On concepts that give themselves their own actuality (Kant, Fichte, Hegel) Edgar Maraguat University of Valencia. 1. Introduction

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "On concepts that give themselves their own actuality (Kant, Fichte, Hegel) Edgar Maraguat University of Valencia. 1. Introduction"

Transcription

1 On concepts that give themselves their own actuality (Kant, Fichte, Hegel) Edgar Maraguat University of Valencia 1. Introduction The centrality of the idea of concept that gives itself its own actuality in Hegel s Logic is difficult to overstate. Indeed, this idea could be seen as the culmination of the argument he makes in The Science of Logic ( ). Hegel explains how every determination of the understanding is ultimately solved or, as he usually puts it, ultimately has its truth in a conceptual determination, in a concept, that gives itself its own actuality (see 12:20f, 24, 171, 174, 182, Enz. 1817: 161, 162 Anm., Enz. 1830: 213). 1 Taken by itself and without specifications, the so-called idea (die Idee) or concept raised to the idea, to which the concluding part of the Logic is entirely devoted, is nothing but the concept that gives itself its own actuality. The Idee is the unity of concept and objectivity, but more specifically the unity of a concept that gives objectivity, actuality, effectiveness, even external existence (in der Form äusserlichen Daseyns) to itself, by itself, from itself (see Enz. 1817: 161). This might initially seem like a bizarre notion, since we tend to understand concepts as mental representations of pre-existing (or potentially pre-existing) states of things or as mental representations of things that could come into being through the intervention of active beings like us, rather than as representations that give themselves their own actuality. However, the idea of a concept that gives itself or contains its own actuality is well known in the metaphysical tradition. It is, as a matter of course, the idea that underlies and allegedly supports any ontological argument. This being said, and although Hegel does not disregard the connection that his idea may have and does have, something he actually does not conceal at all with that tradition (see Enz. 1817: 162, Enz. 1830: 204 Anm.), when he presents his idea of idea both in the Wissenschaft der Logik and in his Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften he links it in the first instance with Kant s practical ideas, by comparing the actuality the concept (in his opinion) gives itself with the necessity, objectivity and actuality of those Kantian 1 All references in the body of the text are to the critical edition of Hegel s works: G. W. F. Hegel, Gesammelte Werke, Frankfurt am Main, Felix Meiner, 1968ff, specifying the volume and page number. The original is only quoted in the case of the 1817 edition of the Encyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im Grundrisse. 1

2 ideas (see 12:174). I think it is correct to infer from such passages that Hegel s idea springs less from the metaphysical tradition than from the Kantian critique of that tradition and, specifically, from the arguments of idealists first Kant and then Fichte and Schelling on the need for philosophy to be based on a selfaffirming principle, be it self-consciousness, reason or freedom. It is well known that Hegel frequently refers to this metaphysical tradition in a derogatory manner. In the Logic, this occurs in relation with discussions about the teleological nature of the world and the doctrine of the soul, among others. Some have thus been tempted to interpret Hegel s thought as fundamentally continuous with the transcendental philosophy of Kant and Fichte, as pursuing their project of seeking in consciousness, in the self or perhaps in moral conscience, a principle of philosophy that might replace or would at least aspire to replace the old traditional divine principle. For reasons that will briefly be stated below, however, I consider it would be hasty and indeed wrong to assume that Hegel borrowed from Kant or, alternatively, Fichte, the idea of concept that gives itself its own actuality (or becomes reality by itself). Literally speaking, it is certainly borrowed from Kant, as Hegel conceives the idea as an end (Zweck) and an end is for Kant, according to the Critik der Urtheilskraft, the concept of an object inasmuch as it is (also) the foundation of its own actuality. 2 We also find it in Fichte, who describes the activity of the self as a causation of the mere concept. 3 Nevertheless, it would first of all be strange for the apex of Hegel s Logic to display such a fundamental coincidence with the views of his idealist predecessors regarding such a fundamental matter as the relationship between concept and reality. After all, Hegel s controversial references to the way in which Kant, in particular, had miscarried once and again his philosophical discoveries are no less known than his disparaging references to the metaphysical tradition. I think his differences with Kant, as also with Fichte (expressed in so many key places) go beyond the dubious development of their well-understood and settled principles or purely structural issues in the systematics of philosophy. Regarding Kant, Hegel praises some of the fundamental distinctions he makes in his Critiques and, in connection with our topic, precisely the resuscitation of the Aristotelian idea of internal finality (innere Zweckmäßigkeit) on which, as we will see, the definition of Hegel s idea of idea will be based. However, he relentlessly observes that Kant immediately reduces this notion the principle of finality to a maxim of the understanding, thus depriving it precisely of the actuality Hegel believes it has and should be recognised to have (cf. Enz. 1830: 58-60, 12:158f). 2 See I. Kant, Critik der Urtheilskraft, B XXVIII. 3 J. G. Fichte, System der Sittlichkeit, Gesammtausgabe, I, 5:27. 2

