them

8 8 as miracles. 3 Let me now say in some more detail why we should not be happy with a theory that invokes miracles for standard causal counterfactuals. Had things been different in various ordinary ways, that would not have taken a miracle, or so we think. My having lunch at a different cafe, or Everest being found twenty metres closer to K2 than it in fact is, or there being half a tank of petrol in a car instead of a full tank, would not require violations of the actual laws of nature. Or so we ordinarily think. Of course, we could be radically wrong about the actual laws of nature: perhaps everything that happens, happens as a matter of nomic necessity, for example. And I do not mean to say that no counterfactual whose antecedent is about specific causal processes could have a consequent saying there were miracles and still be true: if I were to cause a miracle worker to perform miracles, there would be a miracle. In Are We Free to Break the Laws? (Lewis 1981) Lewis defends the view that some possible agents in deterministic worlds are free to perform acts such that, if they perform them, a miracle would occur. And in Lewis 1979, he defends the view that in deterministic worlds, often the nearest world in which standard antecedents for causal counterfactuals are true are ones with miracles: small miracles, that do not make for too much distance between worlds. Lunching at a different cafe, Everest being a little closer to K2, cars having different levels of petrol in their tank, and so on are all compatible with the actual laws of nature. We are inclined to think that were any of these things the case, we would not need to have different laws of nature, but just differences in ordinary matters of fact. Nobody trying to change the level of petrol in a car ever tries to do this by changing the laws themselves. Very few people who regret they did something that was under their control blame the laws of nature rather than their particular actions. I do not think those led to suppose that leaving a chip uneaten, or putting on a different shirt in the morning, would have taken a miracle, do so because that strikes them as the pre-theoretically compelling view: rather, they seem pushed there by the apparent lack of a feasible theoretical alternative that has other features they want. If quotidian things could be otherwise without requiring miracles, that would seem preferable. For 3 Well, strictly speaking, the definition should make no mention of the actual world, an event in w 1 counts as a miracle according to a possible world w 2 provided the event is against the laws of w 2, and I intend this general definition to be the one in force: but the more general definition is unnecessary to get the idea.

9 9 one thing, miracles cannot happen. (That is, events that in fact violate our laws are nomically impossible though they are possible in a more generous sense, and are nomically possible in the worlds where they occur.) But wearing a different shirt or not eating a chip are things that can happen, we ordinarily think. On the face of it, were they to happen, nothing impossible would need happen. The case for requiring miracles in the nearby worlds relevant for ordinary causal counterfactuals often requires some other assumptions: that those worlds share a lot of other truths with ours, and that the laws tightly constrain how things can be at the antecedent time given those other truths, or at least that we should have an account flexible enough that it delivers similar results even when the laws restrict the possible outcomes in this way. Let us, then, turn to the other two desirable features the nearby (i.e. relevantly similar) worlds should have when evaluating causal counterfactuals. 3.2 Common Past The first two constraints suggest a picture: that we consider the closest worlds where what happens at some time associated with the antecedent varies from what in fact happens, but is otherwise as similar as feasible, in respect of what happens at that time, to the actual world; and which obeys the actual laws of nature at all the times in that world (and perhaps shares the actual laws of nature to boot). One feature that this approach would have is that it may well result in some of the closest worlds having quite different pasts from the actual world. It is a familiar point that in a world that is deterministic and chaotic (in the technical sense of chaotic), very small changes at one time can result in very great differences in the future: one butterfly flaps its wings in one place, and a tornado that would not have otherwise happened happens on the other side of the world a year later. 4 In such deterministic and chaotic worlds, fixing the physical state at a time and determining what follows, given that state and the laws, for earlier times can produce equally extravagant differences. An extra butterfly flapping its wings now, plus the laws, might entail tornadoes in the years before that are absent from the actual world. The oddness of these counterfactual worlds diverging in their pasts (and in some cases, more and more radically as times considered are earlier and earlier than the antecedent) may only seem a 4 I am not aware of any meteorological model that is this sensitive to slight air movements, and the case that the weather is this sensitive has not been made, to my knowledge: but the illustration of the principle is useful enough, perhaps as a convenient fiction, even if actual weather systems do not behave like this.

10 10 curiosity so long as we consider causal counterfactuals with consequents only about the future. But they give incorrect results about a range of counterfactuals which have consequents that are partly about the future and partly about the past. Cases like this have been presented by Lewis [1979 p 33] and by Bennett 2003 (pp 202, 214). Let me present two, very ordinary, cases of this sort. Suppose I have just come home and looked through my bag, worried about my umbrella, and located it. I say if I had left my umbrella in the bar, that would have been the third umbrella I d have lost this month : and let us suppose that counterfactual is true in the envisaged case. For that to be true, the nearest umbrella-in-the-bar worlds have to be worlds that do not just have to resemble ours with respect to laws or how the world unrolls from the incident in the bar, but must also agree with ours in how many umbrellas I had lost earlier in the month. Examples like this can be multiplied indefinitely: it is very natural to utter counterfactuals with consequents that require all sorts of matches with the actual past to be true. The natural thing to think, here, is that our practice of uttering causal counterfactuals takes for granted that the past before the antecedent time would be as it in fact is. Counterfactuals like these also count against theories that consider situations with no past before the antecedent time: see Paul and Hall 2013 pp for a proposal of this variety. 3.3 Compatibility with Determinism, and Near Determinism If determinism is true, then necessarily if the laws are as they actually are and some complete timeslice of the past is as it actually is, then every other event will be as it actually is. So given determinism, keeping both the laws and the past the same is a challenge if we are looking for a relevantly similar world W where some antecedent which is actually false is true according to W. A theory that is compatible with determinism is one that allows that even when an antecedent of a causal counterfactual is false at a deterministic world, still there will typically be worlds relevantly similar to that world in which that antecedent is true. Indeed, the past and the laws will be able to rule out some antecedent times varying from what actually happened even if determinism is not true. Having indeterministic laws is not the same as saying that anything goes: it just means that there can be some variation in worlds that share some common past and the same laws. If our laws were indeterministic about some phenomena but not others, or some stages of the evolution of the universe but not others, they might still have the result that the past before an antecedent time, plus those laws, guarantee that the antecedent will not occur at the antecedent time. Call such cases cases of near-determinism.