3 With respect to Fichte, we can arguably find the presence of a veiled critique of his argumentative strategy in the first pages of the chapter devoted to teleology in the Logic, precisely the one that contains the deduction of the idea of idea, when referring to the way in which some assume the truth of the teleological principle (as others would have done with the mechanical principle) and then show that the principle they have taken for granted cannot be deduced from the other (see 12:154 and 12:15), deploying an argumentative strategy Hegel neither shares nor wants to share. All this does not obscure the fact that Hegel continues a discussion opened by his predecessors. When the time comes to presenting and examining which actuality the concept gives itself and how, the matter of the Logic has become the antinomy between fatalism and freedom (see 12:154) or, what for Hegel would be the same, the third conflict of transcendental ideas of the Critique of Pure Reason (see 12:157), about whether all causation is governed by natural laws or it is necessary to accept, in order to explain the world s phenomena, a causation through freedom as well (durch Freiheit). The issue thus becomes one that is also essential for Fichte, who saw the refutation of Spinoza s opinion on that antinomy as one of the major achievements of his Wissenschaftslehre. In my opinion, therefore, the great interest that the Logic s chapter on teleology must arouse stems from the fact that Hegel seems to explain there which is his personal resolution (or dissolution) of the third Kantian antinomy, one that was already of great importance for Kant and that Fichte s Doctrine had, if anything, emphasised. So that an examination of this chapter would make it possible to understand the critical differences between them on this point. In the short space at my disposal, I will limit myself to offer a seemingly reasonable outline of this matter. I think it is inevitable to start out by considering in some detail how Kant and Fichte respectively understood the possibility of a concept giving itself its own actuality, in order to picture the backdrop against which Hegel could define his position. I shall then explain, albeit very schematically, how Hegel understood the battle over this concept, the place where his argument starts, how it develops and where it leads him. 2. Antecedents In the specific field of the philosophy of action, what is at stake for Kant is our ability to act according to the representation of an unconditional duty, and purely because of the nature of this duty. What is at issue, of course, is whether this actually occurs, whether we sometimes act because of such a representation, regardless of the direction in which our inclinations push us, and how that might 3

4 be possible, how that representation and the feelings it certainly arouses might outdo the influence of contradictory tendencies. But Kant effectively calls into question that anyone has ever acted according to a duty purely for the sake of complying with it. As a result, he does not intend to offer any evidence that a particular action was the pure effect of a pure representation of duty. Kant limits himself to showing that we cannot think this could not have been the case and that, therefore, we are indispensably obliged to morally judge what we did in the past and what we might do in the future, from the perspective of an unconditional duty (and the existence of alternatives). For this reason, since we cannot rule out either with respect to the past or the future the possibility of having acted or acting in one way and another, against the duty and in favour of the duty, we can say this is how Kant understands it that the idea of pure duty ceases to be or simply is not a mere representation, to become or simply be a representation that gives itself its effectiveness in our (ephemeral) lives. 4 Manifestly, the basis of Kant s argumentation is to be found in the very definite way he has to understand the inevitability or necessity of adopting a moral point of view as the one he defines on ourselves. Kant believes that this inevitability arises from the very fact that we are rational beings, i.e., from the very fact that we recurrently we could almost say systematically in the colloquial sense of the term wonder about what we should think and do. What is more, we consider some opinions and intentions to be ours just because we believe ourselves able to provide reasons for having adopted and for keeping them, as one might argue. Additionally, Kant takes for granted that being rational consists in operating according to principles of fully general validity and that such generality is incompatible with any reference to factual trends or intentions. He thus concludes that, as rational beings, we are bound by a categorical imperative. It is in this obligation, inherent to the rational being, where Kant sees the realisation of the imperative, the realisation of the pure concept of duty. The main difference between Kant s view about the realisation of practical ideas and Fichte s view during the Jena period is that the former apparently believes that his arguments only provide a practical proof of that realisation, whereas Fichte does not accept a relativisation of their value. 5 Certainly, some 4 dadurch es denn geschieht, daß, da es in allen Vorschriften der reinen praktischen Vernunft nur um die Willensbestimmung, nicht um die Naturbedingungen (des praktischen Vermögens) der Ausführung seiner Absicht zu thun ist, die praktischen Begriffe a priori in Beziehung auf das oberste Princip der Freiheit sogleich Erkenntnisse werden und nicht auf Anschauungen warten dürfen, um Bedeutung zu bekommen, und zwar aus diesem merkwürdigen Grunde, weil sie die Wirklichkeit dessen, worauf sie sich beziehen, (die Willensgesinnung) selbst hervorbringen, welches gar nicht die Sache theoretischer Begriffe ist, I. Kant, Kritik der praktischen Vernunft, Akademie Ausgabe, 5:66. Robert Pippin drew my attention to this passage in Hegel s Practical Philosophy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2008, pp. 106f. See also I. Kant, Grundlegung der Metaphysik der Sitten, Akademie Ausgabe, 4: Whether Fichte accepted in Berlin in the end a relativisation will not be examined here, as this plausible development is not relevant for understanding Hegel s positions. 4

5 ambiguities of his texts on this issue must be admitted (famously, at certain times his defence of an idealist point of view seems to have value only for those who claim it), but I consider that a triumphalist tone prevails in the 1794 Wissenschaftslehre and the new Introductions to the Doctrine in 1797 when he declares the victory of idealism on dogmatism, on every philosophy that presents reason and consciousness as products of nature and not as primordial sources of activity. In fact, as is well known, Fichte makes what he calls the self-positing (Selbstsetzung) of the self the principle of idealism in general, and not only of its practical part. The self sometimes also called intelligence or reason absolutely, unconditionally posits itself. It posits itself as the principle of all position, both with respect to itself and with respect to what it considers different from itself. Needless to say, it posits itself as an action and only as inaction when acting consists in not acting. But this does not mean, in Fichte s opinion, that it thus posits itself only when taking action, as if it were able at some point when it is not urgent to act, for instance to see oneself as an object, an effect, an inert or passive entity, rather than an agent. The argument based on which Fichte intends to subdue the dogmatic (without great expectations, it must be said, but with the conviction that no better one is at hand) exploits the fact that the dogmatic, just like the non-dogmatic, tries to form a judgment on causes and effects, on reasons and explanations, of our representation of the world and of the world itself: dogmatism as a whole is a judgement on this matter. In light of this, Fichte argues that the attempt to understand the absolute essence of the world as a blind mechanism of nature (in Hegel s words) cannot be but contradictory. For one thing, nature can certainly be considered to consist of blind mechanisms, but those who contemplate nature as thus constituted cannot consider themselves as a part of nature, since judging and becoming aware of could not be, by itself, the effect of a blind mechanism. Fichte is very explicit in this regard. 6 He understands that it is completely unacceptable that the content of the judgement be at odds with or deny the act of judging, the judgment as such. In this sense, Fichte assumes that the Doctrine contains from the outset a refutation of the mechanistic or naturalistic dogmatism. From the start, indeed, since the self from where all positing, all judgement and all conclusion are derived, the self whose self-positing he declares the principle of the system, cannot but be considered, as I said, primordially and essentially active. Reflections on this character of the self led Fichte to unconditionally affirm the 6 See Zweite Einleitung in die Wissenschaftslehre, für Leser, die schon ein philosophisches System haben, in: Fichtes Werke, herausgegeben von I. H. Fichte, Berlin, Walter de Gruyter, 1971, vol. 1, p

6 actuality of the representation of the fact that I think. The fact that I think is not merely something I think. It is assumed that my judgements effectively raise something to consciousness. So that we can say about them that a concept has objectivity and about ourselves, in general, that we are something necessary, a concept or, even better, the concept that gives itself its own objectivity. 3.The starting point of the chapter on Teleology Nevertheless, when Hegel discusses in his Logic the third Kantian antinomy, the conflict between the Fichtean principle of activity and the dogmatic principle of mechanical causation, he does not feel the need (if he ever felt it) of examining the realisability of moral duty or the unsurpassable character of a subjective principle of judging. In Hegel s view, the question is, first of all, how the general concept of end (Zweck) can be considered the truth of the concept of natural necessity. Although this could admittedly announce a revision of Kant and Fichte s arguments on the issues highlighted above (duty and selfconsciousness), it immediately becomes clear that Hegel worries on this point are rather about a slightly different Kantian topic, first addressed in Kant s critique of the teleological judgement : whether it can be said of something that exists, objectively, that it is an end in itself and by itself. Certainly, the truth of teleology and, indeed, the untruth of mechanism have already been settled before the chapter on teleology in the Wissenschaft der Logik starts. It is assumed that the previous chapters have shown, at the very least, that the mechanistic view of the world is inherently contradictory. Hegel describes the mechanical object by remarking that, in order to explain each of its determinations, those of another object are pointed out; but the latter turns out to be as indifferent as the former both with regard to its being somehow determined and to its active and determinative behaviour with respect to other objects (including the first). Hegel perceived an absurdity in all this: a way of understanding the explanation that, by always referring to something else, turns explanation into an empty word (12:135). The Logic suggests that the deterministic worldview incurs in the contradiction of representing the objects as mutually indifferent and, therefore, self-sufficient, and yet as identical to one another in their indifference to their own determinations. It is in that representation of objective relations, in that concept of the object, where in Hegel s opinion lies the truth (and the untruth) of causal relationships (see 12:137). This truth can be expressed by saying that it is a contingency for the object to be the cause of something else. Indeed, it seems contradictory that the 6

7 point of view which treats natural necessity as the only explanatory principle of what is ends up affirming universal contingency. By stating that the mechanistic, dogmatic vision is contradictory, it could nevertheless seem that Hegel is espousing the views of Fichte. But this is not so. Fichte considers that the contradiction of the mechanism occurs between the (mechanistic) form of judgement and the (mechanistic) content of judgement. In Hegel s opinion, by contrast, the concept of (general) mechanism is contradictory in itself. It should be assumed that this mode of argument that does not presuppose a subjective principle of judgment, a mode of argument exemplified by the chapters on mechanism, natural necessity and determinism (the main part of the section on objectivity ), is characteristic of the method of The Science of Logic. It remains to be examined in what sense, in the transition to the chapter on Die Teleologie, the contradiction of mechanism leads to the affirmation of teleology. In my opinion, this should be done by considering what concept of Zweck opens this chapter. In this concept, as I see it, it is immediately decided that the discussion of teleology in the Logic does not raise for Hegel the issue of a causal power related only contingently to an external existence. Hegel indicates the nature of the starting point of the chapter in a way that makes evident from the outset that his approach differs from that of other idealists: an end, he says, is not a cause, certainly not in the sense in which Kant speaks of the will as a cause whose faculty of action is determined through concepts. 7 Hegel is thinking here about ends that are needs, impulses and the like (see Enz. 1830: 204 Anm., 12:160) and not about mental representations of desirable states of things that might govern the action, the will of rational beings like us, or about the faculty of being thus governed. As an end, Hegel says, the concept is the unity that repels itself (die sich von sich selbst abstossende... Einheit) and is preserved through that repelling (ibid.). This is how the concept gives itself objectivity. An impulse is not an end that someone tries to actualise. The relationship between an impulse and the definite activity by which the impulse is preserved and revealed is immediate. One could say that to be hungry is to treat (in practice) certain things as edible: to seek them in order to eat them, to eat them when they are found. Hegel famously refers to this immediate behaviour that disrespects things (that shows no tenderness for them) in the first chapter of The Phenomenology of Spirit (as in the Logic, the issue there is the certainty of the unessentiality of the external object, ). 7 I. Kant, Critik der Urtheilskraft, B