11 11 Some philosophers reactions will be that this is so much the worse for determinism, and neardeterminism. Some are inclined not to worry about how an account of counterfactuals deals with determinism and near-determinism, since the kind of indeterministic world we inhabit seems to be one where almost any event permitted by the laws at all could happen after almost any history, albeit often with a vanishingly small chance of in fact doing so. However, I think there are several reasons to prefer an account that can vindicate many of our ordinary causal counterfactuals even if determinism were true, and one reason to like the style of account that can accommodate determinism even if our focus is only to produce an account fit for the sort of indeterministic world many take us to in fact be in. One reason to look for a theory compatible with determinism is our tendency to, at least sometimes, treat determinism as irrelevant for causal counterfactuals. Okay, I wouldn t have left my umbrella behind, given the past and the laws. But if I had, would I have been able to get it back?. Since we are (presumptively) competent users of counterfactual expressions, that suggests that determinism would not by itself render all causal counterfactuals vacuous or otherwise defective. Another, related, reason is that apparently competent users did not eschew the construction when determinism was widely believed (at least among the Newtonian intelligentsia). This paper will remain of some interest even for those unconvinced of these motives to have an account compatible with determinism. After all, the issue of whether determinism would have serious consequences for the truth-values of causal counterfactuals can be of interest (perhaps relatively academic interest) even to those convinced of indeterminism: and so the prospects of theories that yield the normal truth-values for causal counterfactuals even in deterministic worlds otherwise rather like our own (superficially, at least), should be of interest in weighing up different verdicts about what impact determinism would have on causal counterfactual propositions. One reason why it is instructive to consider options for counterfactuals under determinism is that some of the pressures on theories of counterfactuals under indeterminism are similar. Some indeterministic frameworks, including the ones that most plausibly describe the actual world, can produce variation from actuality at the antecedent time, while keeping the laws and past fixed, only at the cost of strange and mind-bogglingly unlikely chance events: quantum tunnelling, massive spontaneous decay, and the like. Call an incredibly unlikely quantum event that would mimic a Lewisian miracle a semi-miracle. (Note I do not mean a quasi-miracle in Lewis s sense (Lewis

12 p 60), which is its own can of worms.) Solving the deviation problem by keeping the past and laws fixed and postulating a semi-miracle to bring about an antecedent looks only a little less bad to many than postulating Lewisian miracles. If you think that semi-miracles should not be needed in an account of counterfactuals under the sort of indeterminism we probably have in this world, then you have a similar dilemma to the determinist. Just as same laws (and no miracles), same past, and a contrary-to-fact event at the antecedent time form an inconsistent triad, same laws, same past, a typical contrary-to-fact event at the antecedent time and no semi-miracles at the antecedent time will often be an inconsistent tetrad, when semi-miracle is understood in the appropriate way. The solution I will offer those who wish to allow for determinism will be straightforwardly adaptable for those who wish to endorse typical causal counterfactuals under indeterminism without its being true according to relevantly similar worlds that semi-miracles occur. 3.4 Theorists Often Compromise On These Desiderata Given the above desiderata, it is easy to see why many theorists have thought one or more of them has to go. There is apparently a tension. If world W is deterministic, then the past of W plus the laws of W entail all the other propositions true according to W. (All the other propositions about events subject to the laws of nature, in any case.) So if the antecedent of a counterfactual, A, is true according to a world with the same laws and same past as W, it looks like A would have to be entailed by W s laws and the past. So when we want to consider some counterfactual world which disagrees with W - when we want to consider a counterfactual with an antecedent A that is false according to W it seems that something has to give, out of the laws and the past. Different attempts to solve the deviation problem give up one or more of the desiderata listed above. For example, Lewis 1979 offers two accounts that address the deviation problem, and settles on the second. (Both presuppose determinism for purposes of tractability, though he offers some remarks about how to extend them to indeterminism in Lewis 1986.) Lewis s first account is not presented as a closest-worlds account, though it is easily paraphrasable into one. Both options Lewis considers violate one or more of the desiderata, above. The first permits violations of the actual laws during a transition period beginning shortly before t A (Lewis 1979 p 39) (in my jargon, violations of actual law during the antecedent time ). Lewis s second proposal in principle

13 13 allows for violation of both the desideratum about laws and the one about a common past (and indeed for cases where both are violated): but in practice it lends itself to violations of the principle about laws in deterministic worlds. Typically, the relevantly similar worlds are ones that contain miracles relative to the deterministic worlds. Jonathan Bennett (2003) talks of forks, which occur in relevantly similar worlds when the world first diverges from the actual world in a significant way. He talks of forks happening not long before what he calls the antecedent time T A. In my usage, Bennett s whole fork happens within what I call the antecedent time. Bennett allows that forks can happen in one of three ways in the relevantly most similar worlds. One is through indeterministic variation. The second is through a miracle in Lewis s sense. The third way does not require any changes in laws, even in deterministic worlds, but only tiny imperceptible differences in great stretches of the past (Bennett 2003, 217-8). This violates the common past desideratum in a comparatively low-cost way, at least in worlds that have laws kind enough to permit it, since while worlds differing in this way do not have common pasts, they have pasts that are the same in a number of respects we care about. Bennett wishes to allow that all three of these methods of forking can occur in the relevantly similar worlds (Bennett 2003, 218). Only the second two will be available in deterministic worlds (and in some indeterministic ones): so in effect, Bennett compromises both the desideratum about laws and the desideratum about the common past. One increasingly popular style of analysis of causal counterfactuals is to invoke the sort of causal models popularized by Pearl Different theorists have used these models in different ways to offer semantics for causal counterfactuals, but these approaches either compromise on the desiderata listed above or fall silent about the semantics of relevant counterfactuals, or often both. Woodward 2003, for example, both adopts a story of interventions for evaluating interventionist counterfactuals that, in effect, asks us to consider setups where there are breaches of actual laws (see Woodward p 136 where he compares his interventions to Lewis s small miracles ), and in effect only offers a way of understanding only a narrow range of counterfactuals: those whose antecedents and consequents only concern values of variables in causal models, or counterfactuals related to these. (Counterfactuals with consequents about law violations or miracles are not treated.) Menzies 2002 p 828 gives a closest-world account of the truth-conditions of a wide variety of causally relevant counterfactuals, albeit truth-conditions relative to causal models rather