8 4. The logic of the realisation of the Zweck He nevertheless accepts in the Logic that those ends are externally related to the means for their actualisation and therefore calls them subjective. Moreover, he warns that the concept of necessity or impulse inherently encapsulates, as immediately as the activity, the concept of an external objectivity, mechanical and chemical, confronting the end, in which the end should be actualised (see 12:161). Therefore, the chapter examines the logic of the actualisation of an external and subjective end within that objectivity. There he discovers, once again, a contradiction. An infinite process of actualisation is inherent to that externality, by the interposition and operation of a series of means (see 12:168), but by this work it can both be said that the end is actualised in fact and that the product of the actualisation is but a(nother) means (and the difference between both claims would not be an objective determination, as Hegel points out). At least insofar as the product must be a (mechanical and/or chemical) object, it can only actualise the end provisionally and precariously. The objects wear out, are consumed by that activity. In fact, the more they work toward the end, the more they are rendered useless and (in the long run) stop actualising it (see 12:169). Perhaps an example can illustrate this point. Driven by the need for shelter and protection, we use stone and wood to build a house. The house is certainly the goal of the building process. But when it is complete, we are left with nothing more than stones and timbers exerting mutual pressure to keep the house standing. We are only left with means and yet, with an actualised end. But Hegel believes that this is not the only conclusion to be drawn from the examination of that logic. It should also be noted that an internal end-relation (innere Zweckbeziehung) (in principle in the Kantian sense), an objective end (in Hegel s words), is the truth of the external end-relation, both in the sense that in the process just considered the exteriority and self-sufficiency of objects and means are cancelled and in the sense that the immediacy by which the end firstly relates to those objects and means is cancelled as well. Hegel considers the movement to be especially difficult (see 12:171). He attempts to retrace the objective return of the concept to itself, its true objectivation (die objective Rückkehr des Begriffs in sich, d. i. die wahrhafte Objectivierung desselben). This occurs in a (new) repelling of itself (Abstossen von sich) in which the identity of the concept with itself comes to be precisely what is determined as indifferent and external. That identity, turned over itself, is its own other, says Hegel. I interpret such a conclusion as follows. An end is truly objectified when the means for its actualisation are configured and arranged so that they obey but their own existence. In that case, one can say that they obey an end that is not 8

9 external anymore. And it is through the means themselves, that are external in themselves, that the identity of the concept comes into being. This leads Hegel from the concept of end to the concept of end-in-itself (Selbstzweck) as an actualised end. Kant, as is well known, calls into question the actuality of such objective (or, as he calls them, natural) ends because, in his view, we cannot conceive their possibility a priori. 8 This leads to what Hegel considers the lowering of the teleological principle to a maxim of the understanding. Following this maxim, according to Kant, we talk about nature as if it contained intentional ends, while aware that it is unacceptable to attribute such ends to nature. Although there is a major difference between man-made machines (devices which serve ends) and (natural, living) organisms (there is, at most, a distant analogy between the two 9 ), as the parts of the machine are previous to the machine while the members of an organism are generated by the organism itself, the idea that the concept of a whole determines the form and existence of its parts, that is fundamental in the representation of the organism, is considered by Kant under the model of the causation of reason which arranges and makes use of means. In this sense, we can say that he understands the organisms or living beings through the concepts of intention, finality (purpose) and instrument, which are seen as acquiring meaning for the first time in our practical experience as agents. Hegel opposes this approach. It could even be said that, by trying to prove that the concept of internal end-relation is the truth of the external end-relation, he reverses Kant s argument. First and foremost, he opposes Kant s conclusion, his resistance to consider the teleological principle as something more than an imperative of our understanding. For Hegel, the objective process of differentiating oneself and reproducing oneself from the living reveals the emergence of subjectivity, of the concept that exists for itself (or of the being for itself of the concept) and, in that emergence, the actualisation of the concept as such, as what highlights itself, becomes independent and produces for itself and on its own an exteriority (and thus an interiority). The (conceptually) relevant differences between living beings are determined by their own faculties and actions claws and teeth, swats and nips to distinguish themselves from other living beings (see 9:140f, 12:219; see also Enz. 1830, 351). To be sure, much has been said about the nature of Hegel s affirmation of true ends or ends in themselves. It is Hegel himself who paradoxically speaks about the existence of the concept as soul as being nicht seelenvoll (12:177). But, as I have already pointed out, in the conclusion of the analysis on the concept of teleology he tries to make the claim that the actualised end is nothing 8 I. Kant, Critik der Urtheilskraft, B I. Kant, Critik der Urtheilskraft, B

10 but a means compatible with the claim that this means is, after all, an actualised end. Hegel asserts that in living beings, the concept penetrates exteriority, the objectivity of the living is the means and the instrument of an end in complete conformity with itself (12:184). The paradox is generally expressed with respect to the ideal in the introduction of the final section of the Logic, on The idea. This is what Hegel refers to when he speaks about the most stubborn opposition (12:177) that the idea contains. Everything that has any particular content does and does not actualise, necessarily, its (own) idea. 5. Concluding remark Let me conclude. In Hegel s analysis of teleology as an actualisation of the concept, three theses stand out: (1) from the outset, ends are seen as no mere representations, and certainly not as representations that are contingently related to their own actualisation; (2) an objective process is considered as the actualisation of the concept; and (3) the actualisation for itself is not just any kind of effectiveness but only an objective process that turns over and reproduces itself, existing in any case as external and giving rise to the (self-)production of an exteriority The research for this paper was financially supported by the Spanish Government (Research Project FFI P). I must also thank my colleagues Sergio Sevilla, Manuel Jiménez Redondo, Berta M. Pérez and Andrés Alonso for valuable comments on a previous draft. Pier-Luc Dupont helped me to turn the original Spanish version into a readable English-language text and I am indebted to him for this. 10

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal

The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Arthur Kok, Tilburg The Boundaries of Hegel s Criticism of Kant s Concept of the Noumenal Kant conceives of experience as the synthesis of understanding and intuition. Hegel argues that because Kant is

More information

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals

Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Summary of Kant s Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Version 1.1 Richard Baron 2 October 2016 1 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Availability and licence............ 3 2 Definitions of key terms 4 3

More information

Kant and his Successors

Kant and his Successors Kant and his Successors G. J. Mattey Winter, 2011 / Philosophy 151 The Sorry State of Metaphysics Kant s Critique of Pure Reason (1781) was an attempt to put metaphysics on a scientific basis. Metaphysics

More information

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. by Immanuel Kant FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS SECOND SECTION by Immanuel Kant TRANSITION FROM POPULAR MORAL PHILOSOPHY TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS... This principle, that humanity and generally every

More information

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation

The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 35 The Groundwork, the Second Critique, Pure Practical Reason and Motivation Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper, I will critically examine Christine Korsgaard s claim

More information

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations

Freedom as Morality. UWM Digital Commons. University of Wisconsin Milwaukee. Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee. Theses and Dissertations University of Wisconsin Milwaukee UWM Digital Commons Theses and Dissertations May 2014 Freedom as Morality Hao Liang University of Wisconsin-Milwaukee Follow this and additional works at: http://dc.uwm.edu/etd

More information

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents

Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents Ibn Sina on Substances and Accidents ERWIN TEGTMEIER, MANNHEIM There was a vivid and influential dialogue of Western philosophy with Ibn Sina in the Middle Ages; but there can be also a fruitful dialogue

More information

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy

Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Res Cogitans Volume 5 Issue 1 Article 20 6-4-2014 Saving the Substratum: Interpreting Kant s First Analogy Kevin Harriman Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY

THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNKNOWN AND UNKNOWABILITY IN KANT S PHILOSOPHY Subhankari Pati Research Scholar Pondicherry University, Pondicherry The present aim of this paper is to highlights the shortcomings in Kant

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [University of Chicago Library] On: 24 May 2013, At: 08:10 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office:

More information

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of

In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of Glasgow s Conception of Kantian Humanity Richard Dean ABSTRACT: In Kant s Conception of Humanity, Joshua Glasgow defends a traditional reading of the humanity formulation of the Categorical Imperative.

More information

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins

Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Thought is Being or Thought and Being? Feuerbach and his Criticism of Hegel's Absolute Idealism by Martin Jenkins Although he was once an ardent follower of the Philosophy of GWF Hegel, Ludwig Feuerbach

More information

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg

In Search of the Ontological Argument. Richard Oxenberg 1 In Search of the Ontological Argument Richard Oxenberg Abstract We can attend to the logic of Anselm's ontological argument, and amuse ourselves for a few hours unraveling its convoluted word-play, or

More information

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction

From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction From Transcendental Logic to Transcendental Deduction Let me see if I can say a few things to re-cap our first discussion of the Transcendental Logic, and help you get a foothold for what follows. Kant

More information

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law

From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law From the Categorical Imperative to the Moral Law Marianne Vahl Master Thesis in Philosophy Supervisor Olav Gjelsvik Department of Philosophy, Classics, History of Arts and Ideas UNIVERSITY OF OSLO May

More information

MAIMON'S CRITICISM OF REINHOLD'S "SATZ DES BEWUSSTSEINS"

MAIMON'S CRITICISM OF REINHOLD'S SATZ DES BEWUSSTSEINS Rolf Peter Horstmann MAIMON'S CRITICISM OF REINHOLD'S "SATZ DES BEWUSSTSEINS" In a letter of January 1795 Schelling wrote Hegel: "Philosophy is not at an end yet. Kant has given the results, the premises

More information

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life

Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life Kant on Biology and the Experience of Life Angela Breitenbach Introduction Recent years have seen remarkable advances in the life sciences, including increasing technical capacities to reproduce, manipulate

More information

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit

Chapter 25. Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit Chapter 25 Hegel s Absolute Idealism and the Phenomenology of Spirit Key Words: Absolute idealism, contradictions, antinomies, Spirit, Absolute, absolute idealism, teleological causality, objective mind,

More information

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism

1/10. The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism 1/10 The Fourth Paralogism and the Refutation of Idealism The Fourth Paralogism is quite different from the three that preceded it because, although it is treated as a part of rational psychology, it main

More information

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism

The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism The Greatest Mistake: A Case for the Failure of Hegel s Idealism What is a great mistake? Nietzsche once said that a great error is worth more than a multitude of trivial truths. A truly great mistake

More information

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical

[Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical [Forthcoming in The International Encyclopedia of Ethics, ed. Hugh LaFollette. (Oxford: Blackwell), 2012] Imperatives, Categorical and Hypothetical Samuel J. Kerstein Ethicists distinguish between categorical

More information

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory

Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory Western University Scholarship@Western 2015 Undergraduate Awards The Undergraduate Awards 2015 Two Kinds of Ends in Themselves in Kant s Moral Theory David Hakim Western University, davidhakim266@gmail.com

More information

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES

A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES A HOLISTIC VIEW ON KNOWLEDGE AND VALUES CHANHYU LEE Emory University It seems somewhat obscure that there is a concrete connection between epistemology and ethics; a study of knowledge and a study of moral

More information

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism

Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism Chapter 5: Freedom and Determinism At each time t the world is perfectly determinate in all detail. - Let us grant this for the sake of argument. We might want to re-visit this perfectly reasonable assumption

More information

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte

Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Maria Pia Mater Thomistic Week 2018 Resolutio of Idealism into Atheism in Fichte Introduction Cornelio Fabro s God in Exile, traces the progression of modern atheism from its roots in the cogito of Rene

More information

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals Kant s Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals G. J. Mattey Spring, 2017/ Philosophy 1 The Division of Philosophical Labor Kant generally endorses the ancient Greek division of philosophy into

More information

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5

Philosophy in Review XXXIII (2013), no. 5 Robert Stern Understanding Moral Obligation. Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press 2012. 277 pages $90.00 (cloth ISBN 978 1 107 01207 3) In his thoroughly researched and tightly

More information

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney

Moral Obligation. by Charles G. Finney Moral Obligation by Charles G. Finney The idea of obligation, or of oughtness, is an idea of the pure reason. It is a simple, rational conception, and, strictly speaking, does not admit of a definition,

More information

Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics'

Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics' Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Faculty Publications Department of Philosophy 2008 Apriority from the 'Grundlage' to the 'System of Ethics' Sebastian Rand Georgia

More information

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch

Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Some Notes Toward a Genealogy of Existential Philosophy Robert Burch Descartes - ostensive task: to secure by ungainsayable rational means the orthodox doctrines of faith regarding the existence of God

More information

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect..