14 14 than guidance about which counterfactual claims are true or false simpliciter. I take it the best way to understand Menzies here is in light of Menzies 2004 where he describes his view as a contextualist one: context fixes one or more causal models, and a counterfactual in a context is true provided it is true relative to the contextually relevant model(s). While Menzies s account is broad enough to evaluate counterfactuals with any propositions in their antecedents and consequents, (as a result of using complete worlds in the semantics), on the face of it this view also compromises the desideratum that there are no law violations. In systems that are comprehensive enough so that the initial conditions and the laws guarantee the falsehood of the antecedent, miracles, in the Lewisian sense, occur in the closest worlds where the antecedent obtains (Menzies 2003 p 164). Menzies also allows other law violations and differences in initial conditions for some counterfactuals, but says these are not the typical case for the sort of conditionals we are presently considering, as opposed e.g. to explicit counterlegals or backtrackers. (p 163-5). Menzies s version of a causal models theory of counterfactuals does have some signal advantages over others in dealing with the present puzzle. The laws of one of Menzies s causal models do not need to be the really-and-truly laws of nature, even when a causal model is one of the appropriate ones given a context. When an interfering factor is not ruled out by the laws of a causal model, the nearest worlds where the laws of the model and the initial conditions obtain may have interferers, even if the model is a deterministic one. Menzies also does not insist that a contextually salient causal model need be actually instantiated: the actual world may contain interferers the model is silent about. So the laws of a contextually appropriate causal model need not even be true universal generalisations. While Menzies himself is willing to employ miracles, a Menzies-style view that used enough of these other resources could be developed to preserve all of the desiderata I mentioned in most cases. In some special contexts and worlds, however, when the contextually salient causal models are (i) instantiated at the world of utterance, (ii) comprehensive enough to rule out interferers and (iii) deterministic, even a Menzies-style view will have few options but to violate one of our desiderata. There are, of course, many revisionist options for assigning truth-conditionals to counterfactuals, including taking their truth conditions to be those of the material conditional, offering a non-truthapt account, or endorsing the claim that they are nearly all false (for the last see Hájek unpublished).

15 15 I will assume, for the purposes of this paper at least, that we should prefer a theory of the truthconditions of causal counterfactuals that more closely tracks our reflective assent and dissent: classifying counterfactuals as true when we take them to be true in good conditions, and false when we take them to be false in good conditions. (And where our guide to which conditions are good, in this sense, is our ordinary standards for counterfactual evaluation, not our standards enlightened by much philosophical theorising.) 4. The New Option The option I wish to propose satisfies all of the desiderata discussed above. For a causal counterfactual to be true at a world W, it must be that all the nearest worlds according to which the antecedent is true, and which meet certain other conditions, are worlds according to which the consequent is true as well. The conditions on the worlds W* nearest to W are: first, that the laws of nature true at W are true according to W*. Second, that for the antecedent time t, claims entirely about the goings on in W* before t are true according to W* if, and only if, they are true according to W. Third, no proposition is true according to W* which says that a violation of the laws of nature occurs. 5 Let us in addition require that there will be some worlds among the W*s where the antecedent is true, and the nearest of the worlds in W* where the antecedent is true are worlds where the time after t is constrained to evolve by the goings-on at t and the laws of nature in the natural way (however it is best to spell that out). What this proposal does not insist on, however, is that the closest worlds to actuality where the two conditions are satisfied and the antecedent is true are possible worlds. It might well be that a certain past, together with things being a certain way at an antecedent time, is strictly inconsistent with a certain body of laws of nature. There is an important respect in which these worlds do not give rise to miracles: even if there is a proposition true according to them about what happens that in fact is inconsistent with the propositions true according to them about the laws, or indeed about what mere universal generalisations hold in these worlds, still the world may not have true according to it that there are any law violations, and may have no contradictions true according to these worlds. What is true according to possible worlds is closed under logical consequence, but this is not in general the case 5 When considering the indeterministic case, we may also wish to insist that no proposition to the effect that a semimiracle occurs at W* occurs, or something more sophisticated along those lines.

16 16 for impossible worlds. This respect in which they do not give rise to miracles is important, because the truth-value of counterfactuals such as if I had skipped lunch, something ruled out by the actual laws of nature would have occurred depends on whether something ruled out by the actual laws of nature occurred is true according to the relevantly most similar lunch-skipping world. And even if the conjunction of the actual past, the actual laws, and my skipping lunch is inconsistent, impossible worlds representing all three need not have true according to them that there is a law violation, either of their own laws or the actual laws. There would be more to say about relevant similarity in a complete account. For example, I have not tried to spell out explicitly what conjunctions of information about the past before the antecedent time plus the future of the antecedent time are true according to such closest worlds. There must be plenty of the usual ones, on pain of not vindicating the right counterfactuals that have consequents partly about the past and partly about the future, like the examples in section 3.2. It is not necessary to spell out all of the details exactly in order to evaluate this style of proposal, however: nor, indeed, would an exact specification of any sort be very plausible, since there is likely to be some semantic indeterminacy as to exactly which counterfactual conditionals are true in which contexts. Still, enough has been said to make clear why, once we appeal to impossible worlds, we can retain the laws and past of W together with the antecedent, while holding on to many of the ordinary verdicts about the truth-values of different causal counterfactuals: and can do this even if determinism, or something like it, is true in our world, or a world like ours. The compromises explored by Lewis, Bennett, and others are not needed after all. Furthermore, we can see why the quick argument in Lewis 1981 fails: he suggests that we can discount worlds where contradictory propositions are each are true as relevantly nearest, for if I had raised my hand, there would still have been no true contradictions (Lewis 1981 p 292). But there still are no true contradictions (or however else we should extract the consequent) need not be true according to any of the impossible worlds that are relevantly nearest in such a case: Lewis s objection fails to touch the proposal in this paper. There is at least one intuitive motivation for appealing to impossible worlds as a principled way out of our puzzle, and not just a technical fix. The thought is that when we evaluate a causal counterfactual, we neglect some features of counterfactual scenarios, including, to some extent, the

17 17 gritty detail of how the goings-on specified in the antecedent emerged from the past of the world under consideration. (Considerations of the gritty details tends to put us more in a frame of mind to evaluate backtracking counterfactuals: had A happened, how would it have come about?) Furthermore, this neglect is not just due to our ignorance about the exact processes that our past and laws permit. It may be that the rules of the practice itself are insensitive to some of the details here. If the principles of the practice are somewhat insensitive to these details, then even if the practice is primarily concerned with imposing constraints that it is individually possible to satisfy (sameness of laws, sameness of past, sameness of the kind of dependence the future displays on the laws plus the arrangement of the antecedent time), philosophers may well be over-idealising if they look for scenarios that are possible all-things-considered, rather than just matching possibilities in a number of respects, respects which conflict in an area with which the practice is not particularly concerned. If this picture is the right way of thinking about the counterfactual scenarios relevant to causal counterfactuals, then the discovery that these scenarios are all-things-considered impossible no longer seems particularly objectionable, nor even particularly surprising once we see how the competing demands of actual laws, actual past, and counterfactual antecedent can be inconsistent given determinism, or something close to determinism. The new option I have proposed satisfies all the desiderata listed above, and if that is all we were concerned about it might at this point look ideal. Before reaching that conclusion, however, it would be well to look at the apparent costs of the theory. Others may disagree with me about what weight we should give each of these considerations, but I hope at least to touch on the ones most likely to occur to critics. 5. Counting the Costs The first feature that some will take to be a cost is that the account requires impossible worlds as well as possible ones: and even those happy with possible worlds sometimes balk at ways things couldn t be. (See e.g. Stalnaker 2002.) Positing impossible worlds, and using them in the theory of counterfactuals, seems to me eminently worth doing for reasons entirely independent of puzzles about causal counterfactuals: see Nolan 1997 for arguments to this effect. Employing impossible worlds is not a reason per se to be suspicious of this account. A second potentially objectionable feature of this theory is that it yields the result that many counterfactuals with possibly true antecedents and possibly true consequents nevertheless require

18 18 evaluations of those propositions at impossible worlds to yield their truth values. Or, to put it a different way, the theory holds that the nearest worlds where certain possible antecedents are true are impossible worlds: they manage to be closer than all of the possible worlds where those antecedents obtain. This violates a plausible principle I have labelled the Strangeness of Impossibility Condition (SIC) (Nolan ): the principle that every possible world is closer to every other possible world than any impossible world is to any possible world. This principle is plausible for at least two reasons. One is that it captures the idea that if something A, could obtain, its obtaining wouldn t be impossible: a natural way to try to capture this thought formally would be that, for possible A and impossible I, no case of if A then I is true. Another is that if SIC is true, then something like the usual possible-worlds semantics for counterfactuals can hold in the vast range of ordinary cases when the antecedents of the conditionals that concern us are possible. Impossible worlds need only make a difference to truth conditions when impossible antecedents are in play. Despite these advantages of the SIC, I think there are good enough independent reasons to reject it. I had already expressed some reservations about it in Nolan 1997 p 550, 569 ftnt 21, and more counterexamples can be found in Vander Laan In some contexts at least, relevant similarity seems to require that we count some impossible worlds as closer than some possible worlds. Here is a relatively everyday example. Suppose I have been playing a game with a boy called Oliver, where we arrange balls into a square grid, then tip the balls into a bag, then count the balls that come out. Sometimes the total is 4, sometimes 9, sometimes 49.. and so on. While playing it, I introduce Oliver to the idea of a square number, in the obvious way. On a particular occasion, we come up with a count of 63 balls from the bag. If the bag had 63 balls in it, 63 would have been a square number seems like an appropriate thing for me to say in explaining why I think we miscounted: and I think a true thing to say, in that context. But of course it is possible for that bag to contain 63 balls, and impossible for 63 to be square. So at least in some contexts of utterance of counterfactuals, SIC fails. Even if we reject the SIC in full generality, however, there remains a problem. Many counterexamples to SIC involve relatively unusual cases, or at least unusual contexts of utterance. But the violations of SIC suggested by the theory in this paper are potentially far more widespread, and infect many more everyday conditionals. In deterministic worlds, almost all false antecedents

19 19 in causal counterfactuals will invoke impossible worlds: and in indeterministic worlds where the laws put strict limits on what is permitted in the future given the past, many false antecedents will produce SIC violations. If we are to use the strategy of this paper to avoid semi-miracles, even cases where the past and the laws are co-possible with the antecedent may still be ones where the relevantly nearest world may be an impossible one that lacks semi-miracles rather than possible worlds containing semi-miracles. Even those suspicious of the SIC may be inclined to raise their eyebrows at the claim that goings-on in impossible worlds are relevant to the truth-value of mundane causal counterfactuals. There are some ways to sugar this pill. If we think of people putting together beliefs about how things typically work, with beliefs about what happened before the relevant time, with beliefs about ordinary ways for the antecedent to be true at the antecedent time, and then roll the situation forward in thought, it might not be so surprising after all that the first three parts of that process might answer to standards that can come into conflict. It is agreed on all hands that we lack an a priori guarantee that the actual laws and the actual past will permit the antecedent to be the case, or permit it to be the case in a non-miracle-like way. Finding some possible situation that meets the demands well enough in a non-obvious way is a sensible thing to try: but when we discover that these worlds are unsatisfactory in various respects (containing miracles, containing different pasts, etc.), then involving an impossible situation that meets all the constraints our practice answers to does, after all, seem like a option that is not so unintuitive. A third dubious commitment of this theory is that it requires a particular account of which worlds are most similar, in relevant respects, to the world at which the causal counterfactuals are being evaluated. Some will find the judgement of relevant similarity straightforwardly implausible. Let us suppose that a world is deterministic, and a strong man is standing, holding a hammer, next to a thin glass vase - and at that world he stands still. Why, apart from the demands of the theory, should we suppose that the most relevantly similar world where that man (or his counterpart) swings the hammer at the vase (or its counterpart) is a strange, inconsistent world, where even though the laws plus the past dictate that he stands still he nevertheless swings the hammer and the glass flies into pieces, and furthermore that according to this world, everything happens in accordance with its laws? We may be able to make some surrealist sense of such an impossibility, but surely a possibility where the laws are slightly different, or the past was different enough to produce a man ready to swing, should be counted as a more similar situation to the world we began