This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. This is a repository copy of Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive intellect.. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/81838/

More information

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism

Thursday, November 30, 17. Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being )

On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title being ) On happiness in Locke s decision-ma Title (Proceedings of the CAPE Internatio I: The CAPE International Conferenc being ) Author(s) Sasaki, Taku Citation CAPE Studies in Applied Philosophy 2: 141-151 Issue

More information

Hegel on Fichte s Conception of Practical Self-Consciousness 1 A Fundamental Criticism of the Sittenlehre in the Differenz-Schrift (1801) 2

Hegel on Fichte s Conception of Practical Self-Consciousness 1 A Fundamental Criticism of the Sittenlehre in the Differenz-Schrift (1801) 2 The 3rd BESETO Conference of Philosophy Session 15 Hegel on Fichte s Conception of Practical Self-Consciousness 1 A Fundamental Criticism of the Sittenlehre in the Differenz-Schrift (1801) 2 LIU Zhe Peking

More information

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature

2 FREE CHOICE The heretical thesis of Hobbes is the orthodox position today. So much is this the case that most of the contemporary literature Introduction The philosophical controversy about free will and determinism is perennial. Like many perennial controversies, this one involves a tangle of distinct but closely related issues. Thus, the

More information

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford.

Projection in Hume. P J E Kail. St. Peter s College, Oxford. Projection in Hume P J E Kail St. Peter s College, Oxford Peter.kail@spc.ox.ac.uk A while ago now (2007) I published my Projection and Realism in Hume s Philosophy (Oxford University Press henceforth abbreviated

More information

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE

DISCUSSION PRACTICAL POLITICS AND PHILOSOPHICAL INQUIRY: A NOTE Practical Politics and Philosophical Inquiry: A Note Author(s): Dale Hall and Tariq Modood Reviewed work(s): Source: The Philosophical Quarterly, Vol. 29, No. 117 (Oct., 1979), pp. 340-344 Published by:

More information

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism

Tuesday, November 11, Hegel s Idealism Hegel s Idealism G. W. F. Hegel Hegel Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770-1831) was perhaps the last great philosophical system builder. His distinctively dynamic form of idealism set the stage for other

More information

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS

INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS INTENTIONALITY, NORMATIVITY AND COMMUNALITY IN KANT S REALM OF ENDS Stijn Van Impe & Bart Vandenabeele Ghent University 1. Introduction In the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals Kant claims that there

More information

1/9. The Second Analogy (1)

1/9. The Second Analogy (1) 1/9 The Second Analogy (1) This week we are turning to one of the most famous, if also longest, arguments in the Critique. This argument is both sufficiently and the interpretation of it sufficiently disputed

More information

Categorical Imperative by. Kant

Categorical Imperative by. Kant Categorical Imperative by Dr. Desh Raj Sirswal Assistant Professor (Philosophy), P.G.Govt. College for Girls, Sector-11, Chandigarh http://drsirswal.webs.com Kant Immanuel Kant Immanuel Kant (1724 1804)

More information

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M.

Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS. by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Spinoza, Ethics 1 of 85 THE ETHICS by Benedict de Spinoza (Ethica Ordine Geometrico Demonstrata) Translated from the Latin by R. H. M. Elwes PART I: CONCERNING GOD DEFINITIONS (1) By that which is self-caused

More information

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments

Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments Lecture 4: Transcendental idealism and transcendental arguments Stroud s worry: - Transcendental arguments can t establish a necessary link between thought or experience and how the world is without a

More information

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial.

Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial. TitleKant's Concept of Happiness: Within Author(s) Hirose, Yuzo Happiness and Personal Growth: Dial Citation Philosophy, Psychology, and Compara 43-49 Issue Date 2010-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143022

More information

Critique of Cosmological Argument

Critique of Cosmological Argument David Hume: Critique of Cosmological Argument Critique of Cosmological Argument DAVID HUME (1711-1776) David Hume is one of the most important philosophers in the history of philosophy. Born in Edinburgh,

More information

XI SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS, NEGATION, AND DISAGREEMENT

XI SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS, NEGATION, AND DISAGREEMENT Meeting of the Aristotelian Society held at Senate House, University of London, on 24 April 2017 at 5:30 p.m. XI SELF-CONSCIOUSNESS, NEGATION, AND DISAGREEMENT SEBASTIAN RÖDL It seems obvious that judgement

More information

Between The Bounds of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant s Epistemic Limits and Hegel s Ambitions

Between The Bounds of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant s Epistemic Limits and Hegel s Ambitions Claremont Colleges Scholarship @ Claremont CMC Faculty Publications and Research CMC Faculty Scholarship 1-1-2007 Between The Bounds of Experience and Divine Intuition: Kant s Epistemic Limits and Hegel

More information

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit Boston University OpenBU Theses & Dissertations http://open.bu.edu Boston University Theses & Dissertations 2014 Freedom and servitude: the master and slave dialectic in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit

More information

Real predicates and existential judgements

Real predicates and existential judgements Real predicates and existential judgements Ralf M. Bader Merton College, University of Oxford 1 Real predicates One of the central commitments of Kant s (pre-critical as well as Critical) modal theory

More information

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God

7/31/2017. Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God Radical Evil Kant and Our Ineradicable Desire to be God 1 Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) Kant indeed marks the end of the Enlightenment: he brought its most fundamental assumptions concerning the powers of

More information

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion

The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World. In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages, Kripke expands upon a conclusion 24.251: Philosophy of Language Paper 2: S.A. Kripke, On Rules and Private Language 21 December 2011 The Kripkenstein Paradox and the Private World In his paper, Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Languages,

More information

Kant s Critical Thoughts on Freedom from a Contemporary Perspective -

Kant s Critical Thoughts on Freedom from a Contemporary Perspective - Kant s Critical Thoughts on Freedom from a Contemporary Perspective - To what extent are these thoughts of practical philosophical significance for us? Gerhard Bos Student Number: 0354422 Master s Thesis

More information

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement

What one needs to know to prepare for'spinoza's method is to be found in the treatise, On the Improvement SPINOZA'S METHOD Donald Mangum The primary aim of this paper will be to provide the reader of Spinoza with a certain approach to the Ethics. The approach is designed to prevent what I believe to be certain

More information

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement:

Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Descartes and Schopenhauer on Voluntary Movement: Why My Arm Is Lifted When I Will Lift It? Katsunori MATSUDA (Received on October 2, 2014) The purpose of this paper In the ordinary literature on modern

More information

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent?

Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent? Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 5-3-2017 Is Kant's Account of Free Will Coherent? Paul Dumond Follow this and additional works

More information

The Deistic God of the First Critique and Spinoza s God

The Deistic God of the First Critique and Spinoza s God 金沢星稜大学論集第 48 巻第 1 号平成 26 年 8 月 21 The Deistic God of the First Critique and Spinoza s God Shohei Edamura Introduction In this paper I shall examine Kant s concept of God as ens entium, and see whether

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 21 Lecture - 21 Kant Forms of sensibility Categories

More information

In what sense does consciousness provide its own criterion?

In what sense does consciousness provide its own criterion? In what sense does consciousness provide its own criterion? At the beginning of his Science of Logic, Hegel poses the question: With what must science begin? It is this question that Hegel takes to be

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 22 Lecture - 22 Kant The idea of Reason Soul, God

More information

The Relation of Right and Morality in Fichte s Jena Period

The Relation of Right and Morality in Fichte s Jena Period The Relation of Right and Morality in Fichte s Jena Period Master thesis Philosophy Student Willam van Weelden 3223337 Supervisor Ernst-Otto Onnasch Second supervisor Herman Hendriks 1 of 26 Introduction

More information

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics

Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics Davis 1 Why There s Nothing You Can Say to Change My Mind: The Principle of Non-Contradiction in Aristotle s Metaphysics William Davis Red River Undergraduate Philosophy Conference North Dakota State University

More information

The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals

The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals The Idealism of Life: Hegel and Kant on the Ontology of Living Individuals by Franklin Charles Owen Cooper-Simpson A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of PhD Graduate

More information

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY

KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS CHICAGO DR. PAUL CARUS THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING COMPANY KANT'S PROLEGOMENA TO ANY FUTURE METAPHYSICS EDITED IN ENGLISH DR. PAUL CARUS WITH AN ESSAY ON KANT'S PHILOSOPHY, AND OTHER SUPPLEMENTARY MATERIAL FOR THE STUDY OF KANT CHICAGO THE OPEN COURT PUBLISHING

More information

Dualism: What s at stake?

Dualism: What s at stake? Dualism: What s at stake? Dualists posit that reality is comprised of two fundamental, irreducible types of stuff : Material and non-material Material Stuff: Includes all the familiar elements of the physical

More information

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger

Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Christian Lotz, Commentary, SPEP 2009 Formal Indication and the Problem of Radical Philosophy in Heidegger Introduction I would like to begin by thanking Leslie MacAvoy for her attempt to revitalize the

More information

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism

Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism Kant s Freedom and Transcendental Idealism Simon Marcus June 2009 Kant s theory of freedom depends strongly on his account of causation, and must for its cogency make sense of the nomological sufficiency

More information

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS

AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS Philosophical Books Vol. 49 No. 2 April 2008 pp. 125 137 AUTONOMY, TAKING ONE S CHOICES TO BE GOOD, AND PRACTICAL LAW: REPLIES TO CRITICS andrews reath The University of California, Riverside I Several

More information

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming

Chapter 24. Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming Chapter 24 Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel: The Concepts of Being, Non-being and Becoming Key Words: Romanticism, Geist, Spirit, absolute, immediacy, teleological causality, noumena, dialectical method,

More information

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY

THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION AND ARISTOTELIAN THEOLOGY TODAY Science and the Future of Mankind Pontifical Academy of Sciences, Scripta Varia 99, Vatican City 2001 www.pas.va/content/dam/accademia/pdf/sv99/sv99-berti.pdf THE RELATIONSHIP BETWEEN SCIENCE, RELIGION

More information

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming

Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1. By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics 1 By Tom Cumming Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics represents Martin Heidegger's first attempt at an interpretation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason (1781). This

More information

Sidgwick on Practical Reason

Sidgwick on Practical Reason Sidgwick on Practical Reason ONORA O NEILL 1. How many methods? IN THE METHODS OF ETHICS Henry Sidgwick distinguishes three methods of ethics but (he claims) only two conceptions of practical reason. This

More information

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood

An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori. Ralph Wedgwood An Inferentialist Conception of the A Priori Ralph Wedgwood When philosophers explain the distinction between the a priori and the a posteriori, they usually characterize the a priori negatively, as involving

More information

1/12. The A Paralogisms

1/12. The A Paralogisms 1/12 The A Paralogisms The character of the Paralogisms is described early in the chapter. Kant describes them as being syllogisms which contain no empirical premises and states that in them we conclude

More information

Rezensionen / Book reviews

Rezensionen / Book reviews Research on Steiner Education Volume 4 Number 2 pp. 146-150 December 2013 Hosted at www.rosejourn.com Rezensionen / Book reviews Bo Dahlin Thomas Nagel (2012). Mind and cosmos. Why the materialist Neo-Darwinian

More information

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views

Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views Logic and the Absolute: Platonic and Christian Views by Philip Sherrard Studies in Comparative Religion, Vol. 7, No. 2. (Spring 1973) World Wisdom, Inc. www.studiesincomparativereligion.com ONE of the

More information

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed

Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza. Ryan Steed Sufficient Reason and Infinite Regress: Causal Consistency in Descartes and Spinoza Ryan Steed PHIL 2112 Professor Rebecca Car October 15, 2018 Steed 2 While both Baruch Spinoza and René Descartes espouse

More information

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116.