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument

The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument The Problem with Complete States: Freedom, Chance and the Luck Argument Richard Johns Department of Philosophy University of British Columbia August 2006 Revised March 2009 The Luck Argument seems to show

More information

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts

Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts ANAL63-3 4/15/2003 2:40 PM Page 221 Resemblance Nominalism and counterparts Alexander Bird 1. Introduction In his (2002) Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra provides a powerful articulation of the claim that Resemblance

More information

Between the Actual and the Trivial World

Between the Actual and the Trivial World Organon F 23 (2) 2016: xxx-xxx Between the Actual and the Trivial World MACIEJ SENDŁAK Institute of Philosophy. University of Szczecin Ul. Krakowska 71-79. 71-017 Szczecin. Poland maciej.sendlak@gmail.com

More information

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION

AN ACTUAL-SEQUENCE THEORY OF PROMOTION BY D. JUSTIN COATES JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE JANUARY 2014 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT D. JUSTIN COATES 2014 An Actual-Sequence Theory of Promotion ACCORDING TO HUMEAN THEORIES,

More information

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN

ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN DISCUSSION NOTE ON PROMOTING THE DEAD CERTAIN: A REPLY TO BEHRENDS, DIPAOLO AND SHARADIN BY STEFAN FISCHER JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE APRIL 2017 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT STEFAN

More information

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature.

REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. REVIEW: Marc Lange, Laws and Lawmakers: Science, Metaphysics, and the Laws of Nature. Author(s): Christopher Belanger Source: Spontaneous Generations: A Journal for the History and Philosophy of Science,

More information

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1

NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH. Let s begin with the storage hypothesis, which is introduced as follows: 1 DOUBTS ABOUT UNCERTAINTY WITHOUT ALL THE DOUBT NICHOLAS J.J. SMITH Norby s paper is divided into three main sections in which he introduces the storage hypothesis, gives reasons for rejecting it and then

More information

Counterfactuals and Causation: Transitivity

Counterfactuals and Causation: Transitivity Counterfactuals and Causation: Transitivity By Miloš Radovanovi Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of

More information

Comments on Lasersohn

Comments on Lasersohn Comments on Lasersohn John MacFarlane September 29, 2006 I ll begin by saying a bit about Lasersohn s framework for relativist semantics and how it compares to the one I ve been recommending. I ll focus

More information

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge

ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge ON THE TRUTH CONDITIONS OF INDICATIVE AND COUNTERFACTUAL CONDITIONALS Wylie Breckenridge In this essay I will survey some theories about the truth conditions of indicative and counterfactual conditionals.

More information

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011.

Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks. Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. Truth and Molinism * Trenton Merricks Molinism: The Contemporary Debate edited by Ken Perszyk. Oxford University Press, 2011. According to Luis de Molina, God knows what each and every possible human would

More information

Final Paper. May 13, 2015

Final Paper. May 13, 2015 24.221 Final Paper May 13, 2015 Determinism states the following: given the state of the universe at time t 0, denoted S 0, and the conjunction of the laws of nature, L, the state of the universe S at

More information

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions

Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions Molinism and divine prophecy of free actions GRAHAM OPPY School of Philosophical, Historical and International Studies, Monash University, Clayton Campus, Wellington Road, Clayton VIC 3800 AUSTRALIA Graham.Oppy@monash.edu

More information

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings *

Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings * Commentary Metaphysical Language, Ordinary Language and Peter van Inwagen s Material Beings * Peter van Inwagen Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1990 Daniel Nolan** daniel.nolan@nottingham.ac.uk Material

More information

Theories of propositions

Theories of propositions Theories of propositions phil 93515 Jeff Speaks January 16, 2007 1 Commitment to propositions.......................... 1 2 A Fregean theory of reference.......................... 2 3 Three theories of

More information

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002

Understanding Truth Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 1 Symposium on Understanding Truth By Scott Soames Précis Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Volume LXV, No. 2, 2002 2 Precis of Understanding Truth Scott Soames Understanding Truth aims to illuminate

More information

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June

Conference on the Epistemology of Keith Lehrer, PUCRS, Porto Alegre (Brazil), June 2 Reply to Comesaña* Réplica a Comesaña Carl Ginet** 1. In the Sentence-Relativity section of his comments, Comesaña discusses my attempt (in the Relativity to Sentences section of my paper) to convince

More information

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic

Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic Empty Names and Two-Valued Positive Free Logic 1 Introduction Zahra Ahmadianhosseini In order to tackle the problem of handling empty names in logic, Andrew Bacon (2013) takes on an approach based on positive

More information

Chance, Possibility, and Explanation Nina Emery

Chance, Possibility, and Explanation Nina Emery The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science Advance Access published October 25, 2013 Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 0 (2013), 1 26 Chance, Possibility, and Explanation ABSTRACT I argue against the common and

More information

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield

Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield Humean Supervenience: Lewis (1986, Introduction) 7 October 2010: J. Butterfield 1: Humean supervenience and the plan of battle: Three key ideas of Lewis mature metaphysical system are his notions of possible

More information

xiv Truth Without Objectivity

xiv Truth Without Objectivity Introduction There is a certain approach to theorizing about language that is called truthconditional semantics. The underlying idea of truth-conditional semantics is often summarized as the idea that

More information

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise

Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise Religious Studies 42, 123 139 f 2006 Cambridge University Press doi:10.1017/s0034412506008250 Printed in the United Kingdom Divine omniscience, timelessness, and the power to do otherwise HUGH RICE Christ

More information

Are There Reasons to Be Rational?

Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Are There Reasons to Be Rational? Olav Gjelsvik, University of Oslo The thesis. Among people writing about rationality, few people are more rational than Wlodek Rabinowicz. But are there reasons for being

More information

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview

Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview Branden Fitelson Philosophy 125 Lecture 1 Philosophy 125 Day 21: Overview 1st Papers/SQ s to be returned this week (stay tuned... ) Vanessa s handout on Realism about propositions to be posted Second papers/s.q.

More information

On possibly nonexistent propositions

On possibly nonexistent propositions On possibly nonexistent propositions Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 abstract. Alvin Plantinga gave a reductio of the conjunction of the following three theses: Existentialism (the view that, e.g., the proposition

More information

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln

A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction. Albert Casullo. University of Nebraska-Lincoln A Defense of the Significance of the A Priori A Posteriori Distinction Albert Casullo University of Nebraska-Lincoln The distinction between a priori and a posteriori knowledge has come under fire by a

More information

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle

Millian responses to Frege s puzzle Millian responses to Frege s puzzle phil 93914 Jeff Speaks February 28, 2008 1 Two kinds of Millian................................. 1 2 Conciliatory Millianism............................... 2 2.1 Hidden

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Let me state at the outset a basic point that will reappear again below with its justification. The title of this chapter (and many other discussions too) make it appear

More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information

part one MACROSTRUCTURE Cambridge University Press X - A Theory of Argument Mark Vorobej Excerpt More information part one MACROSTRUCTURE 1 Arguments 1.1 Authors and Audiences An argument is a social activity, the goal of which is interpersonal rational persuasion. More precisely, we ll say that an argument occurs

More information

Stout s teleological theory of action

Stout s teleological theory of action Stout s teleological theory of action Jeff Speaks November 26, 2004 1 The possibility of externalist explanations of action................ 2 1.1 The distinction between externalist and internalist explanations

More information

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick

Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick Review: The Objects of Thought, by Tim Crane. Guy Longworth University of Warwick 24.4.14 We can think about things that don t exist. For example, we can think about Pegasus, and Pegasus doesn t exist.

More information

Contextual two-dimensionalism

Contextual two-dimensionalism Contextual two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks November 30, 2009 1 Two two-dimensionalist system of The Conscious Mind.............. 1 1.1 Primary and secondary intensions...................... 2

More information

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers

Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis. David J. Chalmers Moral Relativism and Conceptual Analysis David J. Chalmers An Inconsistent Triad (1) All truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths (2) No moral truths are a priori entailed by fundamental truths

More information

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division

An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine. Foreknowledge and Free Will. Alex Cavender. Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will Alex Cavender Ringstad Paper Junior/Senior Division 1 An Alternate Possibility for the Compatibility of Divine Foreknowledge

More information

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan

Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan Causing People to Exist and Saving People s Lives Jeff McMahan 1 Possible People Suppose that whatever one does a new person will come into existence. But one can determine who this person will be by either

More information

Varieties of Apriority

Varieties of Apriority S E V E N T H E X C U R S U S Varieties of Apriority T he notions of a priori knowledge and justification play a central role in this work. There are many ways in which one can understand the a priori,

More information

Time travel and the open future

Time travel and the open future Time travel and the open future University of Queensland Abstract I argue that the thesis that time travel is logically possible, is inconsistent with the necessary truth of any of the usual open future-objective

More information

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self

A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self A Review of Neil Feit s Belief about the Self Stephan Torre 1 Neil Feit. Belief about the Self. Oxford GB: Oxford University Press 2008. 216 pages. Belief about the Self is a clearly written, engaging

More information

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge

Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge Wright on response-dependence and self-knowledge March 23, 2004 1 Response-dependent and response-independent concepts........... 1 1.1 The intuitive distinction......................... 1 1.2 Basic equations

More information

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXV No. 3, November 2012 Ó 2012 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC On Possibly Nonexistent Propositions

More information

Bayesian Probability

Bayesian Probability Bayesian Probability Patrick Maher September 4, 2008 ABSTRACT. Bayesian decision theory is here construed as explicating a particular concept of rational choice and Bayesian probability is taken to be

More information

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on

Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work on Review of David J. Chalmers Constructing the World (OUP 2012) Thomas W. Polger, University of Cincinnati 1. Introduction David Chalmers burst onto the philosophical scene in the mid-1990s with his work

More information

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments

Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Foreknowledge, evil, and compatibility arguments Jeff Speaks January 25, 2011 1 Warfield s argument for compatibilism................................ 1 2 Why the argument fails to show that free will and

More information

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response

Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response Prompt: Explain van Inwagen s consequence argument. Describe what you think is the best response to this argument. Does this response succeed in saving compatibilism from the consequence argument? Why

More information

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic

Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT. Alvin Plantinga first brought the term existentialism into the currency of analytic Existentialism Entails Anti-Haecceitism DRAFT Abstract: Existentialism concerning singular propositions is the thesis that singular propositions ontologically depend on the individuals they are directly

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada

VAGUENESS. Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada VAGUENESS Francis Jeffry Pelletier and István Berkeley Department of Philosophy University of Alberta Edmonton, Alberta, Canada Vagueness: an expression is vague if and only if it is possible that it give

More information

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER

DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT JOHN MARTIN FISCHER . Published by Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK, and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA METAPHILOSOPHY Vol. 36, No. 4, July 2005 0026-1068 DENNETT ON THE BASIC ARGUMENT

More information

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026

British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), doi: /bjps/axr026 British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62 (2011), 899-907 doi:10.1093/bjps/axr026 URL: Please cite published version only. REVIEW

More information

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior

Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior DOI 10.1007/s11406-016-9782-z Sensitivity hasn t got a Heterogeneity Problem - a Reply to Melchior Kevin Wallbridge 1 Received: 3 May 2016 / Revised: 7 September 2016 / Accepted: 17 October 2016 # The