P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt Pp. 116. P. Weingartner, God s existence. Can it be proven? A logical commentary on the five ways of Thomas Aquinas, Ontos, Frankfurt 2010. Pp. 116. Thinking of the problem of God s existence, most formal logicians

More information

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings

Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 34 (2003) 5 27 www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsa Forces and causes in Kant s early pre-critical writings Eric Watkins Department of Philosophy, University of California at San Diego,

More information

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141

Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Phil 114, Wednesday, April 11, 2012 Hegel, The Philosophy of Right 1 7, 10 12, 14 16, 22 23, 27 33, 135, 141 Dialectic: For Hegel, dialectic is a process governed by a principle of development, i.e., Reason

More information

CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY FOUNDATIONS OF J. G. FICHTE S 1794 WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE: A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF HIS STARTING POINT

CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY FOUNDATIONS OF J. G. FICHTE S 1794 WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE: A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF HIS STARTING POINT CATHOLIC UNIVERSITY OF AMERICA SCHOOL OF PHILOSOPHY FOUNDATIONS OF J. G. FICHTE S 1794 WISSENSCHAFTSLEHRE: A CRITICAL EXPOSITION OF HIS STARTING POINT A PAPER PRESENTED IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS

More information

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality

Chapter Six. Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Chapter Six Aristotle s Theory of Causation and the Ideas of Potentiality and Actuality Key Words: Form and matter, potentiality and actuality, teleological, change, evolution. Formal cause, material cause,

More information

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View

Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Chapter 98 Moral Argumentation from a Rhetorical Point of View Lars Leeten Universität Hildesheim Practical thinking is a tricky business. Its aim will never be fulfilled unless influence on practical

More information

Michael Thompson: Life and Action Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought, Cambridge/MA

Michael Thompson: Life and Action Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought, Cambridge/MA Michael Thompson: Life and Action Elementary Structures of Practice and Practical Thought, Cambridge/MA. 2008. Wiederholung der letzten Sitzung Hans Jonas, Organismus und Freiheit Wie die Substanz für

More information

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite*

THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE. by Jean Hyppolite* 75 76 THE FICHTEAN IDEA OF THE SCIENCE OF KNOWLEDGE AND THE HUSSERLIAN PROJECT by Jean Hyppolite* Translated from the French by Tom Nemeth Introduction to Hyppolite. The following article by Hyppolite

More information

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies

Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies in Nihil Sine Ratione: Mensch, Natur und Technik im Wirken von G. W. Leibniz ed. H. Poser (2001), 720-27. Paul Lodge (New Orleans) Primitive and Derivative Forces in Leibnizian Bodies Page 720 I It is

More information

5 A Modal Version of the

5 A Modal Version of the 5 A Modal Version of the Ontological Argument E. J. L O W E Moreland, J. P.; Sweis, Khaldoun A.; Meister, Chad V., Jul 01, 2013, Debating Christian Theism The original version of the ontological argument

More information

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism:

Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism: Rationalist-Irrationalist Dialectic in Buddhism: The Failure of Buddhist Epistemology By W. J. Whitman The problem of the one and the many is the core issue at the heart of all real philosophical and theological

More information

KANT ON THE UNITY OF THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON.

KANT ON THE UNITY OF THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON. 1 of 7 11/01/08 13 KANT ON THE UNITY OF THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL REASON. by PAULINE KLEINGELD Kant famously asserts that reason is one and the same, whether it is applied theoretically, to the realm of

More information

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals

Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Groundwork for the Metaphysic of Morals Immanuel Kant Copyright Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small dots enclose material that has been added, but

More information

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism

Tuesday, September 2, Idealism Idealism Enlightenment Puzzle How do these fit into a scientific picture of the world? Norms Necessity Universality Mind Idealism The dominant 19th-century response: often today called anti-realism Everything

More information

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God

Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God Page 1 Baha i Proofs for the Existence of God Ian Kluge to show that belief in God can be rational and logically coherent and is not necessarily a product of uncritical religious dogmatism or ignorance.

More information

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.]

IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.] IMMANUEL KANT Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals [Edited and reduced by J. Bulger, Ph.D.] PREFACE 1. Kant defines rational knowledge as being composed of two parts, the Material and Formal. 2. Formal

More information

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology

Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology Journal of Social Ontology 2015; 1(2): 327 331 Book Symposium Open Access Dave Elder-Vass Of Babies and Bathwater. A Review of Tuukka Kaidesoja Naturalizing Critical Realist Social Ontology DOI 10.1515/jso-2014-0029

More information

What God Could Have Made

What God Could Have Made 1 What God Could Have Made By Heimir Geirsson and Michael Losonsky I. Introduction Atheists have argued that if there is a God who is omnipotent, omniscient and omnibenevolent, then God would have made

More information

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological

Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological Aporia vol. 18 no. 2 2008 The Ontological Parody: A Reply to Joshua Ernst s Charles Hartshorne and the Ontological Argument Charles Hartshorne argues that Kant s criticisms of Anselm s ontological argument

More information

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense

The Cosmological Argument: A Defense Page 1/7 RICHARD TAYLOR [1] Suppose you were strolling in the woods and, in addition to the sticks, stones, and other accustomed litter of the forest floor, you one day came upon some quite unaccustomed

More information

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON

GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON THE MONADOLOGY GOD AND THE PRINCIPLE OF SUFFICIENT REASON I. The Two Great Laws (#31-37): true and possibly false. A. The Law of Non-Contradiction: ~(p & ~p) No statement is both true and false. 1. The

More information

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God?

Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God? Is Innate Foreknowledge Possible to a Temporal God? by Kel Good A very interesting attempt to avoid the conclusion that God's foreknowledge is inconsistent with creaturely freedom is an essay entitled

More information

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant

Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Philosophy of Mathematics Kant Owen Griffiths oeg21@cam.ac.uk St John s College, Cambridge 20/10/15 Immanuel Kant Born in 1724 in Königsberg, Prussia. Enrolled at the University of Königsberg in 1740 and

More information