More information

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth

The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth SECOND EXCURSUS The Inscrutability of Reference and the Scrutability of Truth I n his 1960 book Word and Object, W. V. Quine put forward the thesis of the Inscrutability of Reference. This thesis says

More information

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism

The Rightness Error: An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism An Evaluation of Normative Ethics in the Absence of Moral Realism Mathais Sarrazin J.L. Mackie s Error Theory postulates that all normative claims are false. It does this based upon his denial of moral

More information

Merricks on the existence of human organisms

Merricks on the existence of human organisms Merricks on the existence of human organisms Cian Dorr August 24, 2002 Merricks s Overdetermination Argument against the existence of baseballs depends essentially on the following premise: BB Whenever

More information

Putnam: Meaning and Reference

Putnam: Meaning and Reference Putnam: Meaning and Reference The Traditional Conception of Meaning combines two assumptions: Meaning and psychology Knowing the meaning (of a word, sentence) is being in a psychological state. Even Frege,

More information

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00

The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, Pp $105.00 1 The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings, by Michael Almeida. New York: Routledge, 2008. Pp. 190. $105.00 (hardback). GREG WELTY, Southwestern Baptist Theological Seminary. In The Metaphysics of Perfect Beings,

More information

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori

Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori Boghossian & Harman on the analytic theory of the a priori PHIL 83104 November 2, 2011 Both Boghossian and Harman address themselves to the question of whether our a priori knowledge can be explained in

More information

Causation and Free Will

Causation and Free Will Causation and Free Will T L Hurst Revised: 17th August 2011 Abstract This paper looks at the main philosophic positions on free will. It suggests that the arguments for causal determinism being compatible

More information

Epistemic two-dimensionalism

Epistemic two-dimensionalism Epistemic two-dimensionalism phil 93507 Jeff Speaks December 1, 2009 1 Four puzzles.......................................... 1 2 Epistemic two-dimensionalism................................ 3 2.1 Two-dimensional

More information

Some proposals for understanding narrow content

Some proposals for understanding narrow content Some proposals for understanding narrow content February 3, 2004 1 What should we require of explanations of narrow content?......... 1 2 Narrow psychology as whatever is shared by intrinsic duplicates......

More information

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Saying too Little and Saying too Much. Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Umeå University BIBLID [0873-626X (2013) 35; pp. 81-91] 1 Introduction You are going to Paul

More information

Coordination Problems

Coordination Problems Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Philosophy and Phenomenological Research Vol. LXXXI No. 2, September 2010 Ó 2010 Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LLC Coordination Problems scott soames

More information

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled?

Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? Truth and Modality - can they be reconciled? by Eileen Walker 1) The central question What makes modal statements statements about what might be or what might have been the case true or false? Normally

More information

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work.

It is advisable to refer to the publisher s version if you intend to cite from the work. Article Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions Thornton, Tim Available at http://clok.uclan.ac.uk/4356/ Thornton, Tim (2011) Capacity, Mental Mechanisms, and Unwise Decisions. Philosophy, Psychiatry,

More information

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when

what you know is a constitutive norm of the practice of assertion. 2 recently maintained that in either form, the knowledge account of assertion when How to Link Assertion and Knowledge Without Going Contextualist 1 HOW TO LINK ASSERTION AND KNOWLEDGE WITHOUT GOING CONTEXTUALIST: A REPLY TO DEROSE S ASSERTION, KNOWLEDGE, AND CONTEXT The knowledge account

More information

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions

Truth At a World for Modal Propositions Truth At a World for Modal Propositions 1 Introduction Existentialism is a thesis that concerns the ontological status of individual essences and singular propositions. Let us define an individual essence

More information

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St.

proper construal of Davidson s principle of rationality will show the objection to be misguided. Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Do e s An o m a l o u s Mo n i s m Hav e Explanatory Force? Andrew Wong Washington University, St. Louis The aim of this paper is to support Donald Davidson s Anomalous Monism 1 as an account of law-governed

More information

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp

Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp Philosophical Issues, vol. 8 (1997), pp. 313-323. Different Kinds of Kind Terms: A Reply to Sosa and Kim 1 by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill In "'Good' on Twin Earth"

More information

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language

Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language Unit VI: Davidson and the interpretational approach to thought and language October 29, 2003 1 Davidson s interdependence thesis..................... 1 2 Davidson s arguments for interdependence................

More information

Possibility and Necessity

Possibility and Necessity Possibility and Necessity 1. Modality: Modality is the study of possibility and necessity. These concepts are intuitive enough. Possibility: Some things could have been different. For instance, I could

More information

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1

Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz, Principles, and Truth 1 Leibniz was a man of principles. 2 Throughout his writings, one finds repeated assertions that his view is developed according to certain fundamental principles. Attempting

More information

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind

Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind Objections to the two-dimensionalism of The Conscious Mind phil 93515 Jeff Speaks February 7, 2007 1 Problems with the rigidification of names..................... 2 1.1 Names as actually -rigidified descriptions..................

More information

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS

ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS ILLOCUTIONARY ORIGINS OF FAMILIAR LOGICAL OPERATORS 1. ACTS OF USING LANGUAGE Illocutionary logic is the logic of speech acts, or language acts. Systems of illocutionary logic have both an ontological,

More information

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action

BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity: Thomas Reid s Theory of Action University of Nebraska - Lincoln DigitalCommons@University of Nebraska - Lincoln Faculty Publications - Department of Philosophy Philosophy, Department of 2005 BOOK REVIEW: Gideon Yaffee, Manifest Activity:

More information

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities

Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities This is the author version of the following article: Baltimore, Joseph A. (2014). Modal Realism, Counterpart Theory, and Unactualized Possibilities. Metaphysica, 15 (1), 209 217. The final publication

More information

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona

SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio. University of Arizona SITUATIONS AND RESPONSIVENESS TO REASONS * Carolina Sartorio University of Arizona Some classical studies in social psychology suggest that we are more sensitive to situational factors, and less responsive

More information

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013

Reply to Kit Fine. Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Reply to Kit Fine Theodore Sider July 19, 2013 Kit Fine s paper raises important and difficult issues about my approach to the metaphysics of fundamentality. In chapters 7 and 8 I examined certain subtle

More information

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods

Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods Semantic Foundations for Deductive Methods delineating the scope of deductive reason Roger Bishop Jones Abstract. The scope of deductive reason is considered. First a connection is discussed between the

More information

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University

Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators. Christopher Peacocke. Columbia University Understanding, Modality, Logical Operators Christopher Peacocke Columbia University Timothy Williamson s The Philosophy of Philosophy stimulates on every page. I would like to discuss every chapter. To

More information

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY

WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY Miłosz Pawłowski WHY IS GOD GOOD? EUTYPHRO, TIMAEUS AND THE DIVINE COMMAND THEORY In Eutyphro Plato presents a dilemma 1. Is it that acts are good because God wants them to be performed 2? Or are they

More information

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW

TWO VERSIONS OF HUME S LAW DISCUSSION NOTE BY CAMPBELL BROWN JOURNAL OF ETHICS & SOCIAL PHILOSOPHY DISCUSSION NOTE MAY 2015 URL: WWW.JESP.ORG COPYRIGHT CAMPBELL BROWN 2015 Two Versions of Hume s Law MORAL CONCLUSIONS CANNOT VALIDLY

More information

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University

Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University 1. INTRODUCTION MAKING THINGS UP Under contract with Oxford University Press Karen Bennett Cornell University The aim of philosophy, abstractly formulated, is to understand how things in the broadest possible

More information

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst

Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst Kantian Humility and Ontological Categories Sam Cowling University of Massachusetts, Amherst [Forthcoming in Analysis. Penultimate Draft. Cite published version.] Kantian Humility holds that agents like

More information

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood

Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem. Ralph Wedgwood Gandalf s Solution to the Newcomb Problem Ralph Wedgwood I wish it need not have happened in my time, said Frodo. So do I, said Gandalf, and so do all who live to see such times. But that is not for them

More information

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture *

Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture * In Philosophical Studies 112: 251-278, 2003. ( Kluwer Academic Publishers) Presupposition and Accommodation: Understanding the Stalnakerian picture * Mandy Simons Abstract This paper offers a critical

More information

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul

Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Saying too Little and Saying too Much Critical notice of Lying, Misleading, and What is Said, by Jennifer Saul Andreas Stokke andreas.stokke@gmail.com - published in Disputatio, V(35), 2013, 81-91 - 1

More information

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem?

1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1 What is conceptual analysis and what is the problem? 1.1 What is conceptual analysis? In this book, I am going to defend the viability of conceptual analysis as a philosophical method. It therefore seems

More information

Egocentric Rationality

Egocentric Rationality 3 Egocentric Rationality 1. The Subject Matter of Egocentric Epistemology Egocentric epistemology is concerned with the perspectives of individual believers and the goal of having an accurate and comprehensive

More information

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University

Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational. Joshua Schechter. Brown University Luck, Rationality, and Explanation: A Reply to Elga s Lucky to Be Rational Joshua Schechter Brown University I Introduction What is the epistemic significance of discovering that one of your beliefs depends

More information

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the

THE MEANING OF OUGHT. Ralph Wedgwood. What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the THE MEANING OF OUGHT Ralph Wedgwood What does the word ought mean? Strictly speaking, this is an empirical question, about the meaning of a word in English. Such empirical semantic questions should ideally

More information

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On

Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge by Dorit Bar-On Self-ascriptions of mental states, whether in speech or thought, seem to have a unique status. Suppose I make an utterance of the form I

More information

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument

Compatibilism and the Basic Argument ESJP #12 2017 Compatibilism and the Basic Argument Lennart Ackermans 1 Introduction In his book Freedom Evolves (2003) and article (Taylor & Dennett, 2001), Dennett constructs a compatibilist theory of

More information

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University

Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY. Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University Philosophical Perspectives, 14, Action and Freedom, 2000 TRANSFER PRINCIPLES AND MORAL RESPONSIBILITY Eleonore Stump Saint Louis University John Martin Fischer University of California, Riverside It is

More information

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become

In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become Aporia vol. 24 no. 1 2014 Incoherence in Epistemic Relativism I. Introduction In Epistemic Relativism, Mark Kalderon defends a view that has become increasingly popular across various academic disciplines.

More information

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1. Dana K. Nelkin. I. Introduction. abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory. THE SENSE OF FREEDOM 1 Dana K. Nelkin I. Introduction We appear to have an inescapable sense that we are free, a sense that we cannot abandon even in the face of powerful arguments that this sense is illusory.

More information

Counterfactuals Without Causation, Probabilistic Counterfactuals and the Counterfactual Analysis of Causation

Counterfactuals Without Causation, Probabilistic Counterfactuals and the Counterfactual Analysis of Causation Counterfactuals Without Causation, Probabilistic Counterfactuals and the Counterfactual Analysis of Causation Item Type text; Electronic Dissertation Authors Loewenstein, Yael Rebecca Publisher The University

More information

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they

Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument. Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they Moral Twin Earth: The Intuitive Argument Terence Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently published a series of articles where they attack the new moral realism as developed by Richard Boyd. 1 The new moral

More information

This is an electronic version of a paper Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: , 2014.

This is an electronic version of a paper Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: , 2014. This is an electronic version of a paper Journal of Philosophical Logic 43: 979-997, 2014. The following passage occurs on p.994 of the published version: The invalidity of Antecedent Strengthening cannot

More information

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon

In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle. Simon Rippon In Defense of The Wide-Scope Instrumental Principle Simon Rippon Suppose that people always have reason to take the means to the ends that they intend. 1 Then it would appear that people s intentions to

More information

Counterfactual Skepticism and. Multidimensional Semantics

Counterfactual Skepticism and. Multidimensional Semantics Counterfactual Skepticism and Multidimensional Semantics H. Orri Stefánsson www.orristefansson.is June 9, 2017 Abstract It has recently been argued that indeterminacy and indeterminism make most ordinary

More